22.07.2013 Views

Freedom, Society, and State - Ludwig von Mises Institute

Freedom, Society, and State - Ludwig von Mises Institute

Freedom, Society, and State - Ludwig von Mises Institute

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

FREEDOM,<br />

SOCIETY AND<br />

THESTATE<br />

An Investigation into the<br />

Possibility of <strong>Society</strong><br />

without Government<br />

DavidOsterfeld<br />

COBDEN PRESS<br />

1800 Market Street<br />

San Francisco, CA 94102


Copyright 1986 by David Osterfeld<br />

ISBN 0-930 439-08-2


To Emmy<br />

iii


2. The Defense of Private Property:<br />

Natural Rights Versus Utilitarianism 56<br />

3. The Implications of Universal Private<br />

Property 62<br />

III. The <strong>State</strong> as a Caste Institution<br />

1. The·Origin of the <strong>State</strong><br />

2. The Persistence of the <strong>State</strong><br />

3. The Gr'owth of the <strong>State</strong><br />

a. Democracy<br />

b. War<br />

c. Economic Intervention<br />

4. The Total <strong>State</strong><br />

5. Who Rules the <strong>State</strong>?<br />

6. Comments <strong>and</strong> Evaluation<br />

IV. The <strong>State</strong>, Imperialism, <strong>and</strong> War<br />

73<br />

73<br />

79<br />

82<br />

83<br />

86<br />

87<br />

88<br />

93<br />

95<br />

117<br />

1. Three Theories of Imperialism 119<br />

a. Autarky 119<br />

b. Planned Scarcity 121<br />

c. Inflation 125<br />

d. Imperialism <strong>and</strong> Popular Support 127<br />

2. Evaluations 131<br />

a. Is the United <strong>State</strong>s Imperialistic? 131<br />

b. Analysis of the Theories of<br />

Imperialism 135<br />

3. Conclusion 140<br />

Part Two: The Individualist Anarchist<br />

Paradigm<br />

VI<br />

149


V. Some Justification for the <strong>State</strong><br />

1. The Argument from the Common Good<br />

a. The Totalist Common Good<br />

b. The Personalist Common Good<br />

2. The Argument from Necessity<br />

3. The Argument from Convenience<br />

4. The Argument from Natural Rights<br />

5. The Argument from Utility<br />

6. The Argument from Liberation<br />

7. The Argument from Economic Justice<br />

8. Conclusion<br />

VI. Philosophical Anarchism<br />

151<br />

151<br />

151<br />

155<br />

157<br />

158<br />

159<br />

160<br />

165<br />

168<br />

170<br />

177<br />

1. Josiah Warren <strong>and</strong> the Outlines for<br />

Individual Sovereignty 180<br />

2. William B. Greene <strong>and</strong> Currency <strong>and</strong><br />

Banking Reform 189<br />

3. Joshua K.<br />

of L<strong>and</strong><br />

Ingalls <strong>and</strong> the Ownership<br />

195<br />

4. Benjamin Tucker, Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner <strong>and</strong><br />

the Provision of Police <strong>and</strong> Court<br />

Services 198<br />

5. Tucker <strong>and</strong> His Journal, "Libertyff:<br />

Philosophical Anarchism Matured 208<br />

6. Conclusions: The Decline of<br />

Philosophical Anarchism 211<br />

VII. The Politico-Economic Perspective of<br />

Individualist Anarchism<br />

V) )<br />

221


1. Social Coordination<br />

a. Priorities<br />

b. Efficiency<br />

c • Dis t r ibu t ion<br />

d. <strong>State</strong>, Economy, <strong>and</strong> Conscious<br />

Coordination<br />

221<br />

223<br />

224<br />

226<br />

226<br />

2. Laissez .Faire, Power <strong>and</strong> <strong>Freedom</strong> 230<br />

a. Power Defined 230<br />

b. Ramifications of the Rothbardian<br />

Influence-Attempt Taxonomy 236<br />

c. <strong>Freedom</strong> Defined 239<br />

3•. The PI ight of the Poor<br />

a. Government <strong>and</strong> the Poor<br />

b. The Culture of Poverty<br />

c. Poverty Statistics<br />

d. Poverty Programs<br />

e. The Market <strong>and</strong> the Poor<br />

f. Care for the Truly Poor<br />

4. Monopolies <strong>and</strong> the Free Market<br />

5. Government <strong>and</strong> Utility<br />

6. The Business Cycle <strong>and</strong> Depression<br />

7. Government <strong>and</strong> Taxation<br />

8. Democracy <strong>and</strong> the Market<br />

VIII. The Areas of Anarehist-Minarchist<br />

Agreement<br />

1. Roads<br />

a. Cost<br />

b. Eminent Domain<br />

. c. Inconvenience<br />

d. Price Gouging<br />

e. Safety<br />

2. Education<br />

3. Occupational Licensing<br />

vii i<br />

241<br />

241<br />

242<br />

243<br />

244<br />

247<br />

250<br />

250<br />

252<br />

253<br />

257<br />

260<br />

273<br />

273<br />

274<br />

275<br />

278<br />

280<br />

281<br />

282<br />

289


FORWARD<br />

by<br />

William O. Reichert<br />

Professor of Political Science<br />

Bowling .Green <strong>State</strong> University<br />

When Thomas Hobbes chose to title his theory of<br />

the modern state, The Leviathan, he could not possibly<br />

have known just how prophetic that caption was to<br />

prove to be in our day. Hobbes, of course, did not<br />

have in mind the Old Testament version of the word<br />

Leviathan, viz., a sea monster portending evil. In<br />

Hob b e s' min d the t e r m Lev i a t han s ym b0 1 i zed an 0 c ean ­<br />

going vessel Which, when attached to his social contract<br />

theory, was meant to convey the idea of a mighty<br />

ship of state capable of withst<strong>and</strong>ing the most ferae<br />

i 0 us g a I e san d tern pes t u 0 us sea s t hat h uma n na t ur e<br />

could invent. Today the symbolization of the state as<br />

a ship more logically brings to mind the ill-fated<br />

TIt ani c as its un k tot he bo t tom 0 f t he At lantic wi t h<br />

its cargo of humanity caged within its iron hull.<br />

Clearly, the modern democratic theory of the state is<br />

inc r i sis, for not a n I y ha veman y peopIe losteon f i ­<br />

dence in the state's abi I i ty to keep order within<br />

society but there is a widespread, ominous feeling that<br />

we are being sucked into a whirlpool that is heading us<br />

all toward a political version of Davey Jones' locker.<br />

David Osterfeld's <strong>Freedom</strong>, <strong>Society</strong>, <strong>and</strong> the <strong>State</strong> is<br />

addressed to the quest ion of how we might save ourselves<br />

from this unsavory fate.<br />

In ·the pages that follow, Osterfeld, drawing<br />

heavily upon the tradition of individualist thought as<br />

out I ined by Benjamin R. Tucker <strong>and</strong> other American libertarians<br />

of an earlier era, presents a synthesis of<br />

.anarchism <strong>and</strong> capitalism, a mission that is apt to be<br />

considered by many as futile as Hobbes' attempts to<br />

S quaret he c 1 r c 1 e • Soc i a lis t sin pa r ticu 1a r will be<br />

wary of thIS synthesis, for the free mark t economics<br />

that Osterfeld employs in his argument s generally<br />

thought of as the stock-in-trade of a power ul elite of<br />

we a I t h t hat use s the s tat e t 0 rna i n t a init s posit ion 0 f<br />

special economic privilege <strong>and</strong> political domination.<br />

But the uneasiness socialists experience at the mention<br />

xi


off r e e rna rk e t . e con om i c t heor y is based upon an outmoded<br />

conception of the nature <strong>and</strong> function of the<br />

state as it relates to the general welfare as well as a<br />

serious misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing of what anarchism is all<br />

about. Addressing himself directly to these misperceptions,<br />

David Osterfeld throws a great deal of light<br />

upon the topic of human freedom in comtemporary times.<br />

One of the widely held mi s per c e p t i onsat t a c ked by<br />

Osterfeld is the mistaken notion that all anarchists<br />

are totally opposed to the institution of private property.<br />

The basis of that notion, most probably, is<br />

Proudhon's notorious assertion that "property is<br />

theft." But when Proudhon condemned private property,<br />

hewa s not t h ink i n g 0 f goo d s prod uc e d by the wo r ke r<br />

through his own labor which he had every moral right to<br />

use for his own sustenance, but only those large accumulat<br />

ions of unearned income wrestled from the worker<br />

<strong>and</strong> pro t e c ted i nth e han d s 0 f cap ita 1 i s t s by laws<br />

est a b 1 ish e d by the s tat e • L ike Adam Sm i t h, from wh om<br />

mu c h 0 f his e nth u s i a s m for I a iss e z fa ire the 0 r y wa s<br />

der ived, Proudhon had no misgivings whatever concerning<br />

capital, if by capital is meant that necessary property<br />

the i n d i v i d u a I· ereate s by his own ef for t s wi t hi n an<br />

economic system characterized by unqualifIed freedom of<br />

choice <strong>and</strong> action. What anarchists like Proudhon cond<br />

em n i s pro per t y righ t s rna i n t a i ned inthe i n t eres t 0 f<br />

certain privileged individuals or social classes by<br />

force of state laws artificially imposed without regard<br />

as to who actually produced the property in question.<br />

With respect to political theory, Osterfeld's<br />

position is determined in large measure by the antis<br />

tat ism 0 f F ran z 0 p pen h e i mer <strong>and</strong> 0 ther I i ber tar ian<br />

thinkers who see modern democratic political ideology<br />

as the principal source of the confusion that characterizes<br />

the quest for social justice in contemporary<br />

soc i e t y • A Ion g with Ma r x <strong>and</strong> 0 t he r soc i a lis t s, i nd i ­<br />

vidualist anarchist theory recognizes the enormous<br />

contribution made by capital during the early indust<br />

riaIre v 0 I uti 0 n tothera i sing 0 f huma n 1 i v i ng s t<strong>and</strong>ar<br />

dsan d the wid e s preadd i s t ributi 0 n 0 f the com for t s<br />

of modern 1 i fe. Contemporary individual ist anarchist<br />

the 0 r i s t s a Iso a c know1edgethe ce n t r a I r 0 lethat c I ass<br />

confl iet <strong>and</strong> state power have played in bringing about<br />

the inequitable distribution of wealth that is evident<br />

i n mod ern soc iaIr e I a t ions • Un 1 ike bo t h the L i be r a I<br />

<strong>and</strong> the Mar XIS t, h owe ver, the i nd i v i d uali s tanarchis t<br />

does not look to state power as the savior of those who<br />

are domInated <strong>and</strong> exploited by the irresponsible monop-<br />

xii


o lie s 0 f we a I t h t hat h a v e com e abo ut, for follow ing<br />

Oppenheimer's viewpoint, it is the state that is the<br />

principal cause of the exploitation <strong>and</strong> monopolization<br />

of the means of production. That is so, according to<br />

individual ist anarchist theory, because it would be<br />

virtually impossible for the super-rich to have<br />

achieved the enormously inequitable positions of<br />

economic privilege <strong>and</strong> dorninati.on they presently hold<br />

wit h 0 u t the ass i s tan e e 0 fIegal rna chi ne ryer e c ted by<br />

the modern state. A way out of this imbroglio can be<br />

found only bya d 0 P ting a thoroughly r a diea I solution,<br />

the rejection of state power as the central force in<br />

human relations.<br />

In the place of the "political means" utilized by<br />

the s tat e tor e g u I ate the e con om i c <strong>and</strong> s 0 ci a I a f fa irs<br />

of people, Osterfeld <strong>and</strong> other individualist anarchists<br />

opt for a soc i e t y regu Iated by f r e e rna r k e t for cesthat<br />

ope rat e f r e e 0 f the art i fie i a I rna nipu I a t ion imp 0 sed<br />

upon people by the state's legal apparatus. In calling<br />

for a social order structured within the framework of<br />

laissez faire principles, liberals, especially, will<br />

accuse free market anarchists of turning the lambs over<br />

to the wolves, for one of the essential beliefs held by<br />

the liberal thinkers is that government is absolutely<br />

n e c e s s a r y i f the robber bar on s of cor porat e cap italism<br />

are to be held in check. How could there be social<br />

order, the liberal dem<strong>and</strong>s, if the power of the state<br />

dId not exist to effect reform <strong>and</strong> attempt to establish<br />

social justice? Osterfeld's answer to this is that<br />

g 0 v ernmen tin t e r ven t ion i n e con om i c a f fa irs m0 reof ten<br />

than not takes place for the specific purpose of helpi<br />

n g the supe r - r i e h t 0 rna i n t a i nor ext end the i r posit ion<br />

of supremacy rather than aid the disadvantaged; one<br />

need merely review the history of urban renewal projects<br />

in this country to underst<strong>and</strong> Osterfeld's reasoning<br />

on this point. And even when the motives of<br />

reformers are pure, the help that is extended to the<br />

poor <strong>and</strong> under-privileged inevitably leads to an<br />

increase in the bureaucratic regUlations they already<br />

suffer so that human freedom once again is victimized.<br />

The argument out I ined in favor of indIvidualist<br />

a n archis m by Os t er f e Idin t his book ish i gh I Y comp I ex ,<br />

drawing upon the wisdom of a wide range of social,<br />

economic, <strong>and</strong> political theorists. Of particular merit<br />

is the convincIng argument he makes in favor of a legal<br />

order that operates without the assistance of the<br />

professional legal monopoly that has come to maturity<br />

in America in recent years, a monopoly that depends<br />

xii i


almost exclusively upon the expertise of juridical<br />

specialists while ignoring the, real needs <strong>and</strong> social<br />

instincts of the very people it is supposed to help.<br />

Here Osterfeld dares to refer to the ideas <strong>and</strong><br />

theoretical insights of a number of unconventional but<br />

extremely provocative thinkers, social theorists like<br />

Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spoo'ner, Friedrich A. Hayek, Murray N.<br />

Rothbard, Gabriel Kolko, <strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>, Robert<br />

Nisbet, Walter Grinder, <strong>and</strong> R<strong>and</strong>olph Bourne. Convinced<br />

t ha t t her e· is 1itt Ie hope for human freedom to be found<br />

in the the 0 r i e s 0 f e i the r Ma r x 0 r Keynes, Os t er f e I d<br />

leads his readers in a quest for a more intelligent<br />

sol ut ion to the prodigious problems imposed upon us by<br />

modernity. This book most certainly gives the reader a<br />

percept ive guide to an underst<strong>and</strong>ing of contemporary<br />

libertarian thought <strong>and</strong> the logic of individualist<br />

anarchism as a means to regain our freedom.<br />

xiv


contrary, it would not be too strong to describe classIcal<br />

liberalism's attitude toward anarchism as one of<br />

both contempt as well as fear. It was contemptuous because<br />

as one classical liberal philosopher wrote, anarchism<br />

"would be practicable only in a world of angels"<br />

<strong>and</strong> the "liberal underst<strong>and</strong>s quite clearly" that "one<br />

must be in a position to compel the person who will not<br />

respect lives, health, personal feelings, or private<br />

property of others to acquiesce in the .rules of life in<br />

soc i e t y • " ( 2 ) And c I ass i cal liberalism had fear edana rchism<br />

because, while encompassing a broad spectrum of<br />

thought ranging from the rampant individualism of Max<br />

St i rner to the communism of Peter Kropotkin, the dominan<br />

t s t r a i n 0 fan archism 0 s tens i bl Y p I aced itsquareI y<br />

within the socialist camp. Daniel Guerin put the matter<br />

succinctly. Anarchism, he says, "is really a synonym<br />

for social ism."(3) And, while acknowledging "Stirner's<br />

complete rejection of all polictical, moral, <strong>and</strong> tradit<br />

ion a 1 ti e s of t he i nd i v i d ua I , " Max Ad I e r goes· s 0 fa r a s<br />

to argue that Stirner cannot even be considered an anarchist<br />

since anarchism is only "a definite political<br />

trend within the socialist labor movement," <strong>and</strong> Stirner<br />

was not a socialist.(4)<br />

Hence, not just the state but the capitalist economic<br />

system were the principal evils for the majority of<br />

a narc his t t h ink e r s 0 f the n i net e en t h c e n t ur y • I t wa s<br />

not accidental that in Kropotkin's delineation of the<br />

three cardinal aims of anarchist communism the first was<br />

an. i n j un c t Ion a g a ins t capita 1 ism: " Ema n c i pa t ion from<br />

the yoke of capital; production in common <strong>and</strong> free consum<br />

p t io n 0 f a 1· I the pro d u c t s 0 f common I abo r • " On I y<br />

after his exhortat ion to abol ish capitalism does one<br />

fInd a call for "emancipation from government" <strong>and</strong><br />

"emancipation from religion."(S) The views of the<br />

I t a I i an ana r chi s t, Err i coMa 1ate s t a (6 ) <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Britisher, William Morris(7) were similar. Both equated<br />

anarchism with communism <strong>and</strong> called for the free distribution<br />

of all goods. Bakunin, while a collectivist<br />

rather than 8 communist, also advocated ·the liberation<br />

fro m cap ita lis m . ( 8 ) Eve n inthe wr i tin gs 0 f the mo r e<br />

individualist-oriented anarchists one finds condemnations<br />

of capitalism coupled with panegyrics to socialism.<br />

In a striking phrase, Proudhon not only declared<br />

that rrproperty is theft,rr but also exclaimed "What is<br />

the capitalIst? Everything! What should he be?<br />

Nothing!"(9) Similarly, the English anarchist, William<br />

Godwin, asserted that "it follows upon the principles of<br />

equal <strong>and</strong> impartial justice, that the good things of the<br />

world are a common stock, upon which one man has as<br />

2


state intervention to protect profits <strong>and</strong> institutionali<br />

z e the poSIt ion 0 f the pr 0 per t y- own i ngel ass . When the<br />

sociological definition is used, capitalism becomes incomprehensible<br />

without control of the state by the bourgeoisie.<br />

For with the power of the state behind them,<br />

the bourgeoisie are able to protect their privileged<br />

positions from the threat of competition by the estab­<br />

1 ishment of tariff barriers, licensing restrictions, <strong>and</strong><br />

other statist measures.<br />

The propon en t s 0 f cap italism, howe ve r, had 0 n I y the<br />

economic definition in mind when they defended capitalism.(14)<br />

Far from intending to defend state intervent<br />

ion to preserve artificially high profits, it was, in<br />

fact, such pro-capital ist writers as Adam Smith who vehemen<br />

t 1 y condemned such "mercant i list" arrangements <strong>and</strong><br />

urged their replacement by free trade capitalism.(15)<br />

Since comparison can only be made when definitions tap<br />

the same domain, confusion occurred because of these definitional<br />

differences, <strong>and</strong> critics <strong>and</strong> opponents of<br />

cap ita lis m t a Ike d pas tea c hot her when rna ny werei n<br />

basic agreement. But if the economic spectrum is analyzed<br />

from the point of view of the economic definition<br />

on I y, the n com par i son can berna d eon the f 0 I low i ng<br />

bas is: cap ita lis m w0 u I d beequa ted wit h the rna r ke t ,<br />

communism with the absence of the market, <strong>and</strong> mercantilism<br />

with a mixed or restricted market.<br />

communism mercantilism capitalism<br />

0:-------------------:-------------------:100<br />

non-market restricted market market<br />

We are now in a pas i t i on to reassess the ant icapitalism<br />

of the anarchists. What is evident in such a<br />

taxonomy is that while certain anarchists such as<br />

Kropotkin <strong>and</strong> Bakunin must certainly be classified as<br />

social ist or communist, others like Proudbon, Godwin <strong>and</strong><br />

especially the native American anarchists such as Josiah<br />

Warren, Benjamin Tucker, <strong>and</strong> Victor Yarros, despIte<br />

their characterization of themselves as socialists, must<br />

be placed within the capitalist camp. A closer look at<br />

the anarchists themselves will make this clear.<br />

4


1. THE EOONCNIC SPECTRUM OF ANARCHISM: CXM\1UN ISM TO<br />

CAPITALISM<br />

a. Anafcho-communism.<br />

At one end of the anarchist spectrum we find those<br />

who, like Kropotkin <strong>and</strong> his followers, blend anarchism<br />

<strong>and</strong> commun i sm. The anarcho-communists oppose exchange,<br />

money, the division of labor, private property, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

wage system. Capi tal ism, they argue is just as "barbarous"<br />

as feudalism; only the forms have changed. "The<br />

worker is forced, under the name of free contract," says<br />

Kropotkin, "to accept feudal obligations. For turn<br />

where he will he can find no better conditions. Everything<br />

has become private property <strong>and</strong> he must accept, or<br />

die of hunger." Since the capJtalist owns the means of<br />

production he can dictate wage rates. This puts the<br />

worker at a distinct disadvantage. The wage system<br />

therefore reduces the worker to poverty.<br />

On the other h<strong>and</strong>, despite the advance in technology<br />

which has made a life of abundance possible for all,<br />

"the owners of capital constantly reduce the output by<br />

restricting production," thereby keeping prices high.<br />

Labor is further squ<strong>and</strong>ered by the production of luxur<br />

i es for the capi talist class, as well as by the money<br />

spent on armaments, salaries for judges, prison guards,<br />

policemen, etc. All money spent by governemnt is useless,<br />

says Kropotkin, since there is a definite relat<br />

ion s hip betwe encr i me <strong>and</strong> pove r t y • Hen ce, i f 0 nee I iminates<br />

capitalism, poverty <strong>and</strong> thus crime would nearly<br />

di sappear, <strong>and</strong> government would become unnecessary.<br />

Social behavior would be regulated by voluntary compliance<br />

to "unwritten customs." As Kropotkin's biographer,<br />

Mar tin Mille r, put it, "t he t r a d i t ion 0 f aut h 0 r i t y wa s<br />

to be replaced by the authority of tradition."(16) As<br />

for the "few anti-social acts that may still take<br />

place," says Kropotkin, "the best remedy will consist<br />

in loving treatment, moral influence, <strong>and</strong> liberty." And<br />

if that doesn't work then the aggressor can "of course<br />

·be expelled from fellowship."(17)<br />

Private property, whether that of capitalism or<br />

mercantilism, is likewise condemned. Since everything<br />

material as well as mental is a product of the contributions<br />

of countless individuals, past as well as present,<br />

it is impossible to determine the actual contributions<br />

of each. Consequently, argues Kropotkin, property cannot<br />

rightfUlly be private, but only common; all have a<br />

5


proletariat of the l<strong>and</strong> which it cultivates with its own<br />

han d s • " ( 2 3 ) The pea san t s, a c cording tot he prom i n en t<br />

Bakuninist James Guillaume, wIll then have the option of<br />

either owning <strong>and</strong> working their plots individually or<br />

assocIating Into collectives. Because of the advantages<br />

of the collective in. creating "a communal agency to sell<br />

or exchange the i r products," it is expected that the<br />

collect i ve wi II be the dominant form of organizat lon,<br />

but no coercion will be used to compel individual peasants<br />

to join the collectives.(24) A similar arrangement<br />

is envisioned for industry. Large-scale production, of<br />

course, would entail collective ownership, but h<strong>and</strong>icrafts<br />

<strong>and</strong> other small Industry may well be individually<br />

owned. As for remuneration, whereas anarcho-communism<br />

intends to follow the formula "From each according to<br />

his ability to each according to his needs," the collectivists,<br />

at least initially, adhere to the much different<br />

maxim of "From each according to hIS means to each<br />

according to hIS deeds."(25)<br />

To meet their needs it will be quite natural for<br />

the collectives to organize themselves into federations<br />

of collectlves.(26) Then, as Guillaume describes the<br />

operation of the anarcho-collectlvist society, "the<br />

workers' associations as well as the individual producers.<br />

• WIll deposit their unconsumed commodities In<br />

the f a c iIi tie s pro v Ide d b Y the Ba n k 0 f Ex c han ge, the<br />

value of the commoditIes having been established In advance<br />

by a contractual agreement between the regional<br />

cooperative federations <strong>and</strong> the various communes•••The<br />

Bank of Exchange Will reml t to the producers negot lable<br />

vouchers representIng the value of the products: These<br />

vouchers wi 11 be accepted throughout the territory included<br />

in the federation of communes."(27)<br />

The important difference between anarcho-communism<br />

<strong>and</strong> anarcho-collectivism is that while for the former<br />

the wage system <strong>and</strong> all other market phenomena will be<br />

abolished, the collectivists retain not only a modifIed<br />

wage system but other exchange relationships as well.<br />

Gui llaume, for example, acknowledges that so long as any<br />

pro d u c t s are ins h 0 r t sup ply the y wo u I d have to be<br />

treated as commodities WIth theIr prices set by the Bank<br />

of Exchange according to the dictates of supply <strong>and</strong><br />

d em <strong>and</strong> • Its h 0 u I d be poi n ted 0 ut, howe v e r, t hat the<br />

collectIvists believe that collective labor will be so<br />

productive that all shortages will eventually disappear<br />

<strong>and</strong> wi th it the need for any type of pr ice mechanism.(28)<br />

Once this plateau of plenty is reached, the<br />

structures of anarcho-communism <strong>and</strong> anarch-collectivism<br />

7


will become practically indistinguishable.<br />

c. Anarcho-syndicalism.<br />

Syndicalism is both an organizational structure <strong>and</strong><br />

a method of overthrowing the capitalist system. As a<br />

method, syndicalism, as popularized by Georges<br />

Sorei ( 29 ), i sarno v em en t pr em is ed on t he "my t h of the<br />

general strike" <strong>and</strong> the use of force. Violence, it is<br />

held, is necessary to overthrow both capitalism <strong>and</strong> the<br />

capitalist state. But to galvanize the workers into<br />

act ion, the y mu s t be 1 i eve inthe i nex 0 r a b 1e t r i urn ph 0 f<br />

their cause. It is this function that the "myth" fulfills.<br />

For by believing that the general strike will<br />

produce the triumph of their cause, it brings into relief<br />

the class antagonisms of the capitalist system. In<br />

do i ng so it un it es the proletar iat, producing an "epic<br />

state of mind" which rouses the proletariat to acts of<br />

"heroism."(30) This triumph of the proletarian will<br />

wi 11 eventually culminate in the overthrow of capitalism.<br />

Bel ief in the myth of the i r inev i table vi ctory, in<br />

other words, produces a will to action that does,<br />

indeed, make their victory inevitable.(31) Such, briefly,<br />

is the method of syndicalism.<br />

We are most interested, however, in the organizational<br />

{ramework that will prevail once syndicalism has<br />

tr iumphed. There is an important difference between<br />

synd i ca 1 ism <strong>and</strong> communism on the quest ion of the ownership<br />

of the means of production. While both aim to expropriate<br />

these from the capitalist, under communism, as<br />

envisioned by Kropotkin, all workers would collectively<br />

own all capital. Under syndicalism, however, only those<br />

workers in a particular industry would own the means of<br />

product i on wi thin that industry. This bears an obvious<br />

resemblance to the collectivism of Bakunin, <strong>and</strong> Bakuninism<br />

may actually be seen as a variant of syndicalism, as<br />

can the mutualism of Proudhon.<br />

The essential aspect of syndicalism is workers'<br />

control according to industry. While these syndicates<br />

o r i n d u s t ria lor g ani za t ion s are t 0 be aut 0 nom 0 us, they<br />

are n eve r the 1 esst 0 bel00s ely con federa t ed, bot h ge0g<br />

rap h i cal I y a s weI 1 a s fun c t ionall y • The wo r k e r sin<br />

each locality, according to Rudolph Rocker, will join<br />

the unions of their respective trades. All the unions<br />

in a given region will then be combined into Labor<br />

Chambers. It would be the responsibility of the Labor<br />

Chambers "to determIne the needs of the inhabitants of<br />

their districts <strong>and</strong> organize local consumption." On the<br />

8


to really own their portion of the industry. Since<br />

sociologically ownership is defined as the power to dispose<br />

of property', that individu.al or group within the<br />

s y n d i cat e wit h the power toprev e n t the wo r k e r from<br />

sel I ing "his" share to whom he wishes is the actual owner<br />

<strong>and</strong> controller. Rather than workers' control, there<br />

has merely been a change in form: one set of owners has<br />

replaced another. But if individuals within each industry<br />

really own a share of that industry then they must<br />

be permitted to dispose of their shares.as they see fit.<br />

This means that they can sell their shares to those outs<br />

i de of the industry. But such a pol icy would entai I an<br />

end to "workers' control" <strong>and</strong> a reemergence of the separation<br />

of ownership <strong>and</strong> labor which it was the aim of<br />

syndicalism to overcome. Similarly, the same dilemma<br />

pre sen t sit s elf i f the 0 rig ina 1 wo r k e r s - own e r s 0 f the<br />

more prosperous syndicates decide to hire workers as<br />

simple wage earners <strong>and</strong> not as part owners of the industry.<br />

To prevent them would be a denial of worker control;<br />

but so too would adoption of such a policy.<br />

Aga in, th ings would tend to return to the pre-syndicalis<br />

t, i. e • , cap i tal is t, s tat e of a f fa irs.<br />

T h us, wh i 1 e s y n d i c a lism rna y aim toe lim ina t e pr i ­<br />

va t e ownersh i p of the means of product ion, the wage syst<br />

em, the mar ke t, <strong>and</strong> e conom i c i nequa 1 i t y, the s t r uc t ur e<br />

of syndicalism itself forces a return to the paraphernalia<br />

of the market, if only in a somewhat modified<br />

form.(35)<br />

d. Mutual ism.<br />

Despite his famous remark that "property is theft,"<br />

Proudhon was, in fact, a staunch defender of the small<br />

property owner. He distinguished between property, in<br />

effect absentee ownership, <strong>and</strong> possession. His argument<br />

was that the l<strong>and</strong> really belonged to those who worked it<br />

<strong>and</strong> hence "possession," or "occupancy," "negated property."(36)<br />

He not only defended private ownership but the<br />

rights of barter, sale <strong>and</strong> hereditary property as well,<br />

<strong>and</strong> felt that individual liberty could be protected only<br />

if property were subject to no restriction but that of<br />

size. .<br />

The three cornerstones of Proudhon's ideal society<br />

are contract, exchange, <strong>and</strong> property. The state is to<br />

be abol i shed <strong>and</strong> all relations betwen individuals <strong>and</strong><br />

collectives are to be h<strong>and</strong>led by contract. "The notion<br />

of contract precludes that of government," writes<br />

10


Proudhon. And again, "Instead of laws we would have<br />

con t r act s. N0 I a ws wo u I d be passed e i the r by rna j 0 r i t Y<br />

vote or unanimously. Each citizen,each commune or corporation,<br />

would make its own laws."(37) The corollary<br />

of con tract is exchange; people contract wi th each other<br />

to exchange their products. Accordingly, Proudhon defines<br />

mutualism as "service for service, product for<br />

product. ."(38) Proudhon was not so much an opponent<br />

oft h e cap ita lis tic rna r ke t s ystem as 0 find us t rialism•<br />

He envisioned a society of numerous small <strong>and</strong> independent<br />

producers, voluntar i ly contract ing to exchange<br />

their products on an equitable basis. Where the nature<br />

of production makes such a framework impossible,<br />

Pro u d h 0 n a d v 0 cat e s a s ynd i c a listar rang emen t wh ere the<br />

workers in each industry would own the means of production<br />

in that industry. Relations between the syndicates<br />

<strong>and</strong> other syndicates or individual producers are to be<br />

h<strong>and</strong>led in the same way as relations between individual<br />

producers: exchange <strong>and</strong> contract. But for contract <strong>and</strong><br />

e x c hanget 0 berne ani ng f u I theremus t be pr i vat e owne r ­<br />

ship; one cannot exchange what one does not own.<br />

Proudhon, in fact, proclaims that property "is the only<br />

power that can act as a counterweight to the <strong>State</strong>•••"<br />

T h us, pro per t y he says, "i s the basis 0 f my s ystem 0 f<br />

federation."(39) It is not surprising to find, therefore,<br />

that Proudhon was in fact a bitter opponent of<br />

communism, which he defined as "the exploitation of the<br />

strong by the weak." Any society failing to recognize<br />

the right of private property, he felt, must inevitably<br />

breed a stUltifying rigidity <strong>and</strong> uniformity that is incompatible<br />

with "the free exercise of our faculties, ••<br />

• our noblest dreams, .•• our deepest feelings."(40)<br />

On the quest ion of crime in an anarchist society,<br />

Proudhon thought that contract was the sine qua non of<br />

just ice, <strong>and</strong> that a fully contractual society would be a<br />

fully just one. And he further believed, perhaps naively,<br />

that a just society would alleviate much of the tenden<br />

c y t.owar d<strong>and</strong> need for c rim ina I beha v i 0 r • The 0 c c a ­<br />

sional anti-social individual, Proudhon thought, could<br />

be h<strong>and</strong>led through the method of voluntary reparation.<br />

The c rim ina 1 w0 u 1 d b e askedt 0 rna kerepar a t ion to his<br />

'victim, <strong>and</strong> the threat of being the target of public<br />

disapprobation if he refused would all but insure compliance.<br />

And since reparation accords the criminal "as<br />

much respect as he lost through his crime..•[h]is repa<br />

rat ion i sal so are h a b iIi tat ion." F ina II y, anyone<br />

regularly violating the norms of the society, <strong>and</strong> refusing<br />

to make reparation, what Proudhon terms the "hopelessly<br />

obdurate scoundrel," can legitimately be subject-<br />

11


ed to physical suffering <strong>and</strong> even death.(41)<br />

In short, despite Proudhon's famous statement on<br />

property <strong>and</strong> his regular condemnations of flcapitalism,"<br />

the essent ial components of mutualism are private property,<br />

exchange, <strong>and</strong> contract. With the one SIgnificant<br />

exception of his stricture concerning the size of property,<br />

mutualism is, in most other respects, not incompatibLe<br />

with capitalism.(42)<br />

e • Godwi n i sm ..<br />

H. N. Bra i I s ford says of Godwi n that fl intensely<br />

equal i tar ian, he permits property only that it may be<br />

given away."(43) A close look at William Godwin, however,<br />

reveals that despite his repeated condemnations of<br />

"accumulated property" he was probably an even more<br />

vigorous defender of private ownership than Proudhon.<br />

The idea of property, says Godwin, "is a deduction from<br />

the right of private judgement." Thus, he continues,<br />

pro per t y is, "i nthe 1a s t res 0 r t, the pa 11 ad i urn 0 f all<br />

t hat ought to be dear to us, <strong>and</strong> mus t never be approache<br />

d but wit haw e <strong>and</strong> ve n era t ion • " ( 44 ) I n fa c t, wh i I e<br />

otherwise eschewing violence, Godwin even goes so far as<br />

to remark that the "right of property, with all its inequalities•.should<br />

be defended if need be by<br />

coe rei on. . ."<br />

Godwin views property according to "three degrees."<br />

The fir st<strong>and</strong> most fundamental is that a person may own<br />

property provided U a greater sum of benefit or pleasure<br />

wi II resul t, than could have arisen from their being<br />

otherwise appropriated." From this he believes it foIlow<br />

s "that noma n rna y, i nordina r y ca s e s, rna k e use 0 f my<br />

apartment, furniture or garments, or of my food, ••.<br />

without fIrst having obtained my consent." The crucial<br />

function of the "flrst degree of property," is that if<br />

everyone is granted a certaIn sphere of property, no one<br />

wou I d be subject to the whims of another. Hence property<br />

will provide everyone WIth a sphere of action where<br />

he can exercise his judgement free from the influence of<br />

others.<br />

The second degree of property is the right of every<br />

man "over the produce of his own labor." While this is<br />

less fundamental than the fIrst degree, the latter does<br />

not automatically take precedence. Instead, the fIrst<br />

degree can only be attained by persuasion <strong>and</strong> the force<br />

of public opinion.<br />

12


ished or expelled from the Union. And further, while<br />

there are neither rights nor duties, <strong>and</strong> power is the be<br />

a 1 I <strong>and</strong> end a I 1, sothat 0 ne own son I y wh a the has the<br />

power to control, it is clear that Stirner believes that<br />

the utility of a secure property structure would encourage<br />

the Unions to protect that institution. "Unions<br />

will ,n hewr i t e s, "mu I tip I Y the i nd i v i d ua I 's me a ns<strong>and</strong><br />

SeCure his assailed property."(51)<br />

Asin 0 the r t ypes 0 fanarchism, the ego i s tic wr i tings<br />

of Stirner contain a sustained condemnation of capital<br />

ism <strong>and</strong> "legal property." A closer view,however,<br />

makes it evident that what Stirner opposes is actually<br />

the mercant i list, or state capitalist,system. Thus he<br />

wr i t esthat "t he<strong>State</strong> i sac0 mm 0 ner' s [merchant's]<br />

<strong>State</strong>. ""Under the regime of the commonality," he<br />

says, "the laborers always fall into the h<strong>and</strong>s of the<br />

possessors -- i.e., of those who have at their disposal<br />

some bit of the <strong>State</strong> domains, ••• especially money<br />

<strong>and</strong> 1<strong>and</strong>; 0 f the ca pit a lis t the ref 0 r e. " And aga in:<br />

"The commoner is what he is through the protection of<br />

the <strong>State</strong>, through the <strong>State</strong> 's gr ace. " ( 52 )Thesestatemen<br />

t s, i nth ems e 1 ve s, are compa t ib 1e wit h f r e e -ma r ke t<br />

capitalism. Further, Stirner was such a bitter opponent<br />

of any type of communism that Karl Marx wrote that<br />

S t i r n e r 's It ego i s ticalpr ope r t y • • • is not h i ng more<br />

than ordinary or bourgeois property sanctified."(53) So<br />

wh i I e hewa s vag u e concern i ng wh a t r ole the rna r ket<strong>and</strong><br />

private property would play in a Stirnerite society,<br />

Charles Madison accurately captures the thrust of<br />

S t i r n e r ism when herema r ks t hat "i ron i ca I 1yen0 ugh, the<br />

h a r d s elf ish n e s s 0 f t his i n d i v i d ua listanarchism wa s<br />

admira b 1 Y ad 8 pte d tothe' rug g edind i v i d u 8 I ism' 0 f<br />

modern capitalism."{S4) It might also be pointed out<br />

that such prominent exponents of egoism as John Babcock<br />

<strong>and</strong> John Henry Mackay considered private property sacrosanct<br />

<strong>and</strong> reserved a central role for voluntary contract<br />

<strong>and</strong> exchange for mutual benefit. But both, it should be<br />

noted, were also heavily influenced by the prominent ind<br />

i v i d uali s tor "ph i los 0 phi cal" a narchis t, Ben jamin<br />

Tucker. (55)<br />

g. Philosophical Anarchism.<br />

What is usually termed the philosophical anarchist<br />

tradition received its fullest expression in the writings<br />

of the nineteenth century American anarchists, <strong>and</strong><br />

in particular'Benjamin Tucker <strong>and</strong> Victor Yarros. Tucker,<br />

1 ike other anarchists, couc'hed his arguments in socialist<br />

terminology. Yet an examination of his ideas, as<br />

15


Mu r ray Rot h bar d a g r e e wit h the 0 vera I 1str uc t ur e of the<br />

Tucker i tes: th.e state is to be abolished <strong>and</strong> everything<br />

is to be h<strong>and</strong>led by, or at least open to the possibility<br />

of, competition on the free market. There is one signifie<br />

ant d iff erenee t howe ve r • Wh i leTueker, adher i ng t 0<br />

the labor theory of value, felt that competition would<br />

reduce price to cost, thereby eliminating profits, rents<br />

<strong>and</strong> interest, the individualist anarchists reject the<br />

labor theory of value <strong>and</strong> adopt, in its place, the subj<br />

e c t i ve val u e-ma r gina I ut iIi t Y approach. Fr ee compe t ition<br />

would indeed tend to reduce prices <strong>and</strong> raise wages,<br />

the y say, but the Tuck e r i t e s are i n err 0 r in believ ing<br />

t hat t his mea n s t hat profit s<strong>and</strong>in t eres t wo u 1d a Iso<br />

disappear. Instead, their maintenance is seen as a<br />

requisite for economic rationality, <strong>and</strong> even society<br />

itself.(58)<br />

2. THE POLITICAL SPECTRUM OF CAPITALISM: ANARCHISM TO<br />

HYPERARCHISM<br />

A b r i e f 0 v e r view 0 f the e con om i c s pee t r urn 0 fana r ­<br />

chism revealed a wide array of economic arrangements.<br />

Similarly, the proponents of capitalism traverse the ent<br />

ire pol i tic a I s p e c t rum from a narchism towhat rna y be<br />

c a I led tl h Yper arc his m . " 0 n I y by view i n g t his a r ray 0 f<br />

groups <strong>and</strong> then comparing the political spectrum of capita<br />

lis m wit h the e con om i c s pee t r urn 0 fanarchism can the<br />

relative positions of the individualist, or free market,<br />

anarchists be ascertained.<br />

a. Individualist Anarchism.<br />

The previous discussion of individualist anarchism<br />

focused on its place in the anarchist school. Its posit<br />

ion wit h i nth e cap ita 1 i s t s pe c t r urn s til I need s t 0 be<br />

discerned. The sanctity of private property <strong>and</strong> the<br />

market lie at the heart of laissez faire capitalism.<br />

From a logical point of view, the more things are h<strong>and</strong>led<br />

by the market, the more capitalistic the society.<br />

Co n sis ten t I yap p 1 ied, a r g u e the i n d i v i d ua lis t ana r.-<br />

.chists, capitalism leads to anarchism. Hence, they<br />

argue, the minarchists, or limited-government libertarians,<br />

place themselves in a contradiction for, while believing<br />

that property rights must be protected <strong>and</strong> the<br />

market maintained, they also believe that these services<br />

--the police <strong>and</strong> court functions--are by their nature<br />

col I e c t i v e <strong>and</strong> can not be prov ided by the rna r ke t . Thus<br />

the y are f or c edt 0 reI y on an agencyou t s i de t he rna r ­<br />

kett i.e., the government. The minarchist, it is ar-<br />

17


he sees no reason why government would have to enforce<br />

its 0 wn 1a w • I n f act, h e a c k n.O w1e dgesthat "pr i vat e<br />

police forces are doubtless much more efficient than<br />

those run by governmen t." (66) There is therefore an<br />

economic advantage to permitting police protection to be<br />

han dieden t ire I y b Y the rna r ke t • The 0 n 1y res t ric t ion<br />

that would be necessary to impose upon these private<br />

police companies -- a restriction that Hospers feels<br />

would be impossible to impose in an anarchist society -is<br />

that t1they should be able to enforce only the law of<br />

the l<strong>and</strong>. ."(67) Beyond this, police companies would<br />

have complete freedom to compete against one another<br />

just like firms in any other field. Anyone desiring<br />

policaprotection could purchase it from the firm of his<br />

choice. And while no one would be compelled to purchase<br />

protection, only those paying the protection fee would<br />

r e c e i v e pro t e c t ion • " I f you wa n t po I ice prot e c t ion you<br />

have to pay a fee to obtain it, but of course you are<br />

free not to want it or pay for it, in which case,"<br />

Hospers cont inues, "you wi II not have the protection<br />

even if you need it."(68)<br />

In short, Hospers maintains that while "laws should<br />

.be enacted by the state, ••. the enforcement of<br />

them migh t be Ieft topr i vateage nc i e s • n ( 69 ) The prov i ­<br />

s i on of bot h pol ice <strong>and</strong> court services would be h<strong>and</strong>led<br />

on a fee-for-service basis, with individuals free to<br />

purchase or not to purchase these services as they see<br />

fit, but unable to purchase the services of any maverick<br />

pol ice agency or court which adhere to norms at variance<br />

with those laid down by the state.<br />

It is interesting to note that since a Hosperian<br />

state would render protection only to those purchasing<br />

it, i t doe s not me e t the c r i t e rion 0 f ami n i rna1state<br />

which, by definition, must provide protection for everyone<br />

within its territorial boundaries regardless of paymen<br />

t • We rna y, theref 0 r e, b 0 r r ow ater m co i ned by phi 10sopher<br />

Robert Nozick, <strong>and</strong> refer to Hospers as an "ultraminarchist."<br />

But it is possible that even this appellation is<br />

too s t ron g . On e 0 f the e ssen t i a I c r i t e ria 0fa" s tat e "<br />

is that it must be generally recognized as exercising a<br />

legitimate monopoly on the use of force within a given<br />

area.(70) But since, in a Hosperian society, the use of<br />

force would presumably be h<strong>and</strong>led not by the "government"<br />

but entirely by private police agencies, this<br />

raises the question of whether the Hosperian framework<br />

meets this monopoly criterion. Hospers might, of<br />

20


course, argue that his entire system -- the legislature<br />

plus fee-for-service courts <strong>and</strong> the private police agencies<br />

-- constitutes a "state."<br />

But however one may resolve such definitional problems<br />

this still leaves open the really crucial question<br />

of how, if the use of force is to be left up to private<br />

police agencies, could the Hosperian proviso that these<br />

agencies must only enforce the legislature's statutory<br />

laws be enforced? What would happen if one, or two or a<br />

d 0 zen e n for c ementage nc i esstart edenfor c i ng norms t hat<br />

confl icted wi th the laws enacted by the legislature?<br />

There are, so far as I can see, two possible scenarios.<br />

Fir s t, H0 s per s mig h t con tend t hat sinc e thesernaverick<br />

agencies would clearly be acting illegally either they<br />

would not receive public patronage <strong>and</strong> so go out of<br />

business. or other police agencies, perceiving the<br />

threat of the illegals, would join forces to crush them.<br />

But since these are exactly the same measures Rothbardian<br />

anarchists rely on to insure the enforcement of<br />

the i r comm0 n I a w, H0 s pers' u I t ram ina r chi s m beeomesal I<br />

but i n dis tin g u ish a b I e from Ro t hbar d ian a narchism• But<br />

Hospers might argue for a second course, that of permitting<br />

the pUblic legislature to diversify into the provision<br />

of police services. The public agency might then<br />

not only enact laws but have enough force at its disposal<br />

to punish or crush any maverick agency. But since<br />

Hospers admits that private agencies are much more efficient<br />

than pUblic ones it is difficult to see why anyone<br />

wou I d pu r cha se protect ion from the la t ter. Consequent­<br />

I y, the 0 n 1 y way s the pub 1 i c age n c y cou I d r ema i n i n<br />

business would be either by outlawing not just maverick,<br />

but all, private police agencies, or by charging every<br />

pol ice agency a fee sufficiently high to cover the pub­<br />

I i c age n c y 's los s e s • Sinc e the pub 1 i c agenc y wo u 1d now<br />

hold an effective monopoly on the use of force it would<br />

meet the criteria for a state, although if it continued<br />

to operate on a fee-for-service basis it would remain a<br />

less than minimal state. But, it must be noted, neither<br />

oft he s e 0 p t ion s can be r e con c i led wit h 1 i be r tar ian<br />

principles. The outlawing of all private agencies would<br />

·constitute a restriction on peaceful activities, while<br />

the fee charged every agency would be neither voluntary(71)<br />

nor paid in exchange for services rendered. It<br />

would therefore be a tax in the full sense of that word.<br />

Ins h 0 r t, H0 s persis PI acedin a d i 1emma: e i the r he<br />

must accede in some restriction on peaceful activities<br />

<strong>and</strong>/or taxat ion, thereby violating his libertarianism,<br />

o r hem u s t reI y for the en for cern e n t 0 f his n s tat utor y<br />

21


law" on non-monopolistic mechanisms, thereby ab<strong>and</strong>oning<br />

his archism. Thus, Hosperian ultraminarchism appears to<br />

con t a ina s e rio usin t ern a 1 con t r ad i c t ion wh i c h wo u I d<br />

logically compel it to move either to complete anarchism<br />

or fUll-fledged minarchism.<br />

e. Minarehism.<br />

Thosewhod 0 not believethat a rna r ke t for prot e ct<br />

ion s e r vic e s w 0 u I d bee i the r e conom i cal I y v i a b 1e 0 r<br />

morally permissible must therefore endorse some sort of<br />

s tat e • And thosew i t h i ntha t g r 0 up wh 0 rna i n t a i ntha t<br />

the provis ion of such services is the only proper function<br />

of government must therefore advocate a minimal, or<br />

completely laissez faire, state. The "minarchist" position<br />

has received its most recent <strong>and</strong> perhaps ablest -at<br />

any rate most ingenious -- expression in the "invisible<br />

h<strong>and</strong>" argument of philosopher Robert Nozick.<br />

Nozick begins with a discussion of a hypothetical<br />

free market anarchist society. But protective services,<br />

he says, di ffer from other types of services in that<br />

they employ the use of coercion. Therefore, in defending<br />

their respective clients they would come into confl<br />

i ct wi th each other, the result being that one dominant<br />

protect ive agency would eliminate its competition<br />

<strong>and</strong> emerge as the single such agency in the particular<br />

geographical region. This, says Nozlek, would eOllstitute<br />

an "ultraminimal state," which differs from the<br />

minimal state of the classical liberals in that the<br />

-former, by the law of supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>, eliminates its<br />

competition in 8 particular area, thereby maintaining "a<br />

monopoly over the use of force" but providing "protection<br />

<strong>and</strong> enforcement services only to those who would<br />

purchase its protection <strong>and</strong> enforcement policies."(72)<br />

The classical liberal state, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, held 8<br />

legal monopoly over the use of force <strong>and</strong> supplied protection<br />

services to all its citizens.<br />

But, a r g u e s N0 z i c k, the "u I tram i n i rna 1state" wi I I<br />

s 0 0 n t rans formit s elf i n t 0 ami n irna1state, for underan<br />

"ultraminimal state" individuals would still be free to<br />

extract "private justice." But "the knowledge that one<br />

is living under a system permitting this, itself, produces<br />

apprehension," with individuals never knowing how<br />

or wh en the y ma y r e c e i ve "re t r i bu t ion" from a pr iva t e<br />

agent·. Fear will pervade the entire society. Thus private<br />

justice constitutes "a public wrong." To protect<br />

its c i i e n t s, the d 0 min ant pro t e c t i ve agen c y rna y then<br />

"prohibit the independents from such self-help enforce-<br />

22


There is, however, the potential for an additional<br />

pro b I em. Sup po s e, the 0 r i z e s Roy Ch i Ids, t hat in the<br />

midst of an establ ished minimal state an agency arises<br />

which uses procedures identical to those of the state's<br />

agents. Since, under this condition, the incipient<br />

agency could not be any more risky than the state, a<br />

s tat e 0 per a tin g 0 n N0 z i c k ian pr inc i pies wo u I d ha ve no<br />

grounds for prohibiting its activities. But, continues<br />

Chi Ids, since the state was already compensating those<br />

who would have patronized agencies using risky procedures,<br />

the new agency would not have to assume this burden<br />

<strong>and</strong> could therefore charge lower prices for the same<br />

qual i ty service. This would, in turn, create an economic<br />

incentive for people to subscribe to the new agency,<br />

thereby forcing the minimal state to ab<strong>and</strong>on its own<br />

compensation policy. But this would mean that the minimal<br />

state had reverted to the ultraminimal state. But,<br />

cont inues Chi Ids, provided the new agency continued to<br />

win new cl ients, <strong>and</strong> other entrepreneurs, seeing the<br />

success of the new agency, entered the field themselves,<br />

the u I t ram i n i mal s tat e W 0 u 1 d de g e n era t e in to a me r e<br />

dominant agency, <strong>and</strong> eventually that into "simply one<br />

age n c yam 0 n g mIi n y • " Insh0 r t, Ch i 1ds a r gue s, therei s<br />

no reason, on strietly Nozictian grounds, why the invisible<br />

h<strong>and</strong> could not strike back.(80)<br />

But regardless of how it is justified, the minarch<br />

i s t advoca t es 8 single agency wi th a monopoly on the<br />

use 0 f for c e ins 0 c i e t y <strong>and</strong> wh 0 S e sol e fun c t ion i s the<br />

protection of individual rights.<br />

d. Evolutionary Individualist Anarchism.<br />

)<br />

An interesting view, which proposed a minimal state<br />

for the present, wh i Ie espousing an anarchist society<br />

for the future, was that advanced by the nineteenth<br />

century English philosopher, Herbert Spencer, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

French economist, Frederic Bastiat. Both condemned any<br />

extens ion of government beyond the minimum necessary to<br />

protect the natural rights of every individual. Spencer<br />

argued that "every man has freedom to do as he wills,<br />

provided he infringes not the equal freedom of every<br />

other man." From this it follows, he believed, that if<br />

government does anything more than protect individual<br />

rights "it becomes an aggressor instead of a protector."<br />

(81) Thus Spencer was an ardent opponent not only<br />

of any. regulation of commerce, religion, health, education,<br />

etc., but of taxation as well. Indeed, Spencer<br />

goes even further <strong>and</strong> declares that the individual has a<br />

"right to ignore the state." His reasoning is instruc-<br />

24


logic of the Beairdian analysis, every property owner<br />

would have the right to contract with the government of<br />

his choice. But this can only mean that all governments<br />

would operate on a fee-for-service basis. For any government<br />

endeavoring to provide free protection for the<br />

poor would be forced to raise its premiums to cover the<br />

subsidy. But this, of course, would encourage its patrons<br />

to seek protection from other governments not prov<br />

i dingas u bsid y <strong>and</strong> the ref 0 rein a posit ion toof fer<br />

lower rates. Thus, under the Beairdlan proposal only<br />

those paying for protection would receive it. But this<br />

is. c I ear I y a t 0 d d s with R<strong>and</strong>'s ass e r t i on that un deran<br />

objectivist government everyone, including the poor,<br />

would receive protection.(95) Thus, while R<strong>and</strong> opts for<br />

a minarchist state, Beaird's proposal would be consistent<br />

with, at most, an ultraminarchist state.<br />

Sec 0 n d 1y, R<strong>and</strong>'s ma j 0 r c r i tic ism 0 f "fr e e rna r ke t<br />

anarchism" is its failure to solve the problem of jurisd<br />

i c t ion • Beair d, 0 f cour s e, rei t e ra t esthis· c r i tic ism<br />

<strong>and</strong> maintains that this would not be a problem under his<br />

proposal since "only one government" would have "authority<br />

on a plot of l<strong>and</strong> at a time." But surely this would<br />

not be sufficient to alleviate the jurisdictional problem.<br />

Ironically, R<strong>and</strong>'s criticism of anarchism would<br />

a p ply wit h e qua I i f not grea t e r for c e tothis Ra nd- a 1a ­<br />

Beaird proposal. For it would certainly be possible for<br />

a Beairdian society to be confronted with a situation in<br />

which "Mr. Smith, a customer of Goverment A, suspects<br />

that his ••• neighbor, Mr. Jones, a customer of Government<br />

B , has rob bed him," <strong>and</strong> ne i ther Go ve r nme n t r e cogn i ze s<br />

the other as legitimate. In fact, if every property<br />

owner were free to subscribe to the government of his<br />

c hoi c e, the n umb e r 0 f go v ernmen t s wo u I d be 1ike 1y to<br />

increase enormously -- theoretically there could be as<br />

many gover nments as property owners -- thereby magni fying<br />

the potential for the type of jurisdictional problems<br />

R<strong>and</strong> is so anxious to avoid.<br />

Finall y, itis i n t eres ting t hat Ra nd ca lIs the idea<br />

of "competing governments" -- the idea that "every citizen"<br />

should be "free to 'shop' <strong>and</strong> to patronize whatever<br />

government he chooses," -- a "floating abstraction" <strong>and</strong><br />

a "weird absurdity." But how else could one classify<br />

the Beair d ian pro p 0 s a I e x c e ptin t e r ms 0 f "compet i ng<br />

governments" <strong>and</strong> the right of "every citizen••• to<br />

'shop' <strong>and</strong> to patronize the government of his choice"?<br />

28


exp<strong>and</strong>s <strong>and</strong> more areas are subject to vote, the scope of<br />

the market becomes progressively more restricted. Of<br />

t his pro b 1em, <strong>Mises</strong>ca n me reI y hope t hat the rna j 0 r i t Y<br />

wi II exercise such self-restraint that government will<br />

remain miniscle.(99)<br />

The doctrinaire liberal also faces another dilemma.<br />

On the one h<strong>and</strong> he is passionate in defending the right<br />

oft he in d i v i dual tor un his life as he de ems fit.<br />

<strong>Mises</strong>, as we have seen, terms the extension of government<br />

beyond the protection of rights an "evil." But<br />

since government is necessary, <strong>and</strong> since it must have<br />

revenue, "taxes are necessary_"(lOO) If it is evil to<br />

confiscate part of the earnings of individua1s for some<br />

things, however, why is it not just as evil to confiscate<br />

them for other things such as court <strong>and</strong> police services?<br />

To this <strong>Mises</strong> can merely say that "the expenditure<br />

caused by the apparatus of a liberal community is<br />

so small" that it will be of little burden to the individual.(lOl)<br />

But the dilemma remains: taxation, whether<br />

large or small, constitutes a violation of the principles<br />

of liberalism so cherished by men like <strong>Mises</strong>.<br />

In short, while what government exists is to be<br />

d em 0 c rat i c, the doc t r ina ire I i ber a Idesirest 0 res t rict<br />

government activity as much as possible; he is a procapitalist<br />

first <strong>and</strong> a democrat second. The positions<br />

are reversed, however, for the moderate liberal, for he<br />

is prepared to see, <strong>and</strong> in fact often advocates, the extension<br />

of government into areas that the dogmatic liberal<br />

would consider anathema. The prototype of this<br />

group, which would include the bulk of the classical<br />

liberals, is John Stuart Mill. "The purpose for which<br />

power can rightfully be exercised over any member ofa<br />

c i viii zed c omm un i t Y a ga ins t his wi I 1 ," says Mil I, "j s t 0<br />

pre v en t h arm toother s • His own good. • • i s not a s u f ­<br />

f i c i e n twa r ran t • "( 10 2 ) Wit h s uchastateme n t Mil I a ppears<br />

to fall into the dogmatic liberal tradition. But<br />

as George Sabine wrote of Mill, he was uncompromising in<br />

the abstract, "but having stated the principle, he proceeded<br />

to make concessions <strong>and</strong> restatements until in the<br />

end the original theory was explained away without any<br />

new principle being put in its place."(103)<br />

T h u s the s tat e rna y ifit wi shes, he says, regu Iate<br />

t r a d e 8 s weI I a s the h 0 u r s 0 f t a v ern s • I t rna y even<br />

" con f "i net h e power 0 f sell i ng thesecomm 0 d i ties. • • t 0<br />

persons of vouched-for respectability of conduct." The<br />

state has the duty to enforce "universal education" <strong>and</strong><br />

to he I p to pay the school fees of the poorer classes of<br />

30


tal of nations, <strong>and</strong> of ages ••• Prejudice<br />

renders a man.'s virtue,·his habit; <strong>and</strong> not a<br />

series of unconnected acts. Through just<br />

prejudice, his duty becomes a part of his<br />

na t ur e • ( 109 )<br />

One of the conservative traditions is the reluctance<br />

to rely on the government to solve social evils.<br />

Hence, conservatives opt for a limited government <strong>and</strong> a<br />

generally laissez faire economic system. But not only<br />

dot hey not 0 p P 0 set h e use 0 f for c e toprot e c t thos e<br />

"true values" that are viewed as necessary to maintain<br />

the social order, they feeIi t ' s one's duty to use force<br />

for such ends. Thus, force is advocated against such<br />

things as pornography, prostitution, labor unions, communism,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the like. Another fact of conservatism is<br />

that it consciously eschews delineating a positive program,<br />

wh i ch it condemns as abs tract theorizing. Instead,<br />

its overriding characteristic is its resistance<br />

to "the enemies of the permanent things."(IIO) The most<br />

feared enemy is communism. The Conservatives feel that<br />

it is man's moral duty to oppose communism by any means<br />

necessary <strong>and</strong> therefore advocate the use of government<br />

coercion on this regard. "The communists," argues noted<br />

conservative writer, James Burnham, "are serious <strong>and</strong>••<br />

• are irrevocably fixed on their goal of a monopoly of<br />

world power • Because the communists are serious,<br />

they will have to be stopped ••• by superior power <strong>and</strong><br />

will. Just possibly we shall not have to die in large<br />

numbers to stop them; but we shall certainly have to be<br />

willing to die."(lll)<br />

But, as has often been pointed out by their critics,<br />

conservatives place themselves in a serious dilemma.<br />

First, while they are in general opposed to government<br />

power <strong>and</strong> endorse a market economy, their willingn<br />

esst 0 use go v ernmen t for ce toprot e c t "the pe r rna nen t<br />

t h i n g s ," nee e s sitate s res t rict ionson the ma r ke t t hat<br />

are far fro m min i rna 1 • Fur ther, the f ear 0 f "the wo rldwide<br />

communist menace," has meant their endorsement of a<br />

military large enough "to defend the West against all<br />

.challenges <strong>and</strong> challengers."(112) Not only is it difficuI<br />

t t 0 see how the r equi r emen t s 0 f s uchala r gemiii ­<br />

tary can be reconciled with their espousal of a minimal<br />

state, but a huge military can only be financed by massive<br />

taxation which, itself, constitutes further restrictions<br />

of the market. Thus, while the conservatives<br />

generally endorse a market economy they are also perfectly<br />

willing to restrict its operations for goals they<br />

con sid e r m0 rei mp 0 r tan t • Inthe ins i gh t f u 1 c ommen t 0 f<br />

33


top indicates the political range of capitalism; the<br />

u n b r 0 ken v e r ticall i ne i ndieates ' the e con om i esc0 pe 0 f<br />

anarchism.(118)<br />

Box [1] entai Is both a capi tal ist ic economic system<br />

<strong>and</strong> a nanarchis tic pol i tica 1 s t rue t u r e • Th i s wo u I d<br />

include the contemporary individualist anarchists such<br />

as Rothbard <strong>and</strong> Friedman as well as the philosophical<br />

anarchists such as Tucker <strong>and</strong> Spooner., Still squarely<br />

with i nth e a n 8 r chi s t s peet r urn but rno v i ng s 1 i g h t 1Y awa y<br />

from capitalism would be Stirner <strong>and</strong> Godwin. On the<br />

other h<strong>and</strong> somewhat less anarchistic but still ardently<br />

capitalistic would be the ultraminarchists such as<br />

Hospers.<br />

Box [2] entails a limited form of government<br />

c 0 u pIe d withaca pit a lis t ic e c on om i cstrue t ur e • This<br />

would include the minarchists, like Nozick, the<br />

e vol uti 0 n a r y a n 8 r chi s t s, 1 ike Spen c e r 8nd B8 s t i at, as<br />

well as the objectivists. Also included in this<br />

category would be the doctrinaire classical liberals<br />

such as Humboldt <strong>and</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>, <strong>and</strong> thei r more moderate<br />

counterparts like Mill <strong>and</strong> Smith <strong>and</strong>, more currently,<br />

Hayek.<br />

Box [3] entails a highly interventionist state coupled<br />

with a market economy. Such a state would restrict<br />

its interventionist activities to the social realm, regu<br />

1 a tin g s pee c h, pre s s, d rug use, <strong>and</strong> t he I ike, wh i Ie<br />

permi tt ing the market to function freely. While this<br />

cat ego r y is, per haps, 0 f rather 1 imit e d emp i ricalimport,<br />

probably the closest thing to capitalist-hyperarchi<br />

s m w0 u I d bethe cons e r vat ism 0 f Bur ke <strong>and</strong> de Ma i s t r e<br />

<strong>and</strong>, more currently, Buckley, Kirk, <strong>and</strong> Burnham.<br />

Box [4] entails an anarchist political framework as<br />

in Box [1], but a less capitalistic economic structure<br />

than prevailed in Boxes [1-3]. There would still be<br />

much market phenomena <strong>and</strong> individual ownership, however<br />

some form of collectivism or workers' control is also<br />

envisioned. This would include the mutualism of<br />

Proudhon <strong>and</strong> Warren <strong>and</strong>, while somewhat more collectively<br />

oriented, the syndicalism of Sorel, Rocker, <strong>and</strong><br />

Goldman.<br />

Box [5] e n t a i 1st helimit a t ion 0 f the rna r ke t by<br />

interest group democracy which extends government into<br />

areas that under Boxes [1-3] would be h<strong>and</strong>led by the<br />

market. This includes the modern exponents of pluralism<br />

<strong>and</strong> the partisans of contemporary liberalism <strong>and</strong> the<br />

36


welfare state such as John Rawls.<br />

Box [6] e n ta i Iss everei imita t i ons on the rna r ke t •<br />

Democracy is also rejected in favor of rule by elites.<br />

It includes the mercantilists <strong>and</strong> cameralists of the<br />

eighteenth century, <strong>and</strong> the extreme conservatives as<br />

well as the exponents of fascism <strong>and</strong> nazism such as<br />

Rockwell <strong>and</strong> Gentile.<br />

Box [7]. entails the rejection of the state coupled<br />

wi th a pronounced movement toward a marketless economy.<br />

T his would inc1ude the a narch0 - colI e c t i vism of Ba kun in,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the more extreme anarcho-communism of Kropotkin.<br />

Box [8] entai Is a social ist economy coupled with<br />

some form of limited statism. It would include the<br />

quasi-anarchist ic Guild Socialism with its reliance on<br />

fun c t ionaIr e pre sentat ion, wh ere the 0 n 1y r ole for the<br />

state is to mediate between the functional groups when<br />

controversies could not be otherwise resolved. Close to<br />

t his w0 u 1 d b e F a b ian ism (1 8 8 9) wit hit s em phas i son<br />

universal suffrage <strong>and</strong> municipal or local control of<br />

industry.<br />

Box [9] entails a socialist or communist economic<br />

framework with planning to be done through the instrumen<br />

t a lit Y 0 f the s tat e • This wo u Idinc Iude the Br i tis h<br />

Labor Party (1937) with its call for nationalization of<br />

industry <strong>and</strong> a 1t general state plan." Close to this is<br />

Fa b ian ism (19 0 8) wit h em p has i s on na tiona I i za t ion 0 f<br />

sue h i n d u s t r i e s as wa t e r wo r ks, the mine s, <strong>and</strong> the ha r ­<br />

bors, as well as a large dose of state planning. Also<br />

included in this category would be Marxism, which advocated<br />

a planned economy, but one in which all individuals<br />

participated in both the planning <strong>and</strong> the execution<br />

of the plans, <strong>and</strong> the elite-planned socialist technocracies<br />

outlined by Saint-Simon <strong>and</strong> Edward Bellamy.<br />

If the foregoing is correct, the traditional view<br />

that anarchism is incompatible with capitalism is clearly<br />

incorrect. Both anarchism <strong>and</strong> capitalism traverse a<br />

·w ide s p e c t rum oft h 0 ugh t, <strong>and</strong> wh i Ie s orne varian t s 0 f<br />

anarchism are incompatible with some variants of capitalism,<br />

other types are quite compatible. Moreover, the<br />

place of the individualist anarchists in both the economic<br />

<strong>and</strong> the political sepctrums has been pointed out,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the initial groundwork has been laid for the study<br />

of individualist anarchism.<br />

37


FOOTNOTES<br />

(l)Onemay distinguish between "states" <strong>and</strong> governments."<br />

For example, John S<strong>and</strong>ers says that "states are<br />

not taken to be the same as governments••• They are<br />

communities-with-governments." Government therefore is<br />

a necessary but not a sufficient condition for a state.<br />

Since S<strong>and</strong>ers defines government "in terms of coercion,"<br />

<strong>and</strong> since government is a necessary condition for a<br />

s tat e, the s tat e too isinher en t 1Y coer c i ve. See John<br />

T. S<strong>and</strong>ers, The Ethical Argument Against Government<br />

(Washington, D.C.: University Press of American, 1980),<br />

p p. x i-xii i • Since the purpos e 0 f t h j sstudy i s topr e ­<br />

sent <strong>and</strong> analyze a particular voluntary model of social<br />

organization <strong>and</strong> to compare it with the coercive model,<br />

unless otherwise noted, I will use the terms "government"<br />

<strong>and</strong> flstate" interchangeably.<br />

(2)<strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>, The Free <strong>and</strong> Prosperous<br />

Commonwealth: An Exposition of the Ideas of Classical<br />

Liberalism (Princeton: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>, 1962), pp.<br />

26-37.<br />

(3) Dan i e 1 Guer in, Anarehism, From Theory to<br />

Practice (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1970), p. 12.<br />

(4)Max Adler, "Max Stirner," Encyclopedia of the<br />

Soc i a I Sci en c e s (N e w Yo r k: Ma cm illan, 1948), v0 I. 14,<br />

p. 393. Also see George Woodcock, "Anarchism,"<br />

Encyclopedia of Philosophy (New York: Macmillan,<br />

19 6 7 ), v 0 I. 1, P p. 111- 14 , <strong>and</strong> e s pecia I 1Y P • 11 3 wh ere<br />

Stirner is described as being on the "dubious fringe" of<br />

anarchism.<br />

(5) Pet er Kropotkin, "Anarchist Communism," The New<br />

Encyclopedia of Social Reform, eds. William Bliss <strong>and</strong><br />

Rudolph Binder (New York: 1908), p. 47.<br />

(6)George Woodcock, Anarchism, A History of<br />

Libertarian Ideas <strong>and</strong> Movements (Clevel<strong>and</strong>: Meridian<br />

Books, 1969), pp.163 <strong>and</strong> 204.<br />

(7)William Morris, News Prom Nowhere (London:<br />

1891).<br />

(8)Mikhail Bakunin, "<strong>State</strong>less Socialism:<br />

Anarchism," The Pol i tiealPh i losophY 0 f Ba kun in, ed •<br />

G. P. Maximoff (New York: Free Press, 1953), pp. 298-99.<br />

Also see Woodcock, A History, p. 164.<br />

(9)Pierre Joseph Proudhon, "What is Property?",<br />

Socialist Thought, eds. Albert Fried <strong>and</strong> Ronald<br />

San d e r s (N ew Yo r k: Do ubI e day, 1964), p. 202; <strong>and</strong><br />

Woodcock, Anarchism, A History, p. 129.<br />

(10)William Godwin, Enquiry Concerning Political<br />

Justice (Middlesex, Engl<strong>and</strong>: Penguin, 1976), p. 705.<br />

(11)Benjamin Tucker, "<strong>State</strong> Socialism <strong>and</strong><br />

38


ma j 0 r rep res en tat i v e fig u res 0 f each a narchis t type.<br />

Thus only Kropotkinwas dealt wi·th here. However, Leo<br />

Tolstoy <strong>and</strong> Paul Goodman could also be classified as<br />

"anarcho-communists." For 8 good summary of Tolstoy's<br />

views see Eltzbacher, pp. 149-81. Also see Paul <strong>and</strong><br />

Percival Goodman, Communitas (New York: Vintage,<br />

1960). On the simi larities between Kropotkin <strong>and</strong> Paul<br />

Goodman see William Merill Downer, "Kropotkin in<br />

America: Paul Goodman'S Adaptation of the Communitarian<br />

Anarchism of Peter Kropotki.n" (Paper presented .at the<br />

1977 Midwest Political Science Convention, April, 1977).<br />

Also in the Kropotkinian tradition is Murray Bookchin.<br />

See his The Limits of the City (New York: Harper,<br />

1974). .<br />

(23)Mikhail 8akunin, "On the Morrow of the Social<br />

Revolution," The Political Philosophy of Batunin, ed.<br />

G.P. Maximoff (New York: Free Press, 1953), p. 410.<br />

( 2 4 ) Jam e s Gu i I I a ume, " 0 n Bu i I ding the New Soc i a I<br />

Order," Bakun in on Anarchy, ed. Sam Dolgoff (New York:<br />

Al fred A. Knopf, 1971), p. 360.<br />

(25)Woodcock, Anarchism, A History, p. 164.<br />

Witness Bakunin's remark that "any persons who, though<br />

robust <strong>and</strong> of good heal th, do not want to gain their<br />

livelihood by working shall have the right to starve<br />

themselves to death. ""On the Morrow of the Social<br />

Revolution," p. 412.<br />

(26)According to Bakunin, the collectives will form<br />

themselves into federations, the federations into regions,<br />

the regions into nations <strong>and</strong>, ultimately, the nat<br />

ions into what he terms an "international fraternal<br />

association." See Bakunin, "<strong>State</strong>less Socialism:<br />

Anarchism," p. 298.<br />

(27)Guillaume, p. 366.<br />

(28)lbid., p. 368.<br />

(29)lt should be pointed out that the anarchosyndicalist,<br />

Rudolph Rocker, explicitly repudiates Sorel<br />

<strong>and</strong> maintains that Sorel neither "belonged to the movement,<br />

nor had ••• any appreciable influence on its internal<br />

development." See Rudolf Rocker, "Anarchism <strong>and</strong><br />

Anarc h 0 - 5 Yn d i c a lis m," a p pen d i x toPa u I E I t z bacher,<br />

Anarchism (New York: Chips, n.d.), p. 250 •.<br />

( 30 ) Ge 0 r g e SoreI, Ref 1 e c t ions 0 n Vi olence (N ew<br />

York: Doubleday, 1941), p. 294.<br />

(31 )See Mul ford Sibley, Political Ideas <strong>and</strong><br />

Ideologies (New York: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1970), p. 547.<br />

(32)Rocker, pp. 253-55.<br />

(33)Emma Goldman, "Syndicalism," Liberty <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Grea t Lib e r tar ians, e d. C h a r I e sSp r a din g ( New Yo r k :<br />

Arno Press, 1972), p. 507. Also see the quotation of<br />

H ins in Rocke r, p. 247.<br />

40


Paul, "Anarchism <strong>and</strong> Natural Rights" (Paper Presented at<br />

the Associat ion for the Philosophic Study of <strong>Society</strong>,<br />

October 6, 1977).<br />

(62)David Friedman is one of the few individualist<br />

anarchists to recognize the distinction between libertar<br />

ian ism <strong>and</strong> a narchism, <strong>and</strong> he ext ricates hims elf from<br />

this possible dilemma by refusing to classify himself as<br />

ali b e r tar ian • See his The Machi n e r y 0 f Preedom (New<br />

York: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1913),pp. 173-78.<br />

(63)John Hospers, "What Libertarianism Is," The<br />

Libertarian Alternative, ed. Tibor Machan (Chicago:<br />

Ne I son- Ha 11, 1974), p. 13.<br />

( 6 4 ) I b i·d ., P p. 7 - 8.; a n· d H 0 S per s ,<br />

Libertarianism, pp. 61-62.<br />

(65)Hospers, Libertarianism, p. 386-87.<br />

(66)John Hospers, "Rothbard's Free-Market Justice,"<br />

p. 21. (67)Ibid.<br />

(68)Hospers, Libertarianism, p. 387.<br />

( 69 ) H0 s per s, " Rot h bard's F r e e -Ma r ke t Jus tice ," p.<br />

21.<br />

(70)See, for example, Max Weber, Law in Economy<br />

<strong>and</strong> Soc i e t y, e d. Ma x Rh e ins t e i n ( New Yo r k: S im0 n<strong>and</strong><br />

Schuster, 1954), pp. 338-39.<br />

(71)lt would certainly be stretching the point to<br />

maintain that the fee would be voluntary since consumers<br />

could forego purchasing protection altogether, <strong>and</strong> those<br />

providing protection could enter a new line of work, if<br />

either objected to the fee. This is tantamount to arguing<br />

that the obligation to pay income tax is "voluntarily"<br />

assumed when the individual "chooses" to earn a<br />

living.<br />

(72)Robert Nozick, Anarchy, <strong>State</strong> <strong>and</strong> Utopia (New<br />

York: Basic Books, 1974), pp. 15-26.<br />

( 73) Ibid., pp. 110-13.<br />

( 74) I bid., pp. 33-5 •<br />

(75)Ibid., p. 156.<br />

(76')See ibid., pp. 22-25.<br />

( 77 ) I bid., p • 109 • ( em phas isin 0 rig ina 1 ) •<br />

(7S)See John S<strong>and</strong>ers, "The Free Market Model Versus<br />

Government: A Reply to Nozick," The Journal of<br />

. Libertarian Studies (Winter 1977), pp.' 35-44.<br />

(79)Nozick, p. liS.<br />

(SO)Roy Childs, "The Invisible H<strong>and</strong> Strikes Back,"<br />

The Journal of Libertarian Studies (Winter 1977), pp.<br />

23-33. ( 8 1 ) Her b e r t S pen c e r, Soc i a 1Sta ties ( New Yo r k: D.<br />

Appleton, 1892), p. 125.<br />

(82)Herbert Spencer, The Right to Ignorelhe<br />

<strong>State</strong> (Cupertino, Cal.: Caymen Press, 1973), p. 5.<br />

43


aut h 0 r 's Ene m i e s 0 f the Per man en t T h i n g s (N ew<br />

Rochelle: Arlington House, 1969)•.<br />

(111 )James Burnham, Suicide of the West (New<br />

Rochelle: Arlington House, 1964), pp. 290-91.<br />

(112) Ibid., p. 288.<br />

(113)L. T. Sargent, Contemporary<br />

Political Ideologies (Homewood, Ill.: Dorsey Press,<br />

1972), p. 99.<br />

(114)Kirk, Enemies, p. 282.<br />

(115 )Burnham, p. 139.<br />

( 11 6 ) " Co n s e r vat i v e s res pee t the wi s d om of the i r<br />

ancestors ••• They think society is a spiritual reality,<br />

possessing an eternal life but a delicate constitution:<br />

it cannot be scrapped <strong>and</strong> recast as if it were a<br />

machine." Kirk, The Conservative Mind, p. 6.<br />

(117)For analyses that point out the authoritarianism<br />

0 f con s e r vat ism see Ed i thEf fron, f1 Cons e r vat ism: A<br />

Libertarian Challenge," The Alternative (October<br />

1975), pp. 9-13; Murray Rothbard, "Conservatism <strong>and</strong><br />

<strong>Freedom</strong>: A Libertar ian Comment," Modern Age (Spring<br />

1961), pp. 217-20; Murray Rothbard, "Confessions of a<br />

Right-Wing Liberal," Ramparts (June 15, 1968), pp.<br />

4 7 - 5 2.• The con t em p 0 r a r y soc i 0 log is t, Ro be r t Ni s bet ,<br />

sees as least the traditional conservatism of Burke,<br />

Lemmenais <strong>and</strong> DeBonald not only as highly pluralistic<br />

but as a bulwark against political centralization <strong>and</strong><br />

the authoritarian state. See his "Conservatism <strong>and</strong><br />

Libertarians: UneaSy Cousins," Modern Age (Winter<br />

1980), pp. 2-8; "Conservatism <strong>and</strong> Sociology," The<br />

American Journal of Sociology (September 1952), pp.<br />

167-75; <strong>and</strong> "DeBonald <strong>and</strong> the Concept of the Social<br />

Group," Journal of the History of Ideas (June 1944),<br />

pp. 315-31. In emphasizing the role that the "social<br />

group" <strong>and</strong> tradition played in impeding the growth of<br />

centralized power, Nisbet has highlighted an important<br />

<strong>and</strong> un jus t I Y neg1e c ted aspe c t 0 f cons e r vat ism .' But t his<br />

st i 11 doesn't negate the authoritarian streak in much of<br />

conservative, particularly modern conservative, thought.<br />

(118)Two things should be mentioned regarding the<br />

"political spectrum." First, it might be argued that<br />

thereisan i n v e r s ere 1a t ions hip betweenthe e con om i c<br />

<strong>and</strong> political spheres -- as one increases the other must<br />

decrease -- so that both spectrums are merely measures<br />

of the same things. This, however, not only overlooks<br />

the I a r ge bodY 0 f tho ugh t t hat f eItthat the rever s e wa s<br />

true -- that the market presupposed a highly interventionist<br />

<strong>and</strong> authoritarian state -- Marx, for example,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Kropotk in -- but also ignores that group which desired<br />

neither the market nor the state -- Kropotkin,<br />

Bakunin <strong>and</strong> Berkman, to name just a few. It seems to me<br />

46


PART ONE<br />

The Individualist Anarchist.<br />

Critique 01 Government<br />

T he b u 1 k 0 f t his stud Y f 0 c use s on the i nd i v i d ua 1ist<br />

anarchist alternative to the state. But before one<br />

can deal meaningfully with that question it must first<br />

be asked why should one be concerned with an alfernat<br />

i vet 0 the s tate a t a II ? Whatis i t about the na t ur e<br />

oft hestate t hat rna kesit anin t r ins i cal I y dange r 0 us<br />

or aggressive institution?<br />

Chap t e r s I I, I I I, <strong>and</strong> I V wi I 1 a t t em pt to dea 1 wit h<br />

the individualist anarchist response to that question,<br />

the reb y I a yin g the g r 0 u n dw0 r k for Par t Two 0 f t his<br />

study: the development of a positive alternative to<br />

the state.<br />

49


power s 0 f go ver nme n t can be rna de as Iongas soc i e t y i s<br />

divided into two hostile camps <strong>and</strong> the laborer is, econom<br />

i cally s peaking, a s 1a vet0 his emp loye r. • •Butin<br />

a society where the distinction between capitalist <strong>and</strong><br />

laborer has disappeared, there is no need of such a<br />

go v ernmen t • • The no - capitalis t s Ystem imp 1 iesthe<br />

no-government system."(4) And Berkman says that "when<br />

government is abol ished, wage slavery <strong>and</strong> capitalism<br />

must also go with it, because they cannot exist without<br />

the support <strong>and</strong> protection of government."(5) Thus the<br />

collectivist anarchist believes that private property<br />

i$ a form of coercion <strong>and</strong> can exist only when supported<br />

by t he power of the sta tee The abol it ion of government<br />

is therefore the means to the abolition of private<br />

property.<br />

The individualist anarchist,on the other h<strong>and</strong>,<br />

argues that while the premise is correct the conclusion<br />

doe S not n e c e s s a r i I Y f 0 I 1ow • From the cognit ion t hat<br />

government uses its force to protect the interests of<br />

the property-owning class, it does not follow that property<br />

rights, themselves, are coercive.(6) Rather, he<br />

not only contends that [1] in the absence of property<br />

rights there can be no rights at all, but also that [2]<br />

far from"upholding property rights, a$ contended by the<br />

collect ivist anarchist, the state. by its very nature,<br />

is the single greatest violator of these rights.<br />

The i n d i v i d uali s tanarchis t reas ons as follows.<br />

That individual (or group) who is able to determine how<br />

a good will be utilized is the actual owner. regardless<br />

of the legal fictions to the contrary. Sociologically.<br />

own e r s hip i s the a b iIi t y to rna ke the determ i n i ng dec i ­<br />

sions regarding the disposition of property.(7) It is<br />

clear that it is impossible to eliminate ownership in<br />

the sociological sense of the term, for decisions conc<br />

ern i n g the use 0 f properties havet0 be rna de i n ever y<br />

society. Whoever makes these decisions is the owner.<br />

From th i s cogn it i on the individual ist anarchist concludes<br />

that if an individual is not permitted to retain<br />

what he has earned, i.e., either produced himself or<br />

obtained by means of voluntary exchange, his life is<br />

dependent upon whoever determines the disposition of<br />

pro per t y • Reg a r die s s 0 f wh e the r s uc h de t e r mina t ion s<br />

are made by a single individual--a tyrant, a group of<br />

individuals--an oligarchy, or a majority--a democaracy,<br />

such "human rights" 8S those of freedom of speech, assembly,<br />

religion, etc., are. if not meaningless, at<br />

least perpetually precarious, for the individual cannot<br />

a f for d t 0 inc u r the dis pIeas ureof thos e wh 0 hoI d his<br />

52


promptly proceeded "to destroy private property with<br />

force." The result ,as is well' know, was n the revival<br />

of despotism in Russia."(9)<br />

The anarcho-collectivist might well agree with the<br />

thrust of the abo vear gum e ntbutar gue t hat libe r t y<br />

would be secure in his society since, according to<br />

Kropotkin, there will be "common possession of the necessaries<br />

for production" <strong>and</strong> all decis'ions will be "the<br />

work of all, ••• a product of the constructive genius<br />

of the great mass."(lO) The individualist anarchist<br />

would contend, however, that such an arrangement does<br />

not materially alter the validity of his ar,gument, for<br />

a n unp 0 p u 1a r 0 r non- con for ming min 0 r i t y rna y s t i 11 find<br />

i t se I f con fron ted wit h the c hoi c e of ei the r con for ming<br />

or starving.<br />

The colle ct· i vi s t - a n arc hi s t , he bel i eve s , has<br />

placed himself in two serious dilemmas. First, while<br />

he proclaims himself to be an advocate of individual<br />

autonomy, i.e., the right of every individual to the<br />

"free development of all his faculties," he believes<br />

that this entails the liberation from private property.<br />

But if the individual is not permitted to own what he<br />

has produced then he becomes dependent upon "society,"<br />

thereby losing his autonomy. But if he is permitted to<br />

own the fruits of his labor then private property is<br />

admitted. In short, the individualist anarchist believes<br />

that autonomy <strong>and</strong> collectivism are mutually contradictory.(11)(12)<br />

Second, the anarcho-collectivist<br />

is opposed to all forms of coercion. But what if some<br />

individuals decide they would like to retain what they<br />

have produced <strong>and</strong> either consume it themselves or eng<br />

8 ge i n v 0 I u n tar y exchange? I f the a narch0 - col I e c t i vists<br />

would permit this, they would be permitting privat<br />

e pro per t y • But i f they wo u 1d ref use tope r mit it,<br />

they would be in i t iat ing the use of force, or the<br />

threat of its use, in order to prohibit non-aggressive<br />

act ion s, i. e ., the y wo u I d been gag i n gin coercion.<br />

Thus the individualist anarchist also concludes that a<br />

society cannot be both collectivist <strong>and</strong> free at the<br />

same time.(13)<br />

The individualist anarchist goes even further,<br />

however, <strong>and</strong> contends not only that there can be no<br />

liberty without property rights but that there are no<br />

rights other than property rights. Rothbard, for example,<br />

argues that "there is no such thing as separate<br />

'r ight to free speech'; there is only a man's property<br />

right: the right to do as he wills with his own or make<br />

54


ish." Second, it is argued that "It is physically imp<br />

0 s sib I e for eve r yone t 0 ke e peontin ua I tabson eve r yone<br />

else <strong>and</strong> thereby to exercise his equal quotal share<br />

o f par t 1 a lown e r h sip 0 vereve r y 0 ther rna n . I n pr a ctice,<br />

then, any attempt to institute universal <strong>and</strong><br />

equal other-ownership is utopian <strong>and</strong> impossible, <strong>and</strong><br />

sup e r vis ion <strong>and</strong>, t·her e f or e , con t r 0 I <strong>and</strong> own e r s hip 0 f<br />

others would necessarily devolve upon specialized<br />

groups of people who would thereby-become a 'rUling<br />

class.' Hence, in practice, any attempt at Communist<br />

society will automatically become class rule, <strong>and</strong> we<br />

would be back at our rejected first alternative."(19)<br />

To summarize, most individualist anarchists adopt<br />

a Lockean natural rights posItion. They then proceed<br />

to. argue that [1] if one accepts the premise of selfownership<br />

there is no alternative to recognition of<br />

private property, <strong>and</strong> [2] if one rejects the premise<br />

then one must adopt the view that (a) A has a right to<br />

own himself as well as B, while B is denied any right<br />

of ownership, or (b) that everyone can own everyone<br />

e I s e but i s den i edther i gh t to own hims elf. Bothof<br />

the s e posit ion s, he fee Is, are s elf - con t r ad i c tor y •<br />

Hence the only logically consistent position is that of<br />

t he L 0 c k e a n p r inc i pIe s 0 f (a) s elf - own e f s hip <strong>and</strong> (b)<br />

its corollary, the fIght to retain the fruits of one's<br />

labor.<br />

2. THE DEFENSE OF PR I VATE PROPERTY: NATURAL RIGHTS<br />

VERSUS UTILITARIANISM<br />

The f act t hat the for ego i ng a na I ysis rna y show t hat<br />

the alternatives to prIvate property are logically contradictory<br />

<strong>and</strong>/or lead to consequences that everyone<br />

considers disastrous does not, in itself, morally validate<br />

private property. What, then, is the individualist<br />

anarchist's ethical defense of property rights?<br />

Free market anarchism is composed of two divergent<br />

f act ion s. The d om ina n t f act Ion i s t he Rot hbar d iananarchists,<br />

which adopts a "natural rights" defense of<br />

pro p.e r t y; the com pet i n g f act ion i s the F r i e drna nit ea<br />

n arc his t s, wh i c h de f e n.d s pro per t y on "util ita ria n"<br />

grounds. The latter will be dealt with first.<br />

Like the philosophical anarchist Benjamin Tucker<br />

before him, David Friedman believes that an anarchist<br />

society will protect private property not because it IS<br />

a natural or human right but because it is useful.<br />

56


<strong>Freedom</strong>, he says, "is efficient--the value to me of<br />

being able to order you around IS rarely as great as<br />

the cos t toy 0 u 0 f be i n g 0 r dered a r 0 un d • Go i ng from<br />

coercive to libertarian law is on net profitable, so a<br />

system which produces law for profit will rarely produce<br />

coercive laws. t1 (20·) While the natural rights<br />

anarchist believes that laws against drugs, pornography,<br />

prostitution, <strong>and</strong> the like, are immoral, Friedman<br />

see s not h i n gin her e n t I Y wron g wit h them. Un d e r his<br />

utilitarian-anarchism laws would be produced on the<br />

market. And if those laws are what people want, that<br />

is what the market will produce. He is confident,<br />

however, that such laws would be the exception; that<br />

because of its social utility, an anarchist society<br />

would be biased toward freedom.(21) ,<br />

An ex c e I I en t c r i tic ism of uti I i tar i an ism has been<br />

prov ided by Murray Rothbard. The ut iIi tar ian, he<br />

notes, must regard the laissez (aire principles of<br />

self-ownership <strong>and</strong> property ownership not as an "absolute<br />

<strong>and</strong> consistent yardstick," but simply as a tendenc<br />

y 0 r r u leo f t h urn b t hat the rna j 0 r 1 t Y i s f r e e toove r ­<br />

rIde at will. Consequently, Rothbard hypothesizes,<br />

suppose that the majority "considers all redheads to be<br />

agents of the Devil <strong>and</strong> therefore to be executed whenever<br />

found. Let us further assume that only a small<br />

number of redheads exist In any generation•.. The<br />

utilitarian libertarian might well reason: 'While the<br />

murder of isolated redheads is deplorable, the execut<br />

Ion s are sma I lin n urn b e r; the vas t rna j 0 r i t Y 0 f the<br />

pub I 1 c • . a chi evesen 0 r m0 us ps y chi c sat i s fa c t Ion from<br />

the pub 1 icex e cut ion 0 f red hea ds • The soc i a 1 costis<br />

negligible, the social, psychic benefit to the rest of<br />

society is great; therefore, it is right <strong>and</strong> proper for<br />

society to execute redheads'."(22)<br />

I tis 1 ike 1 y t hat F r i e dma n wo u I d r e c 0 i 1 from s u c h<br />

a conclusion. Yet, he cannot logically reject it while<br />

remaining consistent with his utilitarianism. Clearly,<br />

utilitarianism provides only a shaky defense for the<br />

principles of self-ownership <strong>and</strong> private property.<br />

Murray Rothbard, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, has endeavored<br />

to defend these rights on ontological grounds. It<br />

s h 0 U 1 d b e a c k now 1 e d g ed, howe v e r, t hat the c losest he<br />

has come is in his book, The Ethics of Liberty.<br />

WhIle he does say "it is not the intentIon of this book<br />

to expound or defend at length the philosophy of natural<br />

law" but rather "to elaborate that subset of the<br />

57


natural law that develops the concept of natural<br />

rights,"(23) the principles from which his ontological<br />

defense would be derived are clearly presented in Part<br />

One of that manuscript.<br />

Rothbard begins by arguing that man, like all<br />

other ent i ties, must have a specific nature: " ••• if<br />

apples <strong>and</strong> stones <strong>and</strong> roses each have their specific<br />

natures," he asks, "is man the only' entity, the only<br />

bei n g, t hat can not h a v e one ? An d i f rna n doe s ha ve a<br />

nat u r e, why cannot itt00 be 0 pen tora t iona 1 obs e r vat<br />

ion a nd ref Ie c t ion? " He the n rna i n t a ins t hat sinc e<br />

"man's reason is objective, i.e., it can be employed<br />

to yield truths about the world," reason can' be used to<br />

study man <strong>and</strong> to ascertain what his nature really consists<br />

of. Once this is done it is possible, again<br />

t h r 0 ugh the use 0 f rea son, to de due e a na t urallaw<br />

ethic which, since it is grounded in man's nature, is<br />

valid for, <strong>and</strong> morally binding on, all men.<br />

Fol lowing the phenomenologist, John Wild, Rothbard<br />

equates virtue, or goodness, or value, with what Wild<br />

terms "the fulfillment of tendencies determined by the<br />

structure of the existent entity." Evil is defined as<br />

"that mode of existence in which natural tendencies are<br />

t hwar ted <strong>and</strong> d e p r i ved 0 f rea 1 i za t ion • " ( 24 ) Hen c e ma n<br />

is held to have a specific nature which is discoverable<br />

by man's reason <strong>and</strong> this discovery leads to the deduction<br />

of an ethic based on objective, absolute values.<br />

Act ion s t hat are inc 0 n formit y wit h rna n 's na t urear e<br />

'virtuous; those that are in conflict with it are evil.<br />

Inc 0 n t r a s t toecon om i c s, wh ere val ue s are t rea ted as<br />

subjective phenomena, Rothbard believes that natural<br />

law is able to demonstrate that there are moral<br />

values which are, in fact, "objective." "The natural<br />

law," he says, tIel ucidates what is best for man--what<br />

ends man should pursue that are most harmonious with,<br />

<strong>and</strong> bes t tend to fu 1fill, his nature." Since, as we<br />

have seen in the previous section, Rothbard believes<br />

that society, <strong>and</strong> even life itself, is impossible without<br />

recognition of self-ownership <strong>and</strong> private property,<br />

these are necessary to enable man to fulfill his<br />

nature.<br />

Rothbard's position can be formulated as follows:<br />

1. The behavior of any entity having a nature<br />

ought to be in accord with its nature.<br />

2. Man has a nature.<br />

3. Henc'e, man ought to act in accord with it.<br />

58


But as Arnold Brecht, among others, has noted,<br />

while there are no logical links between the is <strong>and</strong><br />

the ought, there may be factual or empirical links<br />

bet wee nthe two. ( 26 ) This dis tinc t ion i s rna dec I ear i n<br />

the following syllogisms:<br />

1.<br />

2.<br />

3.<br />

Syllogism A<br />

Man exists.<br />

Murder terminates<br />

that existence.<br />

Hence, murder is<br />

wrong.<br />

1.<br />

2.<br />

3.<br />

Syllogism B<br />

Man has a right to<br />

exist.<br />

Murder terminates that<br />

existence.<br />

Hen c e, mur d e r i s wr 0 ng •<br />

Syllogism C<br />

1. Fred believes that man has a right to exist.<br />

2. Murder violates that existence.<br />

3 • Hen ce, itis wr 0 ng for Fred tomur de r •<br />

I tis 0 b v i 0 u s t hat inS y 1 log ism A the norrna t i ve<br />

conclusion that one ought not to murder does not follow<br />

log i c a I I Y fro m the f act ualp rem isethat rna n ex i s t s •<br />

T h j sis a c 1 ear v i 0 I a t ion 0 f the i s - 0 ugh t d i c hot omy .<br />

It is at least conceivable that man should not exist,<br />

in which case murder would be morally good. The moral<br />

i n j u n c t ion not to. mu r d e r does f 0 I 1ow log i c a I I Y from<br />

its prem i s e inSy 1log ism B. The prob I em her e, tho ugh,<br />

is that of demonstrating the validity of the premise.<br />

Unless its val idi ty can be demonstrated it is nothing<br />

m0 ret han a n ass e r t ion wh i c h, even i f t rue, cannot be<br />

ver i f i ed. Thus, it has no more logical val idity than<br />

.its conve r s e : rna n has nor i g h t toexis t • Insy I log ism<br />

C, however, the conclusion that one ought not to murder<br />

a v 0 ids bot h 0 f thesediff i cuI ties : ( a ) the mo ralinjunction<br />

follows logically from the premise <strong>and</strong> (b) the<br />

prem i s e has a f act u a lor em p i rica 1 s tat us wh i chi s<br />

capable of verification (or falsification).<br />

I believe that the Rothbardian position can be reformulated<br />

after the fashion of Syllogism C. This can<br />

be done, moreover, in a way which enables it both (a)<br />

to meet the problem of the is-ought dichotomy while (b)<br />

sti 11 keeping its comprehensive scope virtually intact.<br />

The reformulation would read as follows:<br />

1. If one values life more highly than death<br />

then he ought to adopt measures to sustain<br />

I i f e.<br />

2. Self-ownership <strong>and</strong> property ownership are<br />

necessary to sustain life.<br />

3. Everyone wants to live.<br />

60


e it he r on his own proper ty or on the proper ty of someone<br />

who has agreed, as a gift or in a rental contract,<br />

t 0 a 1 low him 0 nth e prem i s e s • n C1ear I y, any leg i s I a ­<br />

tion intended either to extend or restrict this scope<br />

of free speech would be a violation of property rights.<br />

S i mil a r 1y, wit h t he n righ t of as semb I y tt : " I f a I I ownership<br />

were private, it would be quite clear that the<br />

cit izens did not have any nebulous 'right of assembly.'<br />

The i r rig h t wo u 1d bethe proper t y righ t 0 f us i ng the i r<br />

money inan effort to buy or rent space on which to<br />

make their demonstration, <strong>and</strong> they could do so only if<br />

the owner of the street agreed to the deal."(30)<br />

Rothbard then proceeds to apply his universal private<br />

ownership approach to Just ice Holmes' argument that<br />

rights cannot be absolute since they must be balanced<br />

against the "common good"; that one does not have, for<br />

instance, a right to yell "fire" in a crowded theater.<br />

The trouble with Holmes' position, he says, is that<br />

there is neither a right to free speech nor a "public<br />

good." I t is therefore imposs i ble to 1 imi t one for the<br />

sake of the other. Instead, the individualist anarchist<br />

reasons as follows. The person yelling "fire"<br />

must be either (a) the owner, (b) a guest of the owner,<br />

or (c) a paying customer. If it is the owner then he<br />

has commit ted f r a ud up 0 n his c us t om e r s by t a king the i r<br />

money in exchange for the promise of showing a motion<br />

picture, but instead disrupts the performance by his<br />

action. "He has thus willfully defaulted on his contractual<br />

obligations <strong>and</strong> has therefore violated the<br />

pro per t y rig h t S 0 f his pa t ron s • " Ifit we r e e i the r a<br />

patron or a guest who yelled, then that person has viol<br />

ate d the 0 b I ig a t ion t 0 res pee t t he owner' s proper t y<br />

rights as well as those of the customers who have paid<br />

to see the performance, <strong>and</strong> must therefore make restit<br />

uti 0 n tot h e vic tim s • " The per son wh 0 rna 1 i c i 0 usly<br />

cries 'fire' in a crowded theater, therefore, is a<br />

criminal, not because his so-called 'right of free<br />

s pee c h ,. mu s t b e p r a gma ticall y res t ricted 0 n beha I f 0 f<br />

the s 0 - c a lIe d 'pubI i c good' but be c a use he has c 1e 8 r 1y<br />

<strong>and</strong> obviously violated the property rights of another<br />

human being. There is no need, therefore, to place<br />

limits upon these rights."(31)<br />

We are now in a position to underst<strong>and</strong> the individualist<br />

anarchist's belief that "the <strong>State</strong> has always<br />

beenth e g rea ten em y <strong>and</strong> in va de r 0 f the righ t s 0 f p r i ­<br />

vate property."(32) In contradistinction to the collectivist<br />

anarchists, the individualist anarchists argue<br />

that by its very nature it is impossible for the<br />

state to exist without violating property rights, <strong>and</strong><br />

63


In brief, in contrast to the collectivist anarchi<br />

s t, the i n d i v i d ua listanarchis t rna i n t a ins t hat the<br />

state is an aggressive institution because it entails<br />

the violation of property rights, not because it upholds<br />

them. And, contrary to the libertarian-rninarchist,<br />

he holds that this violation inheres in the<br />

nature of the state, rather than being incidental to<br />

it. (40 )<br />

Wit h t his i n rn i n d the view t hat the s tat e· isan<br />

institution which violates property rights by its<br />

pro tee t ion 0 f the i n t e r es t s 0 f the p r ope r t y- own i ng<br />

groups becomes intelligible.<br />

66


FOOTNOTES<br />

{I )Alex<strong>and</strong>er Berkman, ABC of Anarchism (London:<br />

<strong>Freedom</strong> Press, 1973), p. 9.<br />

(2 )Peter Kropotkin, "Law, the Supporter of Crime,"<br />

Patterns of Anarchy, eds. Leonard Krimmerman <strong>and</strong><br />

Lew i s Per r y ( New Y0 r k : Do ubI e day <strong>and</strong> Co., 19 68 ), p •<br />

292.<br />

(3)Peter Kropotkin, The Conquest of Bread (New<br />

York: Benjamin Bloom, 1968),p. 18; Berkman,pp. 74-75.<br />

(4)Peter Kropotkin, "A Scientific Approach to<br />

Com m u n i s t Ana r chi s m," Pat terns of An arc h y, e d s •<br />

Leonard Krimmerman <strong>and</strong> Lewis Perry (New York: Doubleday<br />

<strong>and</strong> Co'., 1968), p. 226. .<br />

( 5) Be r kma n, p. 31.<br />

(6)Richard <strong>and</strong> Ernestine Perkins, Precondition for<br />

Peace <strong>and</strong> Prosperity: Rational Anarchy (Ontario:<br />

Private Publication, 1971), p. 9.<br />

( 7 ) L u dwig <strong>von</strong> Mis e s, Soc i ali s m ( London: J. Cape ,<br />

1969), pp. 37-42. And Murray Rothbard, Power <strong>and</strong><br />

Market (Menlo Park, Calif.: <strong>Institute</strong> for Humane<br />

Studies, Inc., 1970), p. 139.<br />

(8)Friedrich A. Hayek, The Road to' Serfdom<br />

(Chicago: Phoenix Books, 1967). See especially Chapter<br />

Ten, "Why the Worst Get on Top," pp. 134-52. For a<br />

reply to Hayek see Herman Finer, The Road to Reaction<br />

( B 0 s ton: Lit tie, Brownan d Co., 1945). Wh i Ie Hayek<br />

sees corruption <strong>and</strong> the abuse of power as endemic to<br />

po lit i cs, Finer sees them as largely a funct ion of \he<br />

type of political order <strong>and</strong>, in a democracy at least,<br />

the ex c e p t ion rat her t han the r u Ie. Robe r t Ni s be t ,<br />

however, has recently advanced the interesting proposition<br />

that, if anything, these things would occur with<br />

greater regUlarity in a democracy than in other political<br />

orders: "Democracy, with its tacit responsibility<br />

to the electorate, with its accountability in some deg<br />

r e e to leg i s I a t u res, pre s s, <strong>and</strong> pub 1 i c, ca r r i e s a<br />

larger 'potential for deception than is likely in other<br />

forms of government simply by virtue of this accountabiii<br />

t Y • " The Tw iIi g h t 0 f Aut h 0 r i t Y (N ew Yo r k: Ox ford<br />

University Press, 1975), p. 17. Regardless of whether<br />

one subscribes to the Hayekian <strong>and</strong> Finerian explanation<br />

of political corruption <strong>and</strong> abuse of power, empirical<br />

documentat ion of these phenomena in this country is<br />

certainly abundant. Watergate, of course, comes first<br />

to mind. Of the legions of books now written on the<br />

sub j e c t, The 0 d 0 r e Whit e 's The Brea c h 0 f Fa i t h ( New<br />

York: Dell, 1975) is the most balanced <strong>and</strong> reflective<br />

t 0 a p pea r t h u s far. Someat t em ptis now be i ng rna d e to<br />

place Watergate in historical perspective. Jarol<br />

67


Mannhelm's Deja Vu (New York: St. Martin's Press,<br />

1 9 7 6) com par esit wit h the C r 'e d i t Mob iIi e r s ca nda I<br />

d uri n g the Gran tAdmin i s t rat ion <strong>and</strong> the Teapot Dom e<br />

S can d a 1 un d e r Ha r din g . The parail e 1s be tween Tea po t<br />

Dome <strong>and</strong> Watergate are especially striking. Also<br />

noteworthy is Victor Lasky's It Didn't Start With<br />

Watergate (New York: Dell, 1977) <strong>and</strong> David Wise's The<br />

Politics of Lying (New York: Vintage, 1973). Both<br />

chronicle the extensive Watergate-like activities in<br />

every administration from Franklin Roosevelt tD Lyndon<br />

Johnson. Also valuable are Michael Dorman's Dirty<br />

Poli tics From 1776 to Watergate (New York: Delacorte,<br />

1979), <strong>and</strong> Morton Halperin, et.al., The Lawless <strong>State</strong><br />

(New York: Penguin, 1976). Lest one think that such<br />

activities are confIned to America, see John Barron,<br />

KGB (New York: Bantam, 1974). And one should not<br />

forget that it was precisely the rampant corruption in<br />

the sixteenth century Italian city-states that prompted<br />

Machiavelli to write The Prince. See George Sabine,<br />

A His tor y 0 f Pol i tica 1 The0 r y (N ew Yo r k: Hen r y HoI t ,<br />

1947), pp. 337-38. Finally, the interested reader<br />

should consult Harry Elmer Barnes' (ed.), Perpetual<br />

War For Per pet ualPe ace (Ca I d weI I: Ca x ton, 19 5 3 ) ,<br />

WhICh presents an unorthodox interpretation of<br />

America's entry into World War II. If correct, thIS<br />

would certainly make the aetions of Franklin Roosevelt<br />

the most serious abuse of power in US history.<br />

(9)Alfred Cuzan, "Political Profit: TaXIng <strong>and</strong><br />

Spending in Dictatorships <strong>and</strong> Democracies," American<br />

J 0 urn a 1 0 f E conom i cs<strong>and</strong> Soc i 01 0 gy ( 0 c t 0 be r 19 81 ), pp •<br />

329-40.<br />

(lO)Kropotkin, "A Scientific Approach," pp. 227 <strong>and</strong><br />

230.<br />

(11)See, for example, the argument by the individ<br />

u a lis tanarchis t, J 0 hn Hen r y McKay, "Comm un is t s Ca nnot<br />

be Anarchists;" Patterns of Anarchy, eds. Leonard<br />

Krimmerman <strong>and</strong> Lewis Perry (New York: DOUbleday, 1968),<br />

p. 31.<br />

(12)Since individuals can own property they certainly<br />

have every right to divest themselves of it <strong>and</strong><br />

voluntarily form a communal society if they so desire.<br />

However, such a society is a result of the voluntary<br />

contributions of each individual's personal property,<br />

<strong>and</strong> as such it is st i 11 based on the recognition of<br />

pr iva t e pr operty. Any member, of course, could therefore<br />

withdraw from that arrangement any time he<br />

des ired. See my "Notes Toward Underst<strong>and</strong>ing Capitalism<br />

<strong>and</strong> Socialism," The Alternative (October 1972), p.<br />

21 • (13)Murray Rothbard, "Anarcho-Communism,"<br />

68


Egalitarianism As A Revolt Against Nature. <strong>and</strong> Other<br />

Essays (Washington, D.C.: Libertarian Review Press,<br />

1974), p. 121-24.<br />

(14 )Rothbard, Power <strong>and</strong> Market, p. 176. Also see<br />

Morris <strong>and</strong> Linda Tannehill, The Market for Liberty<br />

( Lansing, Mi c h .: P r i va t e Pub I i cat i on, 19 70 ), pp • 60 - 64 •<br />

(15}The only exception is that of David Friedman<br />

who, like his father Milton, is a utilitarian. See<br />

Da v i d F r i e dman, The Mac h i n e r y 0 f F r e e d om ( New Yo r k :<br />

Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1973).<br />

( 1 6 ) J 0 h n L 0 c k e ,Of C i viI Go v er n men t. Sec 0 n d<br />

T rea tise(Chi c ago : Henry Reg n e r y, 1968), p. 22 • It<br />

should be noted at this juncture that Locke did put two<br />

1 imi tat ions on the right of ·property: scarcity <strong>and</strong><br />

spoi lage. Man can, by his labor, remove property from<br />

the common stock provided "there is enough, <strong>and</strong> as good<br />

left in common for others." Locke, himself, however,<br />

does not seem to feel that this isa serious restriction,<br />

for later he expressly states that "Nature <strong>and</strong><br />

the earth furnished only the almost worthless materials<br />

as in themselves," <strong>and</strong> that "the property of labor<br />

should be able to overbalance the community of l<strong>and</strong>.<br />

For it is labor indeed that puts the difference of<br />

value on everything" (pp. 32-35). And elsewhere he<br />

acknowledges that private property so facilitates produe<br />

t ion a s t 0 I e a verno r e, not I e s s, for ever yoneel s e<br />

(p. 29). As for spoilage, Locke's original position is<br />

that since "Nothing was made by God for man to spoil or<br />

destroy" no one has a right to accumulate more than he<br />

can use wit h0 u t wa s t e· (p. 25 ) • Yet, he I ate r says t hat<br />

"t he in ven t i on of money••• introduced larger possess<br />

ions<strong>and</strong>ar i g h t tothem" ( p. 29) • Itis theref 0 rea t<br />

least arguable that Locke's limitations on property do<br />

not really constitute limitations at all.<br />

At any rate, the individualist anarchists feel that<br />

the essence of the Lockean doctrine is its justification<br />

of private property as a "natural right." For<br />

t hat r e'a son, wh eneveranyon e inthiss t ud Y i s referr e d<br />

to asaL0 eke an - nat u r aIr i g h t s the 0 r istit wi 11 be<br />

meant in this sense, i.e., that every man has a natural<br />

right to his own body <strong>and</strong> by extension to the fruits of<br />

his own labor.<br />

(·17 ) AYn Ra n d, "Ma n 's Rig h t s ," Capitali s m : the<br />

Unknown Ideal, ed. Ayn R<strong>and</strong> (New York: Signet Books,<br />

1967), p. 322.<br />

(18)Murray Rothbard, "Justice <strong>and</strong> Property Rights,"<br />

Egalitarianism As A Revolt Against Nature, <strong>and</strong> Other<br />

E s say s (We s h i n g ton, D. C.: Lib e r tar ian Rev i ew Pr e s s ,<br />

1974), p. 59.<br />

(19)Ibid., pp. 59-60.<br />

69


(20)David Friedman, "The Anarchist Reply," Reason<br />

(August 1976), p. 37. Also see his Machinery of<br />

<strong>Freedom</strong>, pp. 173-78.<br />

(21)Even though he speaks of "natural rights,"<br />

Gilbert Harmon subscribes to a utilitarian position<br />

similar to Friedman's when he speaks of rights as<br />

g r 0 un d e din ff con v en t ion" <strong>and</strong> be i n g the 0 u t come 0 f<br />

"implicit bargaining" among individuals of varying<br />

strengths. See his "Moral Relativism as a Foundation<br />

for Natural Rights," The Journal of Libertarian<br />

Studies (Fall 1980) pp. 367-72. A very interesting<br />

<strong>and</strong> far more elaborate defense of property rights by a<br />

ut il i tar ian can be found in James Buchanan, The Limits<br />

of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chic'ago Press,<br />

1975). Although Buchanan has on occasion referred to<br />

himself as a "philosophical anarchist" he is more<br />

accurately placed in the minarchist camp with Robert<br />

Nozick. While Nozick relies heavily on Locke, Buchanan<br />

is essentially a Hobbesian. For a provocative synthesis<br />

of Nozick <strong>and</strong> Buchanan see Lawrence Moss, "Optimal<br />

Jur isdictions <strong>and</strong> the Economic Theory of the <strong>State</strong>: Or,<br />

Anarchy <strong>and</strong> One World Government Are Only Corner<br />

Sol uti on s ," Pub1 i c Cho ice (N o. 1, 1980), pp. 17 - 26.<br />

( 2 2 ) Mu r ray Rot h bar d, For ANew L i ber t y ( New Yo r k :<br />

Macmillan, 1973), pp. 24-25.<br />

(23)Murray Rothbard, The Ethics of Liberty<br />

(Atlantic Highl<strong>and</strong>s, New Jersey: Humanities Press,<br />

1981).<br />

(24)John Wild, "Natural Law <strong>and</strong> Modern Ethical<br />

The 0 r y ," E t h i c s (0 c t 0 b e r 19 S 2 ), pp. 1-13, quoted in<br />

-ibid., p. 14.<br />

(2S)Thomas Spragens,Underst<strong>and</strong>ing Political<br />

Theory (New York: St. Martin's, 1976), p. lOS.<br />

( 2 6 ) A r n 0 I d Brecht , Pol i t ica 1 Theory (Princeton:<br />

Princeton University Press, 1959), pp. 367 ff.<br />

(27)<strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>, Human Action (Chicago:<br />

Henry Regnery, 1966), pp. 11-29; Lionel Robbins, The<br />

N8 t U rea n d S i g n i fie a n ceof Econom i eSc i enc e ( London:<br />

Macmillan, 1962), pp.- 83-94; <strong>and</strong> Murray Rothbard,<br />

"Toward a Reconstruction of Utility <strong>and</strong> Welfare<br />

Economi cS," On <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> Free Enterprise, ed. Mary<br />

Senholz (Princeton: Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>, 1965), pp. 225-35.<br />

(28)For a fuller presentation of this position see<br />

my "Reflections on the Substantive <strong>and</strong> Epitemological<br />

Aspects of the Rothbardian Natural Rights Ethic,"<br />

(Paper presented at the Fifth Libertarian Scholars<br />

Conference, Princeton University, October 21-23, 1977).<br />

For a c r i t i que 0 f t his posit ion see Do ug I a s Ra smussen ,<br />

"A Groundwork for Rights: Man's Natural End," The<br />

Journal of Libertarian Studies (Winter 1980), pp.<br />

70


CHAPTER II I<br />

The Stale IS I Casle Institution<br />

1. THE ORIGIN OF THE STATE<br />

For his views on the origin <strong>and</strong> nature of the<br />

state, the individualist anarchist owes a heavy intellectual<br />

debt to the sociological writings of Herbert<br />

S pen c era n d s u c h me mb e r s 0 f the·. Ger rna n s c h 0 0 lor<br />

historical sociology as <strong>Ludwig</strong> Gumplowicz. Gustav<br />

Ratzenhofer, <strong>and</strong>, in particular, Franz Oppenheimer.<br />

Since Oppenheimer introduced the distinction between<br />

the "political" <strong>and</strong> the "economic means," a distinction<br />

which has assumed a central position in the individualist<br />

anarchist analysis of the state, one cannot underst<strong>and</strong><br />

this analysis without some familiarity with the<br />

wr it ings of this early twentieth century German<br />

sociologist.<br />

Oppenheimer's fundamental insight was that man can<br />

sat i s f y his des ire s t h r 0 ugh two mu t ua I lyexcI us i ve<br />

means. One is work; the other robbery. Work, by which<br />

he means one's labor as well as what one receives in<br />

exchange for one's labor, he designated as "the economic<br />

means."<br />

Robbery, the "unrequited appropriation of the<br />

labor of others , " is termed the "political means."<br />

Whi Ie these two means are mutually exclusive, their<br />

purpose is identical: the acquisition of wealth.<br />

o p pen h e i mer the ref 0 rev i ews It a I I wo rId his tor y. f r OJTl<br />

p rim i t i vet i me sup toour own· c i viI i za t ion n s imp I y as<br />

"a contest. .between the economic <strong>and</strong> the political<br />

means." . Such is Oppenheimer's conceptual framework <strong>and</strong><br />

world view.<br />

There are two ramifications of this conceptual<br />

framework which Oppenheimer is quick to point out: (8)<br />

the s tat e i s the ins tit uti 0 nali zed em bod i men t 0 f the<br />

pol it ical means, <strong>and</strong> (b) since production necessarily<br />

precedes robbery society, by use of the economic means,<br />

must have obtained a certain level of economic development<br />

before the emergence of the state was possible.<br />

This latter point, Oppenheimer feels, explains why<br />

no state ever existed among such groups as the primi-<br />

73


tive peasants (grubbers) or the primitive huntsmen.<br />

The grubbers, for example, are attached to the l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong><br />

live in both abject. poverty <strong>and</strong> relative isolation.<br />

Such a situation provides no foundation for the rise of<br />

a state, for the primitive peasants are too impoverished<br />

to support one <strong>and</strong> too scattered from one another,<br />

ph Ysica I 1y, toor gani z e even for the i r own defens e • I t<br />

is much different,however, with the herdsmen. Acciden<br />

t s 0 f n Ii t u r e (I u c k) a s we 11 as the c I ever ne s s <strong>and</strong><br />

d iIi ge nee 0 f the b r e e de r produce dis tinc t i onsin for ­<br />

tune an d ,c0 n seq ue n t I y, dis tin c t i ons of c I ass. Bu t<br />

since luck .can not be controlled <strong>and</strong> such t r a i t sas<br />

cleverness are not hereditary, economic equality soon<br />

begins to re-emerge. It is quite natural for the<br />

existing wealthy to block this trend by recourse to<br />

violence. This utilization of the political means is<br />

of the utmost significance, says Oppenheimer, because<br />

with it economic <strong>and</strong> social equality is "destroyed<br />

permanently," <strong>and</strong> the foundation of the state is laid.<br />

Theft is easier <strong>and</strong> more exciting than the tedious<br />

<strong>and</strong> disciplined routine of production. Thus the political<br />

means tend to breed on its own success. Its succ<br />

e s s f u Ius e i non e caseencouragesitsuse inot her s .<br />

Consequent Iy, the herdsmen began to turn more <strong>and</strong> more<br />

to the pol i tical means. The weaker huntSmen are able<br />

to flee before their onslaught, but "the peasant cannot.<br />

His I i vel ihood being tied to the l<strong>and</strong>, he yields<br />

to SUbject ion, <strong>and</strong> pays tribute to his conqueror; that<br />

i s the g e n e sis 0 f the 1<strong>and</strong> s tatesin the old wo rId. "<br />

.The state therefore emerges, according to Oppenheimer,<br />

when the developing economic means of the peasantry are<br />

subordinated, by the use of the political means, to the<br />

direction of the herdsmen.<br />

Analyt ically, Oppenheimer sees six stages in the<br />

de vel opmen t of t he s tat e • The fir s t s tage en t a i1sthe<br />

use of the political means ini t s most rudimentary<br />

form: r<strong>and</strong>om robbery <strong>and</strong> killing of peasants by roaming<br />

b<strong>and</strong>s of herdsmen. The second stage is begun when the<br />

peasant finally accepts his fate <strong>and</strong> ceases to resist<br />

the attacks. The herdsman then discovers that except<br />

where it is necessary to keep the subjects suitably<br />

cowed or to crush an occasional rebellion it is in his<br />

interest to enslave rather than kill the peasant.<br />

After all, "a murdered peasant can no longer plow."<br />

The k.ey difference between the first two stages is presented<br />

in terms of an analogy. In the first stage he<br />

says, the herdsman is like the bear who, for the purpose<br />

of robbing the beehive, destroys it. In the sec-<br />

74


con t r a s t toth0 searea s suehas the Ama z 0 n basin wh i c h<br />

,h a dna 1m0 stun1 imit ed 8 grIcu 1t urall<strong>and</strong> • " Wh i 1e the r e<br />

was f r e que n t wa r far e ins uc h pIa c es, he says, t his did<br />

not lead to the rise of the state, for the defeated<br />

groups merely fled to another part of the forest.<br />

Hen c e the e f fee t 0 f war far e ins u c h P I ace s wa s t 0<br />

" dis per s e villa g e s 0 verawide area, <strong>and</strong> to ke e p them<br />

autonomous."<br />

By contrast, fl ight <strong>and</strong> re-settlement in an area<br />

1 ike the coastal valley of Peru, which was surrounded<br />

by mountains to the back, the sea to the front, <strong>and</strong><br />

deserts on both sides, was impossible. As population<br />

pressure increased, so did the dem<strong>and</strong> of each independent<br />

village for more l<strong>and</strong>. Such pressure culminated<br />

i n 1<strong>and</strong> war s<strong>and</strong> "a village de f eat edin wa r t h us fa c e d<br />

g rim pro s pee t s ," says Ca r n e i r 0 • " Ifit wa s a II owed to<br />

rem a i non its 0 wn 1<strong>and</strong>, ins tead 0 f be i ng ex termina ted<br />

or expelled, this concession came only at a price. And<br />

the price was political subordination to the victor."<br />

The d e f eat e d v i I I age wasincor porat e d wit h t hat 0 f the<br />

victor's, forming chiefdoms. As l<strong>and</strong> shortages continued,<br />

the warring units now became large chiefdoms, <strong>and</strong><br />

the process was begun anew. Hence, "autonomous neolithic<br />

villages were succeeded by chiefdoms, chiefdoms by<br />

kingdoms <strong>and</strong> kingdoms by empires."<br />

From the point of view of the individualist anarchi<br />

s t, the d ifferenees betwe e n Oppen he i mer <strong>and</strong> Ca r n e i r 0<br />

are far overshadowed by the agreement of these two notable<br />

scholars on one vital issue: the coercive origin<br />

of the state. As Carneiro says, "there is littlequest<br />

ion that, in one way or another, war played a decisive<br />

role in the rise of the <strong>State</strong>."(2) But coercion, ipso<br />

facto, entails exploitation. It is the method by<br />

wh i ch the dominant group in society is able, by use of<br />

the "political means," to institutionalize its socioe<br />

con 0 mi e posit ion a t the ex pen s e 0 f the sub0 r dina te<br />

group.<br />

It should be pointed out that the conflict theory<br />

has been cr i tic i zed as being one-sided. "There is no<br />

doubt that conquest played a part in most if not all<br />

processes of state formation," Lawrence Krader remarks.<br />

But" the conquest theory fai led as a general theory of<br />

t he or i gin of the state because it introduced only ext<br />

ern a I f act 0 r s, <strong>and</strong> fa i I ed tota ke i n t 0 a c c 0 un tin t e r ­<br />

nalprocessesin the for rna t ion 0 fag i ven s tat e • " P r i ­<br />

o r t 0 con que s t, h e rna i n t a ins, theremus t ha veexis ted<br />

" a tIea s t the ge r m 0 f soc i a1strat i f i cat ion, 0 fan ad-<br />

77


ministrative system, of an ideology of superiority <strong>and</strong><br />

o f r u 1 e r s hip, <strong>and</strong> 0 f a bur g e 0 h i ng e con omy wit h s om e<br />

differentiations of economic functions."(3) Anthropolo<br />

g i s t s suehas R • M. Ma c I ver<strong>and</strong>R. H. Low i e (4) ha ve<br />

concentrated on internal factors <strong>and</strong> contended, along<br />

what i s e s s en t i a 1 I Y A r i s tot eli an line s ( 5 ) , that the<br />

state emerges from the existence within society of<br />

associations which were voluntarily formed by independen<br />

t b<strong>and</strong>s for such speci f ic purposes· as the preservat<br />

ion 0 for d e r 0 r the rna i n tena nee 0 fareli g i 0 uscu It.<br />

As these associations gradually develop their own rules<br />

<strong>and</strong> enforcement mechanisms, they tend to break down the<br />

tr ibal bonds of kinship, thereby uniting several formerly<br />

independent b<strong>and</strong>s into the larger association.<br />

While these various associations are autonomous under<br />

the pain of necessity they are willing, at specific<br />

times <strong>and</strong> for specific purposes, to cooperate in the<br />

formation of a larger political unit <strong>and</strong> to temporarily<br />

delegate their authority to it. This process, according<br />

to Lowie, leads toward the voluntary formation of<br />

the state, which would be attained once such delegation<br />

of power became permanent. For empirical support Lowie<br />

cites the eight Associations of the Crow Indians of<br />

North America. Once every year, at the time of the<br />

hunt, these associations would delegate their authority<br />

to an agreed upon central power. They would do so<br />

because to be successful a hunt required the cessation<br />

of inter-association conflicts during its duration.<br />

Once the hunt was over, however, the associations would<br />

again assume their independent status <strong>and</strong> authority.<br />

While Lowie claims that the tendency was toward the<br />

emergence of the permanent state, the Crow Indians were<br />

conquered by the government of the United <strong>State</strong>s before<br />

the final state was reached. While admitting "definite<br />

validity" to certain aspects of the Lowie-MacIver thesis,<br />

the confl ict theor ists rebut that since the stage<br />

of autonomous associations had existed among the Crow<br />

Indians for centuries there was in fact no tendency<br />

toward the emergence of a permanent state. Hence, they<br />

say, the the 0 r y i sun a b let0 ace0 un t for "the' j urn p ,<br />

from non-state to state."(6)<br />

Another theory, also concentrating on internal<br />

factors, has been propounded by Morton Fried. Fried is<br />

in basic agreement with Oppenheimer's analysis regarding<br />

the emergence of economic inequality <strong>and</strong> social<br />

s t rat i fie a t ion . Toprot e c t the i r posit ion s, howe ve r ,<br />

the wealthy must not simply resort to occasional violence,<br />

but must establish "powerful institutions of<br />

political control." Thus, the stratified non-state<br />

78


tain a perpetual flux.(12) But regardless of how powe<br />

r f u 1 the s tate, its powe r is a Iwa y s fin i t e • Thus, no<br />

g 0 v ernmen tean beeom pIetel y "t 0 t a lita rian" <strong>and</strong> nos 0 ­<br />

ciety can be completely atomized. Moreover, the central<br />

point still holds, for even with an atomized society<br />

no government could persist if large numbers of individuals,<br />

despite their isolation, suddenly decided to<br />

res i s t the s tat e • Hen ce, wh i lethe moret0 t a lita r i 8 n<br />

countries can coerce obedience from greater numbers<br />

than can the more open societies, the extent <strong>and</strong> effectiveness<br />

of coercion still remains limited.<br />

But if both the carrot <strong>and</strong> the stick are confined<br />

to the minority, the brunt of the burden falls on the<br />

third category of political indoctrination. There are,<br />

the individualist anarchist argues, two types of justificat<br />

ions propounded by the apologists for the state:<br />

[1] the rulers are good <strong>and</strong> wise, <strong>and</strong> [2] the rule of<br />

the s tat e i s neee s sary<strong>and</strong>ine v ita bIe. Un de r the I a t ­<br />

ter one finds arguments such as [1] anarchism is chaos<br />

<strong>and</strong> hence the state is inevitable, <strong>and</strong> [2] the state is<br />

the great benefactor of the people, protecting them<br />

from both foreign invasion <strong>and</strong> domestic violence.<br />

Other means of securing support, Rothbard says, are<br />

such ploys as [1] patriotism, [2] "tradition," [3] exaltation<br />

of the collectivity, <strong>and</strong> [4] guilt. First,<br />

the state is able to generate patriotism by identifying<br />

itself with such common objects of love as one's homel<strong>and</strong>.<br />

Thus, one comes to think of the entire territory<br />

over which the state rules as "my country." Second, the<br />

rulers exhort their subjects to "worship your ancestors"<br />

<strong>and</strong> "uphold old customs <strong>and</strong> institutions," while<br />

the y p 0 r t ray t h em s e I v e s a s the 1 e gi t i rna t e he irs of<br />

theseancest 0 r san d t he prod uc t 0 f thesecus t oms. ( 13 )<br />

Third, individual dissent is discouraged by appeals to<br />

n a d jus t to soc i e t y" 0 r "heedthewi I I 0 f the rna j 0 r i t Y• "<br />

And finally, "Any increase in private well-being," says<br />

Rothbard, "can be attacked as 'unconscionable greed,'<br />

'mater ial ism' or 'excessive affluence'; profit-making<br />

can be attacked as 'exploitation' <strong>and</strong> 'usury,' mutually<br />

beneficial exchanges denounced as 'selfishness,' <strong>and</strong><br />

s 0 me how wit h the con c 1 us ion a I wa y s be i ng dr awn t hat<br />

more resources should be siphoned from the private to<br />

the 'pubI i c sector • ' The i nduee d gu i 1t rna kesthe pub­<br />

I i c m0 r ere 8 d Y t 0 do jus t t h8 t • For wh i 1e i nd i v i d u8 I<br />

persons tend to indulge in 'selfish greed,' the failure<br />

of the <strong>State</strong>'s rulers to engage in exchanges is supposed<br />

to signify their devotion to higher <strong>and</strong> nobler<br />

causes--parasitic predation being apparently morally<br />

<strong>and</strong> esthetically lofty as compared to peaceful <strong>and</strong> pro-<br />

81


ductive work."(14)<br />

It is through a combination of all of these devices<br />

that the state is able to make itself appear both<br />

benef icial <strong>and</strong> legi t imate <strong>and</strong> thus to secure popular<br />

support, ranging from enthusiasm to simple resignation.<br />

A way in which the state is able to obtain acquiescence<br />

by comb i n in g the use of such methods as appea I s to patriotism<br />

<strong>and</strong> the threat of coercion is well illuStrated<br />

b y the ant i - s tat i s t R<strong>and</strong>ol ph B0 urn e • Men are t 0 I d, he<br />

writes, that<br />

they will enter the military establishment of<br />

their own volition, as their splendid sacrifice<br />

for their country's welfare, <strong>and</strong> that if<br />

they do not enter they will be hunted down<br />

<strong>and</strong> punished with the most horrid of penalties;<br />

<strong>and</strong> under a most indescribable confus<br />

i' 0 n 0 f d e m0 c rat i cpr ide <strong>and</strong> per sona I f ear<br />

they submit to the destruction of their livelihood<br />

if not their lives, in a way that<br />

would formerly have seemed to them so obnoxious<br />

as to be incredible.(15)<br />

A final word should be mentioned concerning the<br />

crucial role compulsory public education has in inducing<br />

acceptance of the state ideology. The state gets<br />

the child at a young <strong>and</strong> impressionable age. The child<br />

is then taught to be patriotic, love his country, <strong>and</strong><br />

revere his ancestors. Anarchism is either equated with<br />

chaos or disregarded altogether. Hence, the child is<br />

indoctrinated into the habit of thinking in terms of<br />

the state. He becomes a prisoner of his educational<br />

environment, incapable of thinking in terms beyond the<br />

statist paradigm. Particular government A or particular<br />

government B may be bad, but government itself is<br />

never questioned. It is through such educational indoctr<br />

ination that the individual becomes so susceptible<br />

to the statist ideology he encounters later in life.<br />

3. THE GROWTH OF THE STATE<br />

The fact that the state originated in violence <strong>and</strong><br />

exploitation does not, in itself, go very far in explaining<br />

how <strong>and</strong> why the state grows, <strong>and</strong> grows not<br />

just in size but in the power it exercises over its<br />

subjects. An answer was hinted at earlier.<br />

Oppenheimer's world view was that there were two exclus<br />

i v e mea ns, the e conom i c<strong>and</strong> the pol i ticaI, for 0 b t a i n ­<br />

i n g the same 0 b j e c t : rna t e ria 1 sat i s fa c t ion. Sin c e the<br />

82


latter is the embodiment of violence while the former<br />

entails voluntary <strong>and</strong> peaceful exchange of goods, it<br />

should not be suprising that the political means gain<br />

a t the ex pen s e 0 f the e conom i c • And sinc e itis the<br />

state that maintains a monopoly of the political means,<br />

it should likewise not be surprising that it is able,<br />

as James Madison once remarked, to turn "every contingency<br />

into a resource for accumulating force in the<br />

government.(16)<br />

But this answer, by itself, is too abstruse. What,<br />

more specifically, do·. the individualist anarchists see<br />

as the means that the state uses to augment its power?<br />

Drawing heavily on the writings of such men as Bertr<strong>and</strong><br />

d e J 0 u v e n e 1, Am e rica nan t i - s tat i s t s s uchas Ra ndol ph<br />

Bourne, <strong>and</strong> such laissez faire economists as <strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>von</strong><br />

Mi ses, a few of the more important means can be<br />

indicated.<br />

a. Democracy.<br />

Bertr<strong>and</strong> de Jouvenel agrees with Oppenheimer that<br />

"the state is in essence the result of the successes<br />

achieved by a b<strong>and</strong> of brig<strong>and</strong>s who superimpose themselves<br />

on small distinct societies ••. It pursues no<br />

just end; its one concern is the profitable exploitat<br />

ion 0 f con que red <strong>and</strong> s u bm iss i ve sub j e c t s . I t lives<br />

off the subject populations."(17) But with the passage<br />

of time the governmental units exp<strong>and</strong>ed beyond the<br />

a b iii t Y 0 f the king toex e r t per sona leon t r 0 I. Con s e ­<br />

quently, control over particular areas was delegated to<br />

the kin g T s sub 0 r dinates<strong>and</strong> f r i ends, i n pa r ticu Iart0<br />

those mi I i tary figures who had supported the king in<br />

his s t r ugg I e for power. These areas gradually emerged<br />

into all but completely independent political units,<br />

viz., fiefdoms, possessing their own courts, military<br />

for c e san d sou r c e s 0 f reven ue • Inth i s wa y the king<br />

became largely dependent for his revenue on the support<br />

of those elements independent of him, i.e., the feudal<br />

lords. Since there was an inverse relationship between<br />

the power of the king <strong>and</strong> that of the aristocracy, the<br />

latter were always careful to view the king as a person<br />

in opposition to themselves. They were jealous of<br />

their independent prerogatives <strong>and</strong> relinquished them to<br />

the kin g 0 n I y g r u d gin g 1 Y <strong>and</strong> wh entheye i therag r e e d<br />

with the king's policies or were presented with no alt<br />

ern a t i ve . T h us i twa s rat her d iff i cui t for the employment<br />

of the pol it ical means, or "<strong>State</strong> power" to<br />

use Albert Jay Nock's term, to grow at the expense of<br />

the economic means, or "social power.<br />

83


But the emergence of demo,cracy <strong>and</strong> the idea of<br />

pop u I a r s 0 v ere i g nt y grea t 1y fa c iii tatedthe growthof<br />

s tat e power. " I twa s not t hat the t hrone wa s 0 ve r ­<br />

thrown," says de Jouvenel in speaking of the French<br />

Revolution, "but that the whole, the nation-person,<br />

m0 u n ted it. Its I i f e wa s as t hat 0 f the king itsuc ­<br />

ceeded, but it had one great advantage over him: for<br />

subjects are in regard to a king--whC? is seen to be a<br />

person different from themselves--naturally careful<br />

to secure their rights. Whereas, the nation is not a<br />

different person: it is the subject himself, <strong>and</strong> yet<br />

it is more than he--it is a hypostatized We."(18)<br />

Since the state is now controlled by "the people" it is<br />

no longer feared as a dangerous instrument but looked<br />

upon as the means to achieve the "common good."<br />

Democracy serves to facilitate the growth of state<br />

power in yet another way. By possessing an independent<br />

base the aristocracy in the feudal period were able to<br />

block or at least retard, the growth of the king's<br />

power. But the democratization of society, says de<br />

Jouvenel, entai 1 ing as it does the elimination of all<br />

such independent bases of power, removes all obstacles<br />

to the centraLization <strong>and</strong> augmentation of state power.<br />

For regardless of such devices as the written Constitution<br />

<strong>and</strong> the division of the government into several<br />

separate branches, the fact remains that all branches<br />

derive their power from the same source: the majority<br />

of the peopl e. (19) The individual ist anarchist agrees<br />

<strong>and</strong> therefore denies that even a constitutionally es­<br />

"tabl ished "independent judiciary" is able to serve as a<br />

check. The jUdges themselves, they argue, are employed<br />

by <strong>and</strong> are therefore part of the state. Thus, says<br />

Rothbard, over the years the state has been able to<br />

t ran s for m j ud i cia 1 rev i e w from "a 1 imit i ng device t 0<br />

yet another instrument for furnishing ideological legitimacy<br />

to the government's actions. For if a judicial<br />

decree of 'unconstitutional' is a mightly check to government<br />

power, an implicit or explicit verdict of 'const<br />

i tut ional' is a mighty weapon in fostering pUblic acceptance<br />

of ever-greater goevernment power."(20) The<br />

idea of checking the government by a written constitution<br />

is seen as "a noble attempt that failed." It<br />

fai led because "when you give the <strong>State</strong> itself the<br />

fin a I power t 0 i n t e r pre t the ve r yins t r ume n t t hat i s<br />

supposed to I imi t the <strong>State</strong>, you will inevitably find<br />

the Crinstitution being stretched <strong>and</strong> distorted •.• "(21)<br />

De Jouvenel' s fear is that as democracy matures<br />

power is ever more easily delegated to the state while<br />

84


individual liberty is subordinated to the "common good"<br />

or "s.ocial justice." Under the rubric of popular sovereignty,<br />

he says, Parliaments were established <strong>and</strong> inv<br />

est e d wit h the power 0 f 1a w- ma kin g • This wa s not<br />

s imp I y a t ran s fer 0 f aut h0 r i t Y rr om the king to" the<br />

people" or their representatives, he points out, but an<br />

addition to state power of immense proportions. In<br />

pre-democratic societies the king was not sovereign but<br />

waS seen as the m<strong>and</strong>atory of God or of the gods. But<br />

God I s law was immutable. Hence, the king had no power<br />

to make or change the law. Hec0 u 1d obtain obedience<br />

only if he himself remained obedient to the divine law.<br />

T his con fin edt h e king , sact ions wit h i n rat her na r row<br />

<strong>and</strong> predictable limits.<br />

Pos i t i ve leg i s I at i on appeared only when the idea<br />

of popular sovereignty replaced that of divine sovereignty.<br />

Since the people were now sovereign they were<br />

em power edt 0 rna k e the law, <strong>and</strong> the Age 0 f Ra t iona lism<br />

served to reinforce this by teaching that any order was<br />

merely conventional <strong>and</strong> hence changeable at will. This,<br />

says de Jouvenel, was a great breakthrough for state<br />

power. By ident i fying themselves with the state, the<br />

people were willing to delegate more <strong>and</strong> more power to<br />

it. Democratic theorists erred, he says in quoting<br />

Montesquieu, in confusing the power of the people with<br />

the lib e r t y 0 f the pe 0 pIe, for the powe r 0 f the s tat e<br />

"i s comm<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> everyone cannot comm<strong>and</strong>. Sovereignty<br />

of the people is therefore nothing but a fiction," <strong>and</strong><br />

one whie h "c 0 n fer s on the r u Ie r s the aut h0 r i t Y 0 f the<br />

whole."(22)<br />

Whi Ie the emergence of democracy opened the doors<br />

for the expansion of state power at the expense of social<br />

power, the growth of the state beyond 8 certain<br />

po i n t assumes a Ii fe of its own; expans ion of the state<br />

in one area requires expansion in other areas as well.<br />

For, "when the <strong>State</strong> is so large, when everything is<br />

political, one cannot say 'I will live in a certain<br />

way • I What hem u s t say i s'T0 I i ve ina ce r t a i n wa y<br />

my s elf, I mu s t s e i z e the con t r 0 Isof the grea t rna chi ne<br />

<strong>and</strong> em p loy themin s u c hamanneras sui t s me. I " In<br />

this way every issue becomes politicized <strong>and</strong> requires<br />

the i n t e r v e n t ion 0 f the s tat e • Dem 0 era c y, de J 0 uve ne I<br />

therefore concludes, is merely "the time of tyranny's<br />

incubation."(23)<br />

85


. War.<br />

A second, vi tally important, means for the growth<br />

oft hest ate i s wa r . Her e the i nd i v i d ua listanarchis t<br />

turns, in part icular, to the wr i t ings of R<strong>and</strong>olph<br />

B 0 urn e • Bourne be I ieve s that the s tate is" the ins t r ument<br />

by which the whole herd is wielded for the benefit<br />

of a class." It follows that the more powerful the<br />

s tat e, the mo r e en t r enc hedther u 1 i n g .e lite, the bet t e r<br />

able it is to benefit itself. Hence, says Bourne, "The<br />

ideal of the <strong>State</strong> is that within its territory its<br />

power <strong>and</strong> influence should be universal." But even in<br />

a .d em 0 era c y the rna j 0 r i t y migh t we 11 res i s t na ked a t ­<br />

tempts by the state to restrict free speech or impose<br />

an overriding uniformity. Hence, what is required is<br />

some justification for state action. And since it is<br />

precisely in war that this justification is most easily<br />

<strong>and</strong> clearly found, Bourne concludes that "war is the<br />

health of the state." Once war breaks out "Old nationa<br />

I idea 1 s are taken out, re-adapted to the purpose <strong>and</strong><br />

use d a sun i v e r sal to uc hs ton e s, 0 r mo Ids i n t 0 wh i c h a I 1<br />

thought is poured." Dissent, which was permitted in<br />

times of peace, is usually outlawed in times of war.<br />

"Criticism of the <strong>State</strong>, objections to war, lukewarm<br />

opinions concerning the necessity or the beauty of cons<br />

c rip t ion, are rna des ub j e c t t 0 fer 0 c i 0 us pena I ties far<br />

exceeding in severity those affixed to actual pragmatic<br />

cr imes. Publ ic opinion •.• becomes one solid block.<br />

y Loyal t y " 0 r rat her war 0 r thodox y, bec omesthe sol e<br />

test for all professions, techniques, occupations."(24)<br />

But what is especially striking is the realization<br />

that once the population is infused with a war psychology,<br />

all else follows automatically. For wars, at<br />

I e a s t 0 U r mod ern "d em 0 era tic" wa r s wh i c h depend for<br />

the irsuc c e s son rna s s suppo r t<strong>and</strong>en t h us i am, are i nva r ­<br />

iably presented in terms of a struggle for righteous<br />

<strong>and</strong> human i tar ian goals. The enemy is dehumanized <strong>and</strong><br />

the complex <strong>and</strong> often subtle differences in culture <strong>and</strong><br />

policies are presented in simplistic black <strong>and</strong> white<br />

terms. (25) War is thereby transformed into a moral<br />

crusade to "make the world safe for democracy," to<br />

" des t roy tot a lit a rian ism," 0 r to" con t a i n Comm un i s TTl • "<br />

And not only does this crusade provide a welcome contrast<br />

to the mundane chores of daily living but, perhaps<br />

even more importantly, it infuses life with a<br />

meaningfulness it never had during peacetime. It is<br />

th i s tha t largely explains that striking phenomenon of<br />

the outpouring of voluntary sacrifice, of millions of<br />

men w i I lin g 1 Y rna r chi ng tot he i r near 1y c e r t a i n dea t h s ,<br />

86


that is so characteristic a feature of modern war. For<br />

it is only through voluntary sacrifice that one can<br />

become a part of, belong to, the crusade. Thus it is<br />

during war in particular that government has rarely to<br />

compel sacrifIce. It has only to ask but to<br />

receive.(26)<br />

Hence it is only in wartime, as Bourne notes, that<br />

the nation is able to "attain a uniformity of feeling,<br />

a hierarchy of values, CUlminating at the undisputed<br />

apex of the state idea." This "could not possibly be<br />

produced through any other agency than war."(27)(28)<br />

c. Economic Intervention.<br />

There are two major economic factors the free<br />

market anarchist can <strong>and</strong> does cite to help explain the<br />

growth of government. First is the inequality of costs<br />

<strong>and</strong> bene fit s of government programs, <strong>and</strong> second is the<br />

dynamic of the market process.<br />

The costs of government programs are usually widely<br />

dIffused, while the benefits are highly concentrated.<br />

Since the benef i ts a government can offer to a<br />

particular interest group can be substantial, that<br />

group wi II lobby vigorously for them. But so long as<br />

the costs are distributed widely throughout society it<br />

wi II genera 11 y come to no more than a few cents per<br />

person per program. Since this would be less than the<br />

cost of organizing an effort to oppose the program,<br />

such is not done. It is therefore usually politically<br />

profitable for the politicians to implement the programs<br />

desired by the interest groups.(29)<br />

Sec 0 n d I y, the a n arc his t em phas i zesth e del i cat e<br />

interdependencies of the modern market economy. Since<br />

any tampering with the market process has ramifications<br />

throughout the entire economic system, the policymakers<br />

wi 11 therefore be confronted with the choice of<br />

either ab<strong>and</strong>oning the original interventionist policy<br />

altogether or exp<strong>and</strong>ing it into ever more areas. The<br />

government, for example, may desire to "stimulate" the<br />

economy by increasing the supply of money. This will<br />

result in rising prices <strong>and</strong> the policy-makers may then<br />

find it politically necessary or expedient to impose<br />

maximum prices on some or all goods. But since this<br />

w ill red u ceorev en eli minate profit rna r gins, I n ve s t ­<br />

ment wi II be discouraged in those areas where the controls<br />

were enacted, thereby causing a reduction of output<br />

<strong>and</strong> hen c e ash 0 r t a ge 0 f t hose goods. This wi 1 1<br />

87


have several imporant consequences. First, in an effort<br />

to st imulate production, ·price controls for the<br />

factors of product ion wi 11 also have to be imposed.<br />

But since this will discourage production of factors,<br />

the policy of price controls will have to be exp<strong>and</strong>ed<br />

into ever wider areas. Second, to cope with the shortage,<br />

the g 0 v ernmen t rna y a 1sode c ide to adopta po I icy<br />

of rationing. And third, if rationing is resorted to,<br />

the government wi 11 almost certainly' be forced to exp<strong>and</strong><br />

greatly its police force in order to cope with the<br />

black markets, which are the inevitable accompaniment<br />

of rat ioning.(30) All of this must entail the progressive<br />

extension of government control into areas that<br />

were heretofore independent <strong>and</strong>, as a corollary, the<br />

concentration of ever more power in the h<strong>and</strong>s of<br />

government.<br />

In short, the individualist anarchist believes<br />

that there is an inherent tendency for state power to<br />

exp<strong>and</strong> at the expense of social power. The state, commen<br />

t s Ro t h ba r d, " has i nvaria b 1Y shown a s t r i king tal en t<br />

for the expansion of its powers beyond any limits that<br />

might have been imposed upon it."(31) The general reason<br />

liesin what J 0 hn Ca I h 0 un referredt0 a s the propensity<br />

of the dominant power in society to abuse its<br />

power. Since normally the dominant power is that which<br />

is in control of the government, Calhoun felt that<br />

Constitutional res·trictions "would ultimately be annulled<br />

<strong>and</strong> the government converted into one of unlimited<br />

powers."(32) The political means, as Oppenheimer<br />

·would say, quite naturally prevail over the economic<br />

me a n s • Dem 0 c r a c y, war <strong>and</strong> e c 0 nom i c i n t e r ve n t i on are<br />

just three of the more important ways by which the political<br />

means are implemented.<br />

4. THE TOTAL STATE<br />

The individual ist anarchist as written little on<br />

the twentieth century phenomenon of the totalitarian<br />

s tat e. However some men t i on of it shou I d be made since<br />

i tis the log i cal cui min a t ion 0 f wh a the sees as the<br />

statist dynamic.<br />

Totalitarianism is the logical extension of the<br />

con c e p t 0 f s 0 vere i gn t y • Wh i 1e the devel 0 pmen t 0 f t hat<br />

term owes much to the wr i t ings of Jean Bodin in the<br />

sixteenth century, it was Thomas Hobbes a century later<br />

who made that concept the center of his entire politic<br />

a I s y s t em. Be 1 i e v i ng t hat therewa s nos 0 C i e t y wit hout<br />

order <strong>and</strong> no order without a sovereign, Hobbes<br />

88


qui tel 0 g i c a I I y con c Iudedt hat s 0 ve rei gn t y wa s the<br />

creator, the sine qua non, of society. WithoMt the<br />

state, said Hobbes in his most famous passage, the life<br />

of man is "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish <strong>and</strong> short."<br />

Since order required that all power be centralized<br />

i nthestate the r e co u I d ben 0 room for ind e penden t<br />

associations. Associations could only undermine the<br />

unity of power required for peace <strong>and</strong> order.(33) Thus<br />

the Church, the ·university, <strong>and</strong> even the family fall<br />

vi ct im to Hobbes t sover e ign. But it is important to<br />

rea liz e t hat for Hobbe s sovere i gn t y wa s not an end i n<br />

its elf but was ne c e s a r y, as Ni s bet po i n t sout, topr 0vide<br />

a secure <strong>and</strong> "impersonal environment of law within<br />

which individuals may pursue rationally their proper<br />

interests." And far from infringing upon individual<br />

freedom Hobbes bel i eved that sovereignty <strong>and</strong> freedom<br />

went h<strong>and</strong>- in-h<strong>and</strong>. The sovereign state was the agent<br />

for the liberation of the individual from the petty<br />

tyrannies of "church, guild or any other form of intermediate<br />

association." Thus while Hobbes believed that<br />

the state was the creator of society he did not endeavor<br />

to abolish the distinction between the two.<br />

I twa s R 0 u sse a u who, r e cogn i z i ng t hat rna n t s ps y ­<br />

chological need for attachment conflicted with the impersonality<br />

of Hobbes' Leviathan, preceeded with such<br />

an abolition. Like Hobbes, Rousseau desired the liberat<br />

ion of man from the constraints fo traditional society.<br />

And also like Hobbes, he recognized that this required<br />

a powerful <strong>and</strong> highly centralized state. It is<br />

the cognition of this fact that makes explicable<br />

R 0 u sseau' sotherwi s e pa r adox i ca I r ema r k t hat rna n i s t 0<br />

be "forced to be free." But if the atomization of society,<br />

as Hobbes knew, was a necessary condition for<br />

sovereignty, <strong>and</strong> if sovereignty, as he believed was a<br />

n e c e s s a rye 0 n d i t ion for soc i a lorder, i t wa s not, as<br />

Roussea'u fully realized, a sufficient condition. For<br />

per hap s the m0 S t fun dam e n t a I 0 f rna n 's ps yc hoi 0 g i ca I<br />

nee dsis the nee d t 0 bel 0 ng, to fee I a pa r t 0 f some ­<br />

thing. Thus, if sovereignty dem<strong>and</strong>ed destruction of<br />

all intermediate associations, something would have to<br />

be sub s tit utedin the i r p I ace. Ro us sea u 0 f fer e d as the<br />

funct ional equivalent of membership in the plurality of<br />

independent <strong>and</strong> autonomous associations membership in<br />

the monolithic, overarching political community;<br />

membership, that is, in the total state.(34)<br />

It is therefore in the writings of Rousseau in the<br />

eighteenth century that one fInds a description of the<br />

89


essentials of the modern totalitarian order that did<br />

not em e, r g e for n ear I y an 0 the r two c e n t uri e s . For 0 ne<br />

cannot underst<strong>and</strong> totalitarianism by focusing on such<br />

p hen 0 men a a s the mas s mur de r 0 f Jews by the Na z is, 0 r<br />

the extermination of the kulaks in Soviet Russia. As<br />

Nisbet points out, totalitarianism "cannot be reduced<br />

tot h e 0 per a t ion 0 f for c e <strong>and</strong> t err 0 r • " As t rag i cas<br />

such occurrences are, they are merely i,ncidental rather<br />

than essential elements of the totalitarian order.<br />

For ce wi II be used against recalci trant minor it ies but,<br />

as we .have already seen, it cannot be used effectively<br />

against the majority. Thus, to underst<strong>and</strong> totalitarianism,<br />

one must explain its appeal to the masses.<br />

His tor i c a I I y, the emerge nceof tot a lita rianor de r s<br />

have followed a period of extreme fluctuations <strong>and</strong><br />

rapid SOCIal decay in which the customs <strong>and</strong> stability<br />

oft h e 0 I d 0 r derareov e r t urn e d • This wa s as t rue 0 f<br />

pre - 19 1 7 R u s s i a asit wa s 0 fIt a I y <strong>and</strong> Ge r rna nyin the<br />

1920' s<strong>and</strong> 1930' s. But as Rousseau recognized, <strong>and</strong> a<br />

pIe tho r a 0 f soc i 0 log i s t s 0 f whom Em i leDur k he im wa s<br />

only the most famous have confirmed, man is simply not<br />

equipped, psyhologically, to live in such an atomized<br />

<strong>and</strong> uncertain environment. Hence the emphasis by the<br />

totalitarian state on mass demonstrations <strong>and</strong> parades,<br />

such as the May Day parade, the extensive use of such<br />

symbols as the swastika, <strong>and</strong> such special forms of address<br />

as "comrade." All are cultivated in the con'scious<br />

attempt to generatein the individual a feeling<br />

,of attachment <strong>and</strong> community.(35) But undoubtedly the<br />

most significant element in the creation of attachment<br />

to the total state is the ideology, such as that of the<br />

"master race" or the "proletariat." For, as Jacques<br />

Ellul says, the ideology or myth, being comprehensive,<br />

envelops the individual <strong>and</strong> therefore renders him immun<br />

e from a 1lother i n flue n c e s • (36 )<br />

But if it is the creation of the political community<br />

that largely explains the appeal of totalitarianism,<br />

its appeal holds only in the absence of other,<br />

competing communities. Hence the necessity for the<br />

pol i tiC a 1 communit y t 0 be come tot a 1. Hen ce, too, its<br />

increasing appeal as it becomes total. For when the<br />

s tat e bee 0 me s the 0 n 1 y commun i t y, rega r dIe s s 0 f how<br />

artificial it may be, life becomes identified with the<br />

state.• Dissent can be undertaken in only the most<br />

serious of cases <strong>and</strong> by only the most intrepid. For<br />

open dissent risks ostracism from the political community.<br />

And when that is the only community, this means<br />

con s i.g nmen t tot he ps y c hoI 0 g i c a Idea tho f compIe t e i s 0 -<br />

90


I a t ion. T his ex p I a ins s u c h ot her wi s e i nex p I i ca b 1e<br />

phenomena as the willingness, even desire, of the<br />

"enemies of the people' to confess, during the Soviet<br />

purge-trials, to nearly any charges levelled against<br />

them. (37) For such is the route to psychological peace<br />

<strong>and</strong>, no matter how remote, the possible return to the<br />

flock. As Nisbet has explained in a particularly insightful<br />

passage, "the <strong>State</strong> becomes powerful not by<br />

what itta ke s from the i nd i v i d ua I, but by what itta ke s<br />

from the spiritual <strong>and</strong> social associations which compete<br />

with it for man's devotion."<br />

One can now see the role that violence plays in<br />

the totalitarian state. Since a totalitarian order is<br />

possible only in the absence of intermediate associat<br />

ionsat 0 t a lit a ria n r u 1 e r, un I e s s his r i set0 powe r<br />

itself follows upon the disintegration of the old order<br />

<strong>and</strong> the a tom i z a t ion 0 f soc i e t y, mus t t a k e me as ures to<br />

create atomization. Hence the violent assault upon<br />

all intermediate associations. And since there is a<br />

natural tendency for such associations to reemerge, the<br />

per pet u a t Ion 0 fat om i z a t ion r eq u ire s the per i od i c<br />

recourse to violent measures to forestall such an<br />

occurrence.<br />

The foregoing highlights the salient role intermediate<br />

associations play in the preservation of a relatively<br />

free <strong>and</strong> stable social order, <strong>and</strong> some have contended<br />

that this poses a serious question for the libe<br />

r tar ian • The f r e e rna r ketanarchis t 0 f ten a ppea r s to<br />

be oblivious to such associations. His alternative to<br />

the state is simply The Individual, restricted only<br />

by the" Ii ber tar ian non-aggression axiom" <strong>and</strong> his own<br />

voluntary contractual agreements. The role of custom<br />

<strong>and</strong> tradition is downplayed, if not held in outright<br />

contempt. And the result is a view of the social order<br />

as a mechanical process, changeable at will <strong>and</strong> with no<br />

side effects, <strong>and</strong> held together largely by the heavy<br />

h<strong>and</strong> of the government in a statist society, <strong>and</strong> purely<br />

by contractual agreement in the anarchist. The libertarian's<br />

emphasis is invariably on the individual in<br />

the abstract, the completely rational <strong>and</strong> unemotional<br />

individual. The focus is not on attachment, but on release;<br />

<strong>and</strong> not release from the state to permit attachmen<br />

t too the r comm un i ties<strong>and</strong> ass 0 cia t ions, but 0 n r e ­<br />

lease, per se. But atomization, goes the argument,<br />

is the same whether it is created by the Leviathan<br />

<strong>State</strong> or the "Libertarian Nonagression Axiom." This,<br />

however, ra I ses the quest ion of whether a society constructed<br />

along pure laissez faire lines could ever be<br />

91


stable, or would it, as paradoxical as it may seem at<br />

fir s t, act ua I I Y pavethe wa y for' anew totali tar ian ism?<br />

For "It is ludicrous," warns Robert Nisbet, "to hold up<br />

the assorted charms of individual release <strong>and</strong> emancipation<br />

to popUlations whose burning problems are those<br />

ar ising, today, from moral <strong>and</strong> social release. To do<br />

s 0 i s but t 0 rna ke the wa y for the Gr<strong>and</strong>Inqui sit 0 r the<br />

easier. For this is the appeal, as we have seen, of<br />

the to tal ita ria n pro p h e t - - to' reI e a s e' rna sses 0 f<br />

atomized individuals from their intolerable<br />

individualism"(38)<br />

The old laissez faire failed, Nisbet continues,<br />

beea u s ei t focused on the abstract, imaginary, rational<br />

individual at the expense of kinship <strong>and</strong> community.<br />

What is needed is a "new laissez faire" which will present<br />

an environment within which "autonomous groups may<br />

prosper." (39)<br />

While this analysis of contemporary society is<br />

profound, as a criticism of libertairianism it is based<br />

on a misunderst<strong>and</strong>ing. Libertarianism is a political,<br />

not a m0 r a lor soc i a I, phi los 0 PhY a nd assuc h con cerns<br />

i tsel f wi th the use of force in society.(40) Its premise,<br />

the "non-aggression axiom," is that initiated<br />

for c e i s n ever jus t i fied • Put d ifferen t 1y, t his me a ns<br />

that any <strong>and</strong> all peaceful activity is legitimate. Libertarians<br />

therefore oppose coercively imposed attachments.<br />

But if individuals do have a psychological need<br />

for a t t a c hmen t therei s not hi ng topreve n t them from<br />

,associat ing voluntarily. Given the requisite freedom,<br />

David Friedman argues, not only will groups of likemin<br />

d e d .i n d i v i d u a I s nat u r a I I Y g r a v ita t e t owa r d eac h<br />

other, but those with conflicting values will just as<br />

naturally migrate away from each other. The result,<br />

accor ding to Fr i edman, would be a plethora of more or<br />

less autonomous communities populated by like-minded<br />

individuals, with each community subscribing to its<br />

own, <strong>and</strong> in many cases quite unlibertarian,'laws, <strong>and</strong><br />

cult ivat iog its own identity, customs <strong>and</strong><br />

traditions.(41)<br />

T hus, far from con f lieting wit h rna n 's need for attachment'<br />

on closer analysis libertarianism actually<br />

appears to offer precisely that environment which<br />

Nisbet's community-oriented "new laissez faire"<br />

requires.<br />

92


5. WHO RULES THE STATE?<br />

It is clear that the validity of the individualist<br />

anarchist view of the state is dependent upon the<br />

existence of a ruling elite; yet this elite has not<br />

been ident i f ied. Who, then, constitutes this domInant<br />

g r 0 up? 1 n p rim i t i ve tim esit waseas y t 0 s po t • On e<br />

g r au p, em p I a yin g the pol i tic a 1 me a ns, wo u 1d sub j e c t<br />

an 0 the r to its wi I 1 <strong>and</strong> beg i n to ex t rae t t r i bu t e from<br />

them. Gradually, as this arrangement persisted, it<br />

came to be accepted <strong>and</strong> the extraction of tribute became<br />

sys terna t i zed in the per iodie payment of taxes to<br />

the "government." As 'economist Walter Grinder summari<br />

zes it, "I tis to th j s more powerful group that the<br />

wealth, plundered by the political means, accrues. In<br />

time this group becomes entrenched both politically <strong>and</strong><br />

economically, through its plundered wealth."(42)<br />

But this relatively straight-forward process<br />

becomes much more complicated in today's world. Now,<br />

all areas are ruled by governments. Hence, one cannot<br />

simply organize a military b<strong>and</strong>, impose one's will on a<br />

stateless society, call oneself a government, <strong>and</strong> begin<br />

to collect taxes. Further, since the government is the<br />

most powerful institution in society, a direct assault<br />

is usually doomed to fail. While in primitive societies<br />

the rUling elite was able to set up its own government,<br />

today this is no longer, or only rarely possible.<br />

The ruling elite of today is that group which,<br />

working through the existing power structure, is able<br />

to obtain control of the government <strong>and</strong> use it for its<br />

own purposes. This means that the vast bulk of the<br />

go v ernmen t bur e a u c r a c y are not rea I I Y mem be r s 0 f the<br />

el i te except in the broades t sense of the term, but<br />

rather conscious or unconscious servants of that group.<br />

It also means that, <strong>and</strong> this is perhaps more important,<br />

the essence of the state has remained unchanged from<br />

p rim i t i'v e time s • It isstill the ins tituti ona 1 i za t ion<br />

oft h e po lit i cal means for the purpose of the trans fer<br />

of wealth from the producing group to the exploiting or<br />

ruling group.<br />

Though it might at first seem paradoxical, the Individualist<br />

anarchists believe that the rUling group of<br />

today is composed of the upper echelons of the capitalist<br />

class, or what Walter Grinder refers to as the<br />

ttcorporate-financial super-rich. tt They reason as follows.<br />

The pos i t i on of the entrepreneur on the market<br />

i sal waysinsecu r e . Jus t as the rna r ke t prov idesopp 0 r ­<br />

tunities for the acquisition of wealth, it also pre-<br />

93


sents the possibility of loss. This means that the ent<br />

rep r e n e ureou 1d neve r reI a x • Nos00n e r wo u I d he t r i ­<br />

umph over one competitor than he would be met by others<br />

i n ten t u p 0 n cut tingin t 0 his s hare 0 f the rna r ke t • No<br />

sooner would he uncover a lucrative area for returns on<br />

investment than other entrepreneurs would follow suit,<br />

the increasing production forcing the profit rate down.<br />

And ass 00 n ash e wo u I d fa i Ito t a ke a d van tage 0 f the<br />

latest investment opportunities or .adopt the latest<br />

met hod s 0 f produe t ion he wo u I d r iski 0 sing his i nves t ­<br />

men t tot h 0 sewhod i d. And beh i nd a I I of th i s t he r e<br />

is, of course, the ever present possibility of entrepreneurial<br />

error. Since the first concern of the capitalist<br />

is to realize a profit, <strong>and</strong> since the rigors of<br />

the market mean that this is a difficult <strong>and</strong> perpetual<br />

struggle for an ever elusive object, the capitalist has<br />

n 0 con c ern for the rna r ke t, .ass uc h • Hen c e i t wa son I y<br />

natural for him to turn, whenever possible, to the<br />

state which, with its monopoly on the use of force,<br />

could institutionalize profits by implementing various<br />

statist measures such as tariffs, subsidies, licensing<br />

res t ric t ion s, etc., inor de r to ke e p 0 uteompet i t ion,<br />

r a i s e p ric e s<strong>and</strong> ke e p wa gerat e s I ow . The f r e e rna r ke t<br />

anarchist is therefore in complete agreement with the<br />

anti-statist Albert Jay Nock's contention that, contrar<br />

y t 0 con ve n t .ion a 1 wi s d 0 m, " Arne r i can bus i ness never<br />

followed a policy of laissez faire, never wished to<br />

follow ii, never wished the <strong>State</strong> to let it alone."(43)<br />

In other words, the individualist anarchist believes<br />

that there is a natural affinity between wealth<br />

<strong>and</strong> power. Those who have political power can use it<br />

too b t a i n we a 1 t h • On the 0 the r h<strong>and</strong>, the we a I thy are<br />

able to use their wealth to obtain political power.<br />

Once in control of the state, they are in a position to<br />

use the pol i tical means to perpetuate <strong>and</strong> even enhance<br />

the i rown p 0 sit ionsin the soc i 0 - e con om i chi era r c hy •<br />

As the individualist anarchist sees it, this creates a<br />

vicious circle: wealth can be used to acquire political<br />

power which in turn can be used to acquire more<br />

wealth. While the circle is not completely closed, its<br />

opening is certainly quite small. The "rise to the<br />

top" by tho s e fro m the lower e con om i cst rat a i s not<br />

ruled out completely. However, its occurrence which<br />

would be difficult under any circumstances is made even<br />

more so by the artificial obstacles imposed by the<br />

elite. Such, in brief, is the individualist anarchist<br />

theory of the state as an instrument of elite rule.<br />

94


6. COMMENTS AND EVALUATION<br />

Before evaluating this argument, two points need<br />

to be clarified. First, although the individualist<br />

anarchist often uses the term "class analysis" to descr<br />

i be hi s pos it ion, that term has not been used here.<br />

Instead the term "caste" has been adopted. This has<br />

been done for two reasons. First, "class analysis" is<br />

C ommo n 1 y 1 inked wi t h Marx ism. But ther e ar e fundamental<br />

differences between the Marxist <strong>and</strong> libertarian<br />

a n a 1 y s e s .. Wh i 1 e bot h see the capita lis t cIas s, 0 rat<br />

least part of that class, as the ruling group, they<br />

draw quite different conclusions from this. The<br />

Marxists believe that wealth itself confers power <strong>and</strong><br />

hence that the only means to end exploitation is to<br />

nat ion a liz e the mea ns 0 f prod uc t ion • The f r e e rna r ke t<br />

anarchist, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, argues that wealth does<br />

not init s elf con fer power sin c e the capit a lis t ca n<br />

ma i n t a i n his posit ion 0 nthe f r e e rna r ke ton I y by s e r ving<br />

others better than anyone else. Since the state is<br />

the 0 n I y mea n·s for the ins tit uti ona 1 i za t ion 0 f pr 0fit,<br />

the individualist anarchist believes that "the<br />

<strong>State</strong>, as the institutionalization of force, is the<br />

source of all exploi tat ion, either directly or indirectly."(44)<br />

Thus, while the Marxist sees private property<br />

<strong>and</strong> wealth inequality as the sources of exploitat<br />

ion the i n d i v i d ua lis tanarchis t s e 'e s. i tin the s tat e .<br />

Con seq u e n t 1y, the Ma r xis top t s for the nat iona liza t ion<br />

oft hem e a n s 0 f produe t ion; the f r e e rna r ketanarchis t<br />

advocates the abol it ion of the state.(45) To avoid<br />

confusion with its Marxian counterpart the anarchist<br />

position is referred to as a "caste analysis."<br />

Second, <strong>and</strong> more important, the term "caste" more<br />

accurately denotes the anarchist position than "class."<br />

The key distinction between "class" <strong>and</strong> "caste" is that<br />

the former is characterized by fluidity; the latter by<br />

rigidity. Individuals may move into <strong>and</strong> out of a<br />

class; such movement is precisely what is missing in a<br />

caste.(46)<br />

The distinction is crucial for grasping the anarchi<br />

s tan a I y sis . I tis a c ha rae t e r i s tic 0 f the rna r ke t<br />

process that wealth is dispersed unevenly. But if the<br />

market is free there are no external impediments preventing<br />

an individual, or even an entire group, from<br />

rising from a lower to a higher economic position. For<br />

e x amp Ie, the vas t rna j 0 r i t Y 0 f i mm i gran t s t 0 Am e rica<br />

we repennil e s sup0 nthe irar r i val. This we s a s t ric t 1Y<br />

t em p 0 r a r y phas e . Aft era d jus tin g t 0 Am e rica n I i fe,<br />

95


which usually meant adjusting to the shock of moving<br />

from a rural to an urban environment, these individuals,<br />

<strong>and</strong> in fact entire ethnic groups, began to ascend<br />

the economic ladder, their places at the bottom being<br />

t a ken b y sue c e e din g ge nera t ion s 0 f i mm i gran t s • Thus,<br />

wh i let her e is a perma nen t "bo t tom twen type r cen t" the<br />

i nd i v i dua 1 occupan ts of that category were constant ly<br />

changing.(47) In brief, markets produce classes.<br />

In contrast, a caste is characterized by its rigid<br />

i t y: on e bo r n in t 0 a cas t e r ema ins in i t for 1 i f e. If<br />

the individualist anarchist is correct <strong>and</strong> the wealthy<br />

are able to use government to institutionalize their<br />

p 0 sit ion 0 n e can ref e r tothis as the t rails forma t ion<br />

of a class into a caste. What is important for the<br />

anarchist position is that it is only through governmen<br />

t t hat a soc i 0 - e conom i cposit ion can be ins tit uti 0 n ­<br />

ali zed. Ass hown i n Fig. 1, t his me a n s t hat wh i 1e rna r ­<br />

ket results in classes, governments produce castes.<br />

These concepts are pure types. The question is not:<br />

wh i ch is pr esent class or caste? Elements of both can<br />

market<br />

government<br />

I <br />

class<br />

caste<br />

(fluidity; movement<br />

(rigidity; no<br />

between groups)<br />

intergroup<br />

movement)<br />

Fig. 1: Class <strong>and</strong> Caste Distinctions<br />

be found in all societies. The key question is the<br />

cause of the relative mix of class <strong>and</strong> caste. If the<br />

anarchist analysis is correct, one would expect to find<br />

relat ively fewer castelike features, i.e., more fluidit<br />

y, i n m0 r e rna r ketor i e nted soc i e ties t han inthe m0 r e<br />

go v ernmen t d 0 min atedon e s. A d i c tat 0 r s hip wo u 1d be<br />

expected to contain more castelike features than a<br />

democracy.<br />

For both of these reasons, to avoid confusion with<br />

the Mar x ian a n a I y sis <strong>and</strong> t 0 rna ke c 1ear the a narchis t<br />

bel ief that in statist societies the distinction between<br />

the rul ing el i te <strong>and</strong> other social groups is qui te<br />

rigid, the term caste has been adopted.<br />

The second point needing clarification is the<br />

notion of conspiracy. The anarchist's caste analysis<br />

should not be interpreted as a conspiracy theory.<br />

Analyses of the distribution of power in society are<br />

96


One must admit that it is an accurate description<br />

o f d i c tat 0 r s hip s.. I nth e Sovie t Un 1 on t he Comm un i s t<br />

Party monopolizes control of the government <strong>and</strong> through<br />

it the entIre society. It is the sole political party;<br />

no 0 the r s are per mit ted toexis t . Adm iss ion tot he<br />

party is rigidly controlled with party membership kept<br />

to about five percent of the general population. Within<br />

the party power is concentrated in the h<strong>and</strong>s of a<br />

very small group known as the Politburo. Since the<br />

Pol i tburo determines its own membership, it is a selfper<br />

pet u a tin g 0 I i gar.c h y • I tis c I ear t hat pa r t y members,<br />

<strong>and</strong> in particular party officials, monopolize<br />

power. Not surprisingly, this group also "enjoys the<br />

benefits that power brings." Officially, wealth is<br />

distributed fairly evenly. But this is quite misleadi<br />

n g b e c a use 0 f the hug e econ om i c<strong>and</strong> soc i a I ben e fits<br />

that accrue to party membership. Because of these<br />

benefIts, there is a waiting list for admission to the<br />

party.<br />

Large, centralized dictatorships such as the<br />

So vie tUn ion fit the a n arc his t 's ca s t e ana I ysis: a<br />

smal I, distinct ruling group monopolizes power <strong>and</strong> uses<br />

that power for its own benefit. But what of democracies<br />

such as the United <strong>State</strong>s? Isn't it precisely<br />

bee a use d e moe raeyin t rod ucescom pet i t ion <strong>and</strong> t h us the<br />

eve r - pre sen t po s sibiii ty 0 f r emova I from 0 f f ice, t ha t<br />

the rulers neither [1] constitute a ruling caste nor<br />

[2] are able to use their power to their own advantage?<br />

Is there a rUling caste in the United <strong>State</strong>s? Although<br />

space precludes a full-scale historical investigation,<br />

the evidence is at least very suggestive.<br />

While more open than in the Soviet Union, acquiring<br />

elite positions in the United <strong>State</strong>s can hardly be<br />

said to be equally accessible to all. Political scientists<br />

Kenneth Prewitt <strong>and</strong> Alan Stone among others have<br />

concluded that the wealthiest twenty percent of the<br />

fami I ies in this country supply about ninety percent of<br />

the elite. Of the remaining ten percent about nine<br />

percent are drawn (rom families in the second twenty<br />

percent, with the remaining one percent scattered among<br />

the bottom sixty percent.(49) This is shown in FIg. 3.<br />

99


used cars, rather than direct corporations<br />

that sell them • When the list is<br />

comp i I ed of poss ible appointees to the<br />

Cabinet or possible c<strong>and</strong>idates for the<br />

ambassadorship, it seems never to include the<br />

skilled, personable, hard-working used car<br />

salesman.(51)<br />

A finale 0 n sidera t i on i s t hat i nd i v i d ua 1s tend to<br />

associate with others of the same social status. It is<br />

qui.tena t u ra 1, the n, t hat t he r u 1 i ngel i t e wo u 1d r e ­<br />

cruit most heavi ly from those with upper class backgrounds<br />

similar to their own, just as those with upper<br />

class backgrounds naturally gravitate toward elite<br />

positions. For the same reason those from lower<br />

classes tend to enter less esteemed positions. The son<br />

of the president of General Motors is far more likely<br />

t 0 b ec om e a cor po rat e ex e cut i vethan a me c han i c; t he<br />

son of a garage mechanic is much less likely to become<br />

a corporate executive than a mechanic.<br />

In br i ef, the evidence does suggest that there is<br />

a ruling elite, that this elite is largely closed <strong>and</strong><br />

tends to perpetuate itself, that elite recruitment is<br />

based on achievement but that there is a close affinity<br />

between achievement <strong>and</strong> birth. Moreover, none of this,<br />

i twa s a r g u ed, imp liesac0 ns p irac y • On the con t r a r y ,<br />

the method of recruitment <strong>and</strong> self-perpetuation is<br />

qui tena t u r a I • A1though i t rna y bet00 s t rong tore fer<br />

to the rUling elite as a caste, it does exhibit a<br />

ca s tel ike qua lit y. The ques t ion tha t now mus t be addressed<br />

is: does this elite use its position to benefit<br />

itself?<br />

Even granting the existence of a ruling elite,<br />

doesn't compet i t i on for votes insure that the rulers<br />

will be responsive to the dem<strong>and</strong>s of the ruled? According<br />

to Anthony Downs this is precisely the case.<br />

The goa I of a po 1 it i ca I party, according to the<br />

Downsian model, is to win elections. As such it can be<br />

com par edt 0 the firmin the bus i ne s s wo rId. Jus t as i n<br />

a com pet i t i v e sit ua t i on the fir m wi 11 max i rn i z e profit s<br />

by maximizing sales, so a party will win elections by<br />

ma x i m i z i n g v 0 t e s. And jus t as the profit rno t i ve i nsur<br />

e s tha t the en t repreneur wi 11 respond to the dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

of the consumer, the vote mot i ve, assuming that the<br />

voters are well informed, constrains the political entrepreneurs<br />

to respond to the dem<strong>and</strong>s of the electorate.<br />

The moment the entrepreneur, in either case,<br />

101


Responsiveness<br />

D -------------<br />

W<br />

D'<br />

Information<br />

Fig. 4: Responsiveness as a Function of Information<br />

ut iii ty, <strong>and</strong> if the number of par"ties is sufficiently<br />

small, collusion rather than competition may be the<br />

opt ima I strategy. In fact, what is most interesting is<br />

that the better informed the electroate, the greater<br />

the incentive for collusion. As shown above, the better<br />

informed the electorate the more benefits the competi<br />

t ive party would have to provide the voters. This,<br />

of co u r s e, i s precis ely Downs' po i n t • Bu t t his a 1so<br />

means the fewer the benefits retained by the party.<br />

Thus, party competition with informed voters would all<br />

but el iminate the benefits to .party members. In such a<br />

situation instead of competing against one another to<br />

serve the voters, it becomes rational for parties to<br />

col 1 udew i thon e a not her a g a ins t the v0 t e r s • Ma j 0 r<br />

issues are then avoided, the competition is limited to<br />

"advertising <strong>and</strong> product differentiation," <strong>and</strong> the voters<br />

are denied a choice on fundamental policy issues.<br />

Collusion prevents the benefits from flowing to<br />

the voters. They are retained by the parties for int<br />

ernaId i s t ributi 0 n • T hus, e i the r wa Yt ace0 r ding to<br />

Wi t tman, the voters lose. If voters are completely uninformed<br />

the parties might compete but they will adopt<br />

policies that will provide themselves with all of the<br />

benefits. With two parties, each party would have a 50<br />

percent chance of winning 100 percent of the benefits.<br />

If voters are informed parties will collude, in which<br />

case each party will have a 100 percent chance of<br />

receiving 50 percent of the benefits. This is shown in<br />

Fig. 5.<br />

103


Utility<br />

of<br />

Party<br />

B<br />

A<br />

Percent of Income<br />

A = Expected Ut iii ty wi th 50% chance of 100% of the income<br />

<strong>and</strong> 50% chance of 0% of the income (competit<br />

ion) •<br />

B = Expected Ut iIi ty wi th 100% chance of 50% of the income<br />

(collusion).<br />

Fig. 5: Party Utility Under Competition <strong>and</strong> Collusion<br />

I n b r i e f, inc 0 n t r a s t tot h e Down s ia n modeli n<br />

wh i c h par tie s are viewed ass a I e s -rna x imi z i ng fir ms ,<br />

Wittman depicts them as profit-maximizing oligolopists:<br />

Just as 01 igolopists often collude against<br />

the consumers, the parties may collude<br />

a g a ins t the v 0 t e r s • Insuc h casesthe dis ­<br />

tinct ion between multiparty systems <strong>and</strong> one<br />

party systems may not be very great.(53)<br />

F or 0 u r pur po s esit i s not nee e s s a r y to prove<br />

co II us ion, a I t hough several examples come immediately<br />

to mind: the 1940 agreement between Roosevelt <strong>and</strong><br />

Wilk i e t 0 a v 0 i d the iss u e 0 f the wa r i n Eur 0 pe ; the<br />

apparently tacit agreement between the parties to avoid<br />

such issues as civil rights in the 1950's <strong>and</strong> the war<br />

in Vietnam in the 1960's. Since Downs' model hinges on<br />

the correlation between responsiveness <strong>and</strong> information,<br />

we need only examine this relationship. Public opinion<br />

studies consistently indicate an appalling lack of political<br />

knowledge on the part of the average citizen.<br />

On 1 y abo u t f i f t y per c e n t even know t hat ea c h s tat e has<br />

two Senators; fewer still can name their Congressman or<br />

know the length of his term, much less what party he<br />

belongs to or how he voted.(54) Given this dearth of<br />

in forma t ion, mos t voters would be much closer to W,W'<br />

t han D, D'. T hat i s to say, i n for rna t ion Ieve 1s are too<br />

low to insure much in the way of responsiveness.<br />

104


u n b a I a needin f a v0 r 0 f a ( we a I thy) min 0 r i t Y.n And, he<br />

add s, pro b ab I y "a b 0 u t 90. per c e ot 0 f the peopIe cannot<br />

get i n tot he pres sur e s ystem. " ( 57 ) This me an s t hat in ­<br />

sofar as the government responds to the dem<strong>and</strong>s of int<br />

ere s t g r 0 ups, <strong>and</strong> thosedema nds are mo reor I e s s r estricted<br />

to a wealthy minority, government policies<br />

will reflect the interests of this minority. Politicians,<br />

wr i tes Al fred Cuzan, "have no incentive to redis<br />

t ribute inc 0 mea n d we a I th from t t"h e rich t to' the<br />

poor • 1 A po lit i cia n g a ins no t hi ng t ax i ng we 11 - or ganized,<br />

well-informed, high-income groups <strong>and</strong> spending<br />

the money among a larger number of unorganized lowincome<br />

people who might not even realize the benefits<br />

of the action. On the contrary, the organized, highinc<br />

0 meg r 0 ups w i I lop p 0 s e him wh i lethe uno r gani zed<br />

p 0 0 r w i I I don 0 t h i n g • " " Pol i tica I profit i s rna de, "<br />

Cuzan continues, "by taxing the uninformed <strong>and</strong> the<br />

unorganized <strong>and</strong> spending on the informed <strong>and</strong> organized."<br />

The former tend to be poor; the latter the<br />

ric h • C u zan t· e r ms t his the "i ron I a w 0 f po1 i t i ca I<br />

redistribution."(58) .<br />

Far from representing the interests of the public<br />

at large, as claimed by the pluralists, the interest<br />

group system is, in fact., almost ideally suited to the<br />

interests of a wealthy elite. Thus, neither political<br />

par tie s nor i n t eres t gr 0 ups preve n t the emerge nee 0 f a<br />

r u lingel i t e • Nor, i t wo uIdse em, dothey preve n t t hat<br />

elite from using its position to benefit itself.<br />

From the foregoing one would expect that government<br />

would make class lines more rather than less<br />

fluid. A full scale test of this hypothesis would take<br />

us too far afield. But a cursory review of the data<br />

does lend support for it.<br />

The st<strong>and</strong>ard interpretation of the Progressive<br />

Period of the late 19th <strong>and</strong> early 20th centuries holds<br />

that many businesses had achieved monopolistic positions<br />

which they were using to gouge the public. Responding<br />

to pUblic pressure government intervened to<br />

subject business to regulatory control. Recent historical<br />

<strong>and</strong> economic scholarship has largely discredited<br />

this view by showing that the business elite actually<br />

favored government regulation. Why? Far from tending<br />

toward monopolism markets in practically every area<br />

were becoming increasingly competitive. To cite a single<br />

example, in 1894, A.T.&T. was the only company in<br />

its field. By 1907 A.T.&T. found itself in competition<br />

with over 22,000 companies. Similar, if less dramatic<br />

106


oft his eve r rea c h e s the poor. M0 s t of i t get s eaten<br />

upin bur e a u eratic 0 ve r heador s' i ph 0 ned 0 f f by Pr i vat e<br />

contractors.(64)<br />

We can now conclude this chapter. According to<br />

the anarchist caste analysis the upper classes are able<br />

to use their wealth to capture control of government.<br />

They are then able to use the coercive arm of government<br />

to institutional.ize their positions. In this proces<br />

s econom i c <strong>and</strong> social mobil i ty becomes more<br />

restricted as the economic class congeals into a political<br />

caste. This holds true, according to the theory,<br />

regardless of the type of government.<br />

Although dictatorships are more castel ike than democracies,<br />

the evidence does indicate support for the<br />

anarchist position. Neither political parties nor interest<br />

groups have prevented a rUling elite from emergi<br />

n g • Wh i lethis eli t e i s not c ompietel y c losed, i t<br />

does appear to be relatively permanent enough to be<br />

termed castelike, if not actually a caste. And finally,<br />

evidence was adduced which indicates that this<br />

elite does "enjoy the advantages that power brings."<br />

108


able to the majority." Human Action (Chicago: Henry<br />

Regner y, 1966), pp. 188-89. ,<br />

(10}Those who deny the existence of the court<br />

his tor ian s s h 0 u Ide 0 n sui t Ha r ryE 1mer Ba r n e s ,<br />

"Revisionism <strong>and</strong> the Historical Blackout," in<br />

Perpetual War for Perpetual Peace, ed., Harry Elmer<br />

Barnes (Caldwell, Idaho: Caxton, 1953), 1-78. On the<br />

strategic role of the intellectual in the United <strong>State</strong>s<br />

i n man u f act uri ng the wa r ps y choI 0 g y neee s sa r y t 0 figh t<br />

the fir s two rid wa r see Ro be r t Ni s bet, The Twiii gh t 0 f<br />

Authority (New York: Oxford University Press, 1975),<br />

pp. 71-84.<br />

(ll)Nisbet, ,p. 189.<br />

(12)See, for example, Hanna Arendt, The Origins<br />

ofT0 t a lit a rian ism ( New Yo r k: Wo rid Publisher s, 19 71 ) ,<br />

pp. 341-479. The pI i ght of the atomized individual<br />

a g a ins t the s tat e i sexcelie n t I Y po r t rayed in two<br />

novels, Arthur Koestler, Darkness at Noon (New York:<br />

Bantam Books, 1972); <strong>and</strong> Franz Kafka, The Trial (New<br />

York: Vintage Books, 1969). The latter is particularly<br />

i n t rig u i n g sinc e i t wa s wr itt en prio r tot he consci 0 us<br />

development <strong>and</strong> employment of such tact ics in the<br />

1930's <strong>and</strong> 1940's by Joseph Stalin <strong>and</strong> Adolf Hitler.<br />

(13 )Wi toess, for example, the great, <strong>and</strong> at times<br />

absurd, lengths to which our government went to promote<br />

the celebrat ion of the bi-centennial. But it must be<br />

pointed out that thi's "veneration of tradition" is<br />

strictly one-sided. For while venerating particular<br />

traditions the state must simultaneously endeavor, as<br />

Nisbet points out, to sever all connections with the<br />

past that would conflict with one's duty <strong>and</strong> loyalty to<br />

the state. And in their places, he continues, the<br />

state will create "new ceremonies <strong>and</strong> symbols." Robert<br />

Nisbet, The Quest for Community (New York: Oxford<br />

University Press, 1953), pp. 194-96.<br />

( 14 ) Rot h bar d, " Anat 0 my," p p. 37 - 4 1 • Bo t h the<br />

structure <strong>and</strong> the substance of this chapter draw heavilyon<br />

"The Anatomy of the <strong>State</strong>."<br />

(15)R<strong>and</strong>olph Bourne, "The <strong>State</strong>," The World of<br />

Ran dol ph B 0 urn e, e d. L ill ian SchI isse 1 ( New Yo r k: E.<br />

P. Dut ton <strong>and</strong> Co., 19 6 5 ), Pp. 261- 62 •<br />

(16)Quoted in Albert Jay Nock, Our Enemy, The<br />

<strong>State</strong> (New York: Free Li fe Edi t ions, 1973), p. 11.<br />

Also see John C. Calhoun, A Disquisition on<br />

Go vernmen t (I n d ian a pol is: Bob b s -Me r r i I I Co., 19 5 3 ) ,<br />

pp. 25-26.<br />

( 1 7 ) Be r t ran d de J 0 u v e n e I, 0 n P owe r tIts Nat ur e<br />

<strong>and</strong> the History of Its Growth (Boston: Beacon Press,<br />

1967), pp. 100-11.<br />

(18)Ibid., p. 48.<br />

110


(19)Ibid., p. 298-99.<br />

(20)Rothbard, "Anatomy," p. 43.<br />

(21)Murray Rothbard, "Conservatism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Freedom</strong>: A<br />

Libertarian Comment," Modern Age (Spring 1961), p.<br />

219 .<br />

(22) de Jouvenel, pp. 200ff.<br />

(23)Ibid., p. 11. Compare this with Proudhon's<br />

s t r i kin g commen t t hat "D em 0 era c y i s me rei y the s tat e<br />

raised to the nth power." Cited in Robert Nisbet, "De<br />

Bonald <strong>and</strong> the Concept of the Social Group," The<br />

Journal of .the History of Ideas (June 1944), p. 326,<br />

fn.<br />

(24)Bourne, pp. 248-50.<br />

( 25 ) See Ra 1ph K. Wh i t e' s exce 11 en t Nobody Wan ted<br />

War (New York: Anchor Books, 1970), especially Part<br />

Three, "Black-And-White Thinking," pp. 241-336.<br />

(26)Nisbet, Twilight, pp.181-82.<br />

( 2 7 ) B 0 urn e, p. 2 6 O. B0 urn e 's ant i s tat ism wa s a<br />

corollary of his pacifism for, he concluded, "We cannot<br />

crusade against war without crusading implicitly<br />

against the state," p. 260. The contemporary anarchist,<br />

Paul Goodman, also noted the link between pacifIsm<br />

<strong>and</strong> anarchism. See hIS interesting article, "The<br />

Ambiguities of Pacifist Politics," Patterns of<br />

A n are h y, e d s ., Leona r d Kr i mm erman<strong>and</strong> Lew i s Per r y ( New<br />

Yo r k : Do ubI e day <strong>and</strong> Co., 19 68 ), p • 29 2 •<br />

( 28 ) The ex ten s I ve use 0 f the i n tel lee t ua I s -academics,<br />

writers <strong>and</strong> artists -- by the Wilson<br />

Administrat ion to manufacture, even prior to America's<br />

entry into World War I, a war psychology that functioned,<br />

as Bourne observed, to suppress every hInt of dissent,<br />

has long been overlooked. Thus, Nisbet's seemingly<br />

incredible comment that "the West's first real<br />

exper ience with totalitarianism -- political absolutism<br />

extended into every possible area of culture <strong>and</strong> society,<br />

education, religion, industry, the arts, local commun<br />

i ty <strong>and</strong> fami ly included, with a kind of terror always<br />

waitIng in the wings -- came with the American war<br />

state under Woodrow Wilson," (Twilight, p. 183), has<br />

a great deal of truth to it.<br />

(29)See, for example, Milton Friedman, "Playboy<br />

Interview," Playboy (May 1973), especially pp. 54,<br />

55, <strong>and</strong> 58. Also see Allan Mel tzer, Why Government<br />

Grows (Los Angeles: International <strong>Institute</strong> for<br />

Economic Research, 1976).<br />

(30)See, for example, two essays by <strong>Ludwig</strong> Von<br />

<strong>Mises</strong> in his Planning for <strong>Freedom</strong> (South Holl<strong>and</strong>,<br />

Ill.: Libertarian Press, 1969), "MIddle-of-the-Road<br />

Pol icy Lea d s t 0 Soc iali s m," pp. 1 8 - 35; <strong>and</strong> " I n f I a t Ion<br />

<strong>and</strong> Price Control," pp. 72-82. Also see John Hagel,<br />

111


III, "From Laissez-Faire to Zwangswirtschaft: The<br />

Dynamics of Interventionism," -paper presented at the<br />

sym.pos.ium on Austrian Economics, University of<br />

Hartford, 22-28 June 1975.<br />

(31)Rothbard, "Anatomy," p. 48.<br />

( 32 ) Ca I h 0 un, p • 27 •<br />

( 3 3 ) Hob be s, Lev i a t han (N ew Yo r k: Wa s h i n g ton<br />

S qua reP res s, 19 69 ) • Espe cia I I Y see Chapt e r XX I I, "0f<br />

S Ys t em e s Sub j e c t , Po 1 i ticall <strong>and</strong> Pr i vat e ," pp. 157 - 69 ,<br />

<strong>and</strong> C hapte r XX IX, "0f thoseth i ngs t hat We a ken, 0 r tend<br />

to the Dissolution of the Common-wealth," pp. 229-40:<br />

"Another infirmity of a Common-wealth is immoderate<br />

g rea t n e s s 0 faT 0 wn • • As a Iso the g rea t numbe r 0 f<br />

Corporations; which are as it were many lesser commonwealths<br />

in the bowels of a greater, like wormes in the<br />

entraylesof a naturall man."p. 239.<br />

(34)For this perspective on totalitarianism I am<br />

heavi ly indebted to Robert Nisbet, especially his In<br />

Quest of Community, pp. 121-52.<br />

(35)Jacques Ellul points out a second reason for<br />

the emphasis on getting the individual to take an act<br />

i ve pa r tin the movement. The intent is to entangle<br />

the individual in the totalitarian web by enticing him<br />

to perform actiVIties for the party or ideology. If<br />

thesec0 n f 1 i c t wit h the i nd i v i d uaI' s bel ie f s, ps y c hoi 0 ­<br />

gical stress, or "cognitive· dissonance," results. The<br />

individual desires to relieve this stress by eliminatting<br />

the conflict between his actions <strong>and</strong> his beliefs.<br />

This can be accomplished either by altering one's actions<br />

or by altering one's beliefs. But, notes Ellul,<br />

. sin c e act ion s are s t ron ger<strong>and</strong> mo r e coneret e t han be ­<br />

I iefs, <strong>and</strong> once committed cannot be retracted, the normal<br />

response is for the individual to alter his beliefs<br />

to conform with his (deviant) actions. Jacques Ellul,<br />

Propag<strong>and</strong>a, The Formation of Men's Attitudes (New<br />

York: Vintage, 1965).<br />

(36)Ibid., p. 11.<br />

(37)Aleks<strong>and</strong>er Solzhenitsyn has understood <strong>and</strong> related<br />

th-is phenomenon very clearly in his anecdote on<br />

Bukharin. Stalin, he says, put Bukharin through psychological<br />

hell by not arresting him. In his purge of<br />

the rightists, Stalin had arrested all of BUkharin's<br />

comrades. Yet Bukhar in, as leader of the rightists,<br />

was not. Hewa sin for me d 0 f the c ha r ge s rna d e a ga ins t<br />

him by his former comrades, Kamenev <strong>and</strong> Zinoviev. Much<br />

earl ier in his career he was threatened with expulsion<br />

from the Party, <strong>and</strong> Bukharin promptly renounced his<br />

views to remain in it. He was prepared to do the same<br />

thing now, but Stalin refused to answer his numerous<br />

letters. A.nd, say.s Solzhenitsyn, "no one visited him<br />

112


See my "Class Analysis <strong>and</strong> Economic Systems," The<br />

Libertarian Forum (October 1975), pp. 5-7. The same<br />

theme is pursued further in my "Karl Marx, Benjamin<br />

Tucker <strong>and</strong> Class Ana lys is," (Paper Presented at the<br />

Libertarian Scholars Conference, October 22-24,1976,<br />

New York, New York.)<br />

( 4 6 ) Gera 1 d Ve r reman, "The Con c e p t 0 f Ca s t e ," The<br />

International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (New<br />

York: Macmillan, 1968), vol. 2, pp. 333-39. There are,<br />

of course, other characteristics, such as heredity, but<br />

rigidity Beems to be the most important.<br />

( 47 ) See Thoma s S owe I I, E thn i c Amer i ca (N ew Yor k :<br />

Bas i c Boo k s, 19 81 ) • On the use 0 f e con om i csta tis tics<br />

bearing on the issue of upward mobility-see Thomas<br />

Sowell, KnOWledge <strong>and</strong> Decisions (New York: Basic<br />

Books, 1980), pp. 344 <strong>and</strong> 364-66.<br />

(48)Gaetano Mosca, The Ruling Class (New York:<br />

McGraw-Hill, 1939), p. 50.<br />

(49)Kenneth Prewitt <strong>and</strong> Alan Stone, The Ruling<br />

Elites (New York: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1973), pp. 136-37.<br />

(50) See ibid., pp. 137-38; Michael Parenti,<br />

Dern 0 c r a c y for the Few ( New Yo r k: St. Ma r tin's, 19 7 7 ) ,<br />

pp. 34- 35; Thomas Dye <strong>and</strong> Harmon Zeigler, The Irony of<br />

Dem0 c r a c y (M 0 n t ere y, Ca 1.: Dux bur y, 19 8 1 ), PP • 29 - 64 ,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Albert Jay Nock, Our Enemy.<br />

(51)Prewitt <strong>and</strong> Stone, pp. 143-44.<br />

( 5 2 ) Ant h 0 n y 0 \0 w n s, An E con om i c The 0 r y 0 f<br />

Democracy (New York: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1957).<br />

(53)Donald Wittman, "Parties as Utility<br />

Maximizers," American Political Science Review (June<br />

1973), pp. 490-98. Fig. 5 is taken from p. 497.<br />

(54)See Dye <strong>and</strong> Zeigler, p. 191.<br />

( 5 5 ) Down s, pp. 2 0 7 -76 • AIso see Go r don Tu 11 0 c k ,<br />

Toward a Mathernat i cs of Pol it ics (Ann Arbor:<br />

University of Michigan Press, 1967), pp. 82-143.<br />

(56)See David Truman, The Governmental Process<br />

(New York: Alfred Knopf, 1951); Robert Dahl, Who<br />

Governs? (New Haven: Yale, 1962); <strong>and</strong> Earl Latham,<br />

The Group Basis of Politics (New York: Octagon Books,<br />

1965).<br />

(57)E.E. Schattschneider, The Semisovereign<br />

P e 0 pie (H ill s dale, I 1 1 .: Dry den Pre s s, 197 5), pp.<br />

34-35. (58)Alfred Cuzan, "Political Profit: Taxing <strong>and</strong><br />

Spending in the Hierarchical <strong>State</strong>," American Journal<br />

of Economics <strong>and</strong> Sociology (July 1981), pp. 265-71.<br />

(59) See Gabriel Kolko, The Triumph of<br />

Conservatism (Chicago: Quadrangle Books, 1967);<br />

Gab r i elK 0 1 k 0 "P 0 we ran d Cap italismin 20 t h Cen t ur y<br />

America," Liberation (December 1970), pp. 21-26; D.<br />

114


T. Armantano, The Myths of Antitrust (New Rochelle:<br />

A r 1 i n g ton H 0 use, 1 9 7 2 ) ;. .A• S. 0 ew i ng, ItA Stat i s tica 1<br />

Test of the Success of Consolidations," Quarterly<br />

Journal of Economics (1921), pp. 84-101; Yale Brozen,<br />

"Is Government the Source of Monopoly?" The<br />

Intercollegiate Review (Winter 1968-69), pp., 67-78;<br />

<strong>and</strong> Ron aId Rado s han d Mu r ray Rot h bar d, e d s ., ANew<br />

History of Leviathan (New York: E.P. Dutton, 1971).<br />

Kolko is a New Left writer who is not at all friendly<br />

to the free market. For attempts to fit Kolko into a<br />

I ibertarian framework see Roy Childs, "Big Business <strong>and</strong><br />

the Rise of American Statism," The Libertarian<br />

Alternative, ed. Tibor Machan (Chicago: Nelson-Hall,<br />

1974); <strong>and</strong> my "The Free Market <strong>and</strong> the 'Tyranny of<br />

Wealth'," The Freeman (December 1976), pp. 749-56.<br />

( 6 0 ) Jam e sMa r tin, " Bus·i n e s san d the New 0 e a 1 , "<br />

Reason (December 1975), p. 26; Prewitt <strong>and</strong> Stone, pp.<br />

44-50; <strong>and</strong> Radosh <strong>and</strong> Rothbard, pp. 111-87.<br />

(61) Jos eph Pechman <strong>and</strong> Benjamin Okner, Who Bears<br />

The Tax Burden? (Washington, D.C.: Brookings<br />

InstItution, 197f), p. 10.<br />

(62 )Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New<br />

Yo r k: Ma cm ill an, 1974) p. 190.<br />

(63)Walter Williams, "Commentary," Newsweek<br />

(September 24, 1979), pp. 57-59.<br />

(64)AIso see George Stigler, "Director's Law of<br />

Pu b I i c Inc 0 meR e dis t ributi 0 n ," The J 0 urna 1 0 f Law <strong>and</strong><br />

Economics (April 1970), pp. 1-10; Gordon Tullock, "The<br />

Ch a r i t Y 0 f the Un c ha r ita b Ie," We s t ern Econom i c J 0 urna 1<br />

(December 1971), pp. 379-92; <strong>and</strong> my "The Government,<br />

the Market <strong>and</strong> the Poor," The Freeman (November<br />

1980), pp. 643-59.<br />

115


116


tion for the phenomenon of imperialism. This does not<br />

mean that either libertarians in general or the free<br />

mar keta narc his t sin pa r tic u I a r den y the ex i s tenceo f<br />

imp e ria 1 ism. On the con t r a r y, thereappea r s t 0 bege neral<br />

agreement that imperialism does exist, although<br />

there is nothing resembling what can be termed "the<br />

libertarian theory of imperial ism." In fact, three<br />

dis tin c t v e r s i on s can bed i s c ern ed, all 0 f wh i c h ,<br />

ass umin g the val i d i t Y 0 f Say' s Law, see the mo t i ve<br />

for ceof impe ria lism not inthe rna r ke.t but inthesta t ­<br />

ist restrictions on the market.<br />

1. THREE THEORIES OF IMPERIALISM<br />

General overproduction might be impossible. But<br />

i n t e r fer e n c e wit h the rna r ke t proc e s s dis r up t s the i nformation<br />

flow of the price mechanism, resulting in<br />

shortages of some goods <strong>and</strong> unsaleable surpluses of<br />

o the r s • Sma 1 I erna t ion s are 1 imit e d to a 11 ow ing t he<br />

economy to falter, ab<strong>and</strong>oning the interventionist policy<br />

<strong>and</strong> perm itt i ng the painful readjustment process to<br />

take place, or attempting to stimulate the economy<br />

through further domestic interventionist measures. But<br />

the larger <strong>and</strong> stronger nations have an important additional<br />

option: imperialism <strong>and</strong> aggressive nationalism.<br />

There are three types of domestic intervention that<br />

libertarians see as having imperialistic ramifications.<br />

a. Autarky.<br />

Libertarians argue that interference with the<br />

pr ice mechanism of the market has international ramificat<br />

ions which push the interventionist nation toward<br />

aut ark y, i. e ., a pol icy 0 f nat ion a lee0 nom i c self ­<br />

sufficiency. Regardless of whether the government intervened<br />

to benef i t the workers, the consumers or the<br />

entrepreneurs the effect is the same: prices for some,<br />

or in certain circumstances all, goods are forced above<br />

their would-be market prices. If wages are raised<br />

abovet h e irmar ketIevel s the i mme d i ate impact will be<br />

to raise production costs, thereby reducing the income<br />

oft h e e n t rep r e n e u r s . T his will d r i vethe rna r gina 1<br />

producers out of business <strong>and</strong> discourage additional inves<br />

tmen tin t hos e fields. The resul t ing reduct ion in<br />

output wi 11 then cause the prices in those fields to<br />

r i s e . T h us, go v ern men tin t e r ven t ion to hoi d wa gesup<br />

wi 1 1 have the same effect as attempts to hold prices up<br />

for the benefit of businessmen: domestic prices at<br />

above world-market levels. Efforts to hold prices down<br />

119


concludes, "planning means autarky."(l'2)<br />

The dilemma of intervention, however, is that<br />

wh i lei t for c esana t ion tow a r d aut ark y, c omp 1e t e<br />

autarky "is not practical anywhere." Even in a country<br />

as large <strong>and</strong> well-endowed as the United <strong>State</strong>s, there<br />

are s u c h e ssen t i a 1 rna t e ria 1s as rubber<strong>and</strong> tin t hat we<br />

do not possess.(13) But, if intervention necessitates<br />

autarky <strong>and</strong> if autarky is impossible for most countries<br />

<strong>and</strong> p 0 s sib 1 e on 1y a t very grea t s a cr. i f ices for others.<br />

the n go ve r n rn e n tin t e r ven t ion mustiead to a po 1 icy 0 f<br />

imperialism <strong>and</strong>/or war to make autarky possible.(14)<br />

Libertarians see autarky as a major factor in both<br />

world wars. The domestic interventions which were occurring<br />

with increasing rapidity during the last half<br />

of the· nineteenth <strong>and</strong> first part of the twentieth cent<br />

uri e s produeedthe pre- WorId Wa r I tar iff rna n i a • The<br />

reSUlting economic isolationism, with its consequent<br />

drive for territorial aggr<strong>and</strong>izement, made the outbreak<br />

of war only a matter of time.(IS) While immensely complicated<br />

by both the personality of Adolf Hitler <strong>and</strong><br />

the world-wide depression of the 1930's, the explanat<br />

ion for the 0 u t b reak 0 f wa r i n E ur 0 p e i n 19 39 i s fun ­<br />

damentally the same. As the depression hit Europe each<br />

nat ion adopted prohibitive tariffs as a. device to stimulate<br />

their economies by encouraging the purchase of<br />

domestically produced goods. Similarly, since every<br />

nat ion was eager to protect its wage levels against encroachment<br />

from nations with still lower wage levels,<br />

very strict anti-immigration laws were passed by all<br />

E u r 0 pea n nat ion s • The res u 1 t wa s t ha t once againa<br />

European war was made all but inevitable by the resulting<br />

drive of each nation toward autarky, i.e., for<br />

"Lebenstraum."(16)<br />

b. Planned Scarcity.<br />

A closely related view is that imperialism is a<br />

result of what may be termed a policy of "planned<br />

scarcity," i.e., granting privileges to a few firms,<br />

permitting them to restrict production in order to<br />

r a i s e p ric e s. Fir s tad van c e d by Adam Sm i t h in his<br />

critique of mercantilism as early as 1776, <strong>and</strong> in the<br />

twentieth century by Joseph Schumpeter under the rubric<br />

of "export monopolism" <strong>and</strong> by John Flynn, it has been<br />

defended more recently by Joseph Stromberg.(17)<br />

According to this theory, big business never wantedt<br />

0 bel eft a Ion e • I twa n ted to be f r e e from the<br />

121


isks of competition <strong>and</strong> to institu'tionalize its posit<br />

ion i nth e e con om i c<strong>and</strong> soc i a 1 s t rue t ur e • Sinc e t his<br />

required licensing restrictions, tariffs, subsidies <strong>and</strong><br />

the 1 ike, such economic stabilization entailed close<br />

relations with government.(18) Thus, big business quite<br />

naturally gravitated toward government, <strong>and</strong> the destruction<br />

of the political power of the southern agricultural<br />

interests in the Civil War proved to be acrit<br />

i ca I wa t er shed in Amer i can. his tory for the only opposit<br />

ion tot he' nor the r n i nd us t rialin t eres t s wa s elimi ­<br />

nated. The post-bellum period was therefore characteri<br />

zed by. g 0 v ernmentin t e r vent ion des i gned to aid big<br />

business by keeping prices up <strong>and</strong> wages down. Monopolistic<br />

privileges were granted toa few favored firms,<br />

per mit tin g them t 0 s e I I a tab0 vema r ke t price s, wh i I e<br />

tar i ffs were enacted to keep out foreign competition.<br />

Aside from the autarkical dimensions of the policy,<br />

there are other serious ramifications.<br />

S t rom be r g bel i eve s t hat ago v e r nmen t po I icy of<br />

planned scarci ty mus t, of necessity, result in imperialism.<br />

"Briefly," he says, "steep tariffs enabled a<br />

great many American firms to price their goods well<br />

above the world market levels. At these prices the<br />

quantities produced could not be sold. But to take<br />

f u I I a d van tag e 0 fee 0 nom i c s 0 f sealethesequantit i e s<br />

had to be produced. At this point, the cry went up for<br />

foreign markets for the unsold surplus."(19)<br />

A var iat ion of the foregoing' is that monopolies<br />

may be pr 0 fit a b 1 e bu t t hey become more prof i table as<br />

the area covered by the monopoly exp<strong>and</strong>s. Hence, if<br />

there is a pol it ico-economic elite powerful enough to<br />

use the government to obtain monopoly profits for<br />

thems e I vesther e i s noreas 0 n wh y they wo u I d not a Iso<br />

be powerful enough to increase their profits by exp<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

production beyond what can be sold in the home market<br />

<strong>and</strong> then using the government to extend the area of<br />

their monopoly beyond their own borders. This view,in<br />

fact, was an essential part of Adam Smith's critique of<br />

mercant i 1 ism. Permitting the colonists to trade only<br />

wi th Engl<strong>and</strong>, he noted, enabled the few favored English<br />

merchants to increase their monopoly profits far beyond<br />

what they would have been if the monopoly had been restricted.<br />

to Engl<strong>and</strong>. The only beneficiaries of mercantilism,<br />

he said, were "the rich <strong>and</strong> powerful."(20)<br />

This, according to the proponents of the theory,<br />

is a major factor in Amer ican foreign pol icy throughout<br />

the twen"tieth century, manifesting itself in the<br />

122


Spa n ish - Arne ric a n War, the two Wo rId Wa r s<strong>and</strong> the Co 1d<br />

War. Man y I i be r tar ian s are inag r e erne n t wit h the rev i ­<br />

s ion i s t his tor ian Rob e r t S mit h, wh 0 c I aims t hat the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s "wanted to preserve an international<br />

order in which the country could have the fruits of an<br />

imperial position. The British <strong>and</strong> French empires were<br />

important elements in the maintenance of this system•.•<br />

Thus ,when the Fr-ench collapsed <strong>and</strong> the British began<br />

to falter in mid-1940, the United <strong>State</strong>s officials were<br />

faced with the di lemma of when <strong>and</strong>. how militarily to<br />

engage the disruptors of the status quo."(21) Thus,<br />

the Roosevelt administration had a vested economic interest<br />

in the adoption of a policy of imperialism <strong>and</strong><br />

war.<br />

They also believe that the Truman Doctrine, which<br />

is the basis of the United <strong>State</strong>s Cold War policy, has<br />

merely supplied a new ideological justification for the<br />

consistent American foreign policy of economic expansion<br />

<strong>and</strong> global hegemony. While the American policy<br />

rna k e r ssp 0 k e 0 f c 0 mm un i s taggres s ion <strong>and</strong> the powe r 0 f<br />

the Soviet Union, this was primarily a ploy to generate<br />

popular support. In actual fact, they believe, far<br />

from fear of Soviet power, the American policy makers<br />

were well aware of the Soviet weakness vis-a-vis the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s <strong>and</strong> used this advantage to exp<strong>and</strong> American<br />

economic <strong>and</strong> political controls.(22)<br />

But a pol icy 0 f pIanned s car cityen t a i Is two s i gnificant<br />

ramifications. Not only is there unemployment<br />

resulting from the reduced production,but the result<br />

of the monopoly profits on the one h<strong>and</strong>, together with<br />

the restriction of production on the other, results in<br />

the ph e nomen 0 n 0 f sur p Ius capit a I. Wh i lethe I a t t e r<br />

may be solved by overseas expansion as Stromberg sugges<br />

t s, the problem of unemployment remains. The traditional<br />

method of h<strong>and</strong>ling unemployment in the intervent<br />

ionist system is to make government invest the savings<br />

that private business will not. But the government investment<br />

must be in areas outside the economic system,<br />

for otherwise the additional production in the<br />

areas where the government invests will force some of<br />

the private firms out of business. In that case, government<br />

investment would simply replace private investment<br />

in those areas, <strong>and</strong> neither additional investment<br />

nor job s w i I I ha ve res u I ted . Wh i leothe r pro j e c t s rna y<br />

be found, Flynn feels that since the project [1] must<br />

be 0 net hat w i I I sat i s f yeo n s e r vat i ve <strong>and</strong> t a x paying<br />

elements of the country, <strong>and</strong> [2] must be, at least in a<br />

federal system, h<strong>and</strong>led entirely at the federal level,<br />

123


pIe <strong>and</strong> interest to the government bondholders is by<br />

ado p tingap 0 1 ICy 0 fin f 1a t ion, i. e ., by Pr i nting mo r e<br />

money. Inflation, however, is seen as having an<br />

imperialistic dynamic of its own.<br />

c. Inflation.<br />

Relying heavily on the "Austrian" theory of the<br />

business cycle, some libertarians see the cause of imperial<br />

ism in inflation. Economist W&lter Grinder notes<br />

that since the state prints the money it reaps a pure<br />

economic gain from its activities. But it reaps a<br />

pol it ieal gain as well, since it is usual-ly easier for<br />

the government to finance its activities simply by expan<br />

din g the m0 n e y sup ply rat her t han at tern pting to<br />

raise taxes. But other beneficiaries of the inflationary<br />

process are also noted. "When the state buys from<br />

a 'private' contractor," says Grinder, "both the contractor<br />

<strong>and</strong> the bank have gained: the contractor, because<br />

he can pay for resources before their prices<br />

r is e, <strong>and</strong> t he bank, because its reserves <strong>and</strong> therefore<br />

its loanable funds (assets) ha ve been exp<strong>and</strong>ed. In the<br />

initial stages of inflation, it would appear, the<br />

state, the banks <strong>and</strong> the government contractors have a<br />

vested interest in inflationary polieies."(25) But regardless<br />

of why inflationary policies have been adopted,<br />

some libertarians feel that a nearly inevitable<br />

corollary of domestic inflationary policies is that of<br />

imperialism.<br />

According to the "Austrian" business cycle theory,<br />

an increase in the supply of money <strong>and</strong> credit forces a<br />

reduct ion in the rate of interest. Since interest becomes<br />

an increasingly important cost factor the further<br />

removed a stage is from the point of final consumption,<br />

the reduction stimulates production in the capital<br />

goods industries at the expense of the consumer goods<br />

i n d us t r i e s. One impor tan t conseq uen ce oJ t his accor di<br />

n g t 0 J 0 h n Hagelis t hat "comme rica 1 act i v i t y a b r 0 a d<br />

wi 11 therefore be increasingly supplemented by longterm<br />

investment in producing facilities--both foreign<br />

manufacturing enterprises <strong>and</strong> resource extraction ind<br />

u s t r i e s . " T his sit u a t ion i scornp0 un ded by the fa c t<br />

that since inflation encourages production in such capital<br />

goods areas as resource extraction, it will tend<br />

to encourage investment in less developed countries<br />

which ordinarily export resources to the more developed<br />

nat ionsin e x c han ge for fin ishe d good s . Co nseq ue n t I Y,<br />

inflation will tend to increase the ratio of foreign to<br />

domestic investment which, in turn, will mean that cer-<br />

125


t his recur r i n g s p e c t a c I e of increasing inventor i e s of<br />

unsaleable goods that is largely responsible, according<br />

to these theorists, for the persistent popularity of<br />

the overproduction doctrine. But if the libertarians<br />

are correct, these periodic "surpluses" are not the<br />

res uIto f g e n era I 0 ve r pro due t ion but 0 f rna linves tmen<br />

t, wh i chi n t urn 0 c cur s not fro m the rna r ke t but<br />

from the government spawned inflation.<br />

But Hagel points out that it is. no.t the objective<br />

causes of the business cycle but the subjective percept<br />

ion s 0 fit by the pol icy rna ke r s t hat de t e r mine what<br />

the pol icy wi 11 be. "Since rapid expansion of foreign<br />

investment characterized the earlier period of economic<br />

pro s per i t y, itis not sur p r i sing ," he says, "that rna ny<br />

draw the conclusion that expansion abroad provides the<br />

key to renewed domestic prosperity." Thus, "foreign<br />

markets are mistakenly perceived as an essential 'safety<br />

valve' which will permit an indefinite postponement<br />

of that period of readjustment."<br />

The s eli be r tar iansse e con sidera b 1e his tor i ca I<br />

support for this variant of the imperialistic dynamic.<br />

I ntheye a r s p rio r tot h e 0 u t b rea k 0 f the Span ish-<br />

American War in 1898 America was mired in the throes of<br />

the worst depression it had experienced up to that<br />

tim e • The cry was r a i sed t hat wh a t wa s neede d we r e<br />

"new outlets for American capital <strong>and</strong> new opportunities<br />

for American enterprise."(20) It is not generally recog<br />

n i zed t hat Roo s eve 1 t f S New De a I pol i c i e s fa i 1edt0<br />

revive the American economy during the 1930's. Unemployment<br />

was at a height of 14.6 percent even as late<br />

a s 1 9 4 O. Con seq u e n t 1Y, itis a r g ued, Ro 0 s eve I t began<br />

to look at war <strong>and</strong> foreign expansion as a cure for the<br />

economic difficulties. As New Left historian Robert F.<br />

Smith noted, "the New Deal recovery program was based<br />

par t 1 Y u P0 ntherecover y <strong>and</strong> ex pans ion 0 f for e i gn rna r ­<br />

kets."(30) Hence, the expansionist policies of Japan<br />

<strong>and</strong> Germany were viewed with increasing fear.<br />

d. Imperialism <strong>and</strong> Popular Support.<br />

If the individualist anarchists are correct, the<br />

chief beneficiaries of the combined policies of domestic<br />

intervention <strong>and</strong> foreign imperialism are the elite.<br />

And since a policy of domestic intervention is believed<br />

to restrict output, create unemployment <strong>and</strong> lower the<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard of living, <strong>and</strong> since imperialism is often<br />

accompanied by blood shed by the common man, the majori<br />

ty would seem to be the long run losers. An important<br />

127


question then becomes "why the majorities pay the expenses<br />

<strong>and</strong> fight the wars necessitated by imperial<br />

expansion."(31)<br />

One reason would seem to be that while the majority<br />

might lose in the long run the reduction in unemployment<br />

does give it an immediate gain (rom imperialism.<br />

And there is little doubt that the short run is<br />

felt more keenly than the long run. Second, <strong>and</strong> perhaps<br />

more important, is what may be termed the "1984<br />

ploy. " The 1984 ploy is seen as a me t hod used by the<br />

eli t e togen era t e po pu I a r supportf0 r its po 1ic i e s by<br />

means of conscious deception. The interventionist syst<br />

em, say s F I,Yn n, " des pit e its prom i e s 0 f a bundan c e ,<br />

nee e s sitate s g rea t per sona I <strong>and</strong> financia I sac r i fiee s ,<br />

whie h p e 0 pie cannot be i ndueedt0 rna ke i nthe i n t eres t<br />

ofor din a r y 0 b j e c t i ve s 0 f c i villi f e <strong>and</strong> wh i c h they<br />

wi 11 submi t to only when they are presented with some<br />

national crusade or adventure on the heroic model<br />

touch ing deeply the spr ings of chauvinistic pride,<br />

interest <strong>and</strong> feeling," or, he says elsewere, with "the<br />

fears of. the aggressive ambitions of other<br />

countries."(32)<br />

The classic example of this, according to the anarchist,<br />

is in the Roosevelt Administration's policy<br />

pri'or to America's entry into World War II. For the<br />

short-run reason of lifting the country out of the<br />

depress ion <strong>and</strong> for the long-run reason of preserving<br />

<strong>and</strong> promoting an internaitonal economic order conducive<br />

to American dominance, the Roosevelt Administration<br />

ado pte d a pol icy 0 f impe ria 1 ism <strong>and</strong> wa r • But a d iff i ­<br />

cult problem faced by Roosevelt was that throughout the<br />

1930's opinion polls consistently indicated that eighty<br />

per c en t of the Arne r i can People opposed enter i nga Eur 0pean<br />

war. Even as late as July, 1941, the figure remained<br />

as high as seventy-seven percent. Consequently,<br />

Roosevelt adopted a policy consciously designed to "lie<br />

us into war." Roosevelt's policy of increasing truculence<br />

toward Germany, manifested by such programs as<br />

the destroyer deal with Engl<strong>and</strong>, Lend-Lease, <strong>and</strong> conv<br />

0 yin g, wasintendedt0 prod Ge r rna nyin t 0 a t t a c king the<br />

U.S. But it was officially justified on the grounds<br />

t hat sue h a po liey 0 f "s t r eng t h" wa s neee s sa r y to ke e p<br />

us out of war. Roosevelt not only promised "again <strong>and</strong><br />

again <strong>and</strong> again" that he would not send American boys<br />

into any foreign war, but characterized his policy as<br />

one des i g ned 11 t 0 i sol ate 0 u r s e 1 ve s from wa r . nTh i s<br />

same pol.icy was followed toward Japan. Since an incident<br />

was required to swing public opinion behind him,<br />

128


ass urethe sur v i val <strong>and</strong> sueces S 0 f 1 i be r t y ," <strong>and</strong> Lyndon<br />

Johnson's "shrunken world theory of defensive war,"<br />

which held that "warfare anywhere on earth could, if<br />

the President so judged, constitute an attack on the<br />

Uni ted <strong>State</strong>s <strong>and</strong> thereby authorise him to wage 'defensive'<br />

war without congressional consent."(36) But not<br />

only did the conservatives usually adhere to the goals<br />

of "liberal internationalism," theysuppl"emented these<br />

goa I s wit h the i rown pol icy 0 fan ticomm un ism <strong>and</strong> the<br />

two bee arne a I I but i ndis ting u isha b Ie. The res u I t wa s<br />

the emergence of the "bi-partisan" foreign policy of<br />

the postwar period which, according to Bresler,. "immobil<br />

ized opposition to the executive <strong>and</strong> denied the public<br />

a focal point for debate."(37)<br />

Quite clearly, both "liberal internationalism" <strong>and</strong><br />

" i n t ern a t ion a 1 ant i c omID un ism" r e qui red a n act i ve for e ­<br />

ign pol icy. An active foreign policy in turn necessitated<br />

the centralization of power in the executive<br />

branch, <strong>and</strong> the absence of any organized foreign policy<br />

debate reSUlting from "bi-partisanship" permitted that<br />

centralization. Whether unwittingly or not, the ideology<br />

of 1 iberal internationalism, says Bresler, played<br />

into the h<strong>and</strong>s of the corporate elite who required just<br />

such an active foreign policy to insure world stability<br />

<strong>and</strong> the protection of their investments.(38) Thus<br />

"liberal internationalism" is believed to have provided<br />

the necessary ideological cloak for a policy of imperialism<br />

<strong>and</strong> economic exploitation.<br />

But whenever that policy resulted in bloody wars,<br />

<strong>and</strong> support for it began to wane, reliance on the other<br />

e 1 em e nt, the f ear 0 f for e i g n enem i es, wa s uti lize d •<br />

The active foreign policy of "liberal internationalism"<br />

includes the establishment of military bases throughout<br />

the world <strong>and</strong> these, in turn, insure that enemies<br />

wi 11 always be found when they are needed. George<br />

Lundberg commented that<br />

Ace 0 r din g toe u r r en t pol icy, 0 ur na tiona I<br />

secur i ty dem<strong>and</strong>s mi 1 i tary bases around the<br />

W 0 rid <strong>and</strong> e 1 abo rat e mil itaryes tab 1 i s hme n t s<br />

off the shores or on the frontiers of other<br />

nations. .It is solemnly affirmed that<br />

these provisions are for defense only, <strong>and</strong><br />

an ype r son , party, or foreign nat ion t hat<br />

fails to take our word for this intent is<br />

roundly abused <strong>and</strong> is accused of aggressive<br />

designs upon us.(39)<br />

130


pol icy. But this, of course, is not' history at all; it<br />

is merely dogma.<br />

What 0 f the nob j e c t i ve n e v idenee? Ha ve Am e rican<br />

i n t e r v e n t ion s c 0 inc ided wit h Ame rica n bus i ne ssint e r ­<br />

ests? Once again, the evidence provides little support<br />

of the theory. In fact, argues Slater, "There is no<br />

case in which it can persuasively be argued that Washi<br />

n g ton res 0 r t edt 0 serious covert political action or<br />

the us.e 0 far me d .for ceon beha I f 0 f pr ivateeconom i c<br />

interests as such."(45) Korea <strong>and</strong> Vietnam, America's<br />

two majorpost-1945 wars, cannot be explained by economi<br />

c factors. Both were immensely costly in both human<br />

<strong>and</strong> material terms. Yet neither nation possessed<br />

e i the r i ndis pens a b 1eraw rna t e riaIsor the 1ureof grea t<br />

markets. The same is true of such interventions as<br />

Laos, Cambodia, the Dominican Republic <strong>and</strong> Guatemala.<br />

New Left historians like Williams are aware of the diff<br />

i cui t y <strong>and</strong> h a vet r i edt 0 res cue the i r pos i t i on by<br />

claiming that such economically counterproductive interventions<br />

were necessary to preserve the capitalist<br />

system as a whole. But as Slater points out "a theory<br />

t hat iss 0 b r 0 ad t hat i tis c a pableof 'exp I a i n ing ,<br />

bot h A <strong>and</strong> its 0 P P os i te B (i n t e r ven t i on <strong>and</strong> non in t e rv<br />

e n t ion, i n t e r v e n t ion t hat i sec0 nom i c a I I Y prod uc t i ve<br />

<strong>and</strong> i n t e r ve n t ion t hat isec0 n om i c a I 1Y cos t I y). • • i s no<br />

theory at all, but simplydogma."(46)<br />

Moreover, many cases which appear on the surface<br />

to 'be in conformi ty wi th the theory do not hold up<br />

un d e r dee per a n a I y sis • I tis we 11 known t hat in the<br />

ear ly 1950's the CIA played a major role in undermining<br />

the Mossedegh government in Iran <strong>and</strong> restoring the<br />

Shah. A popular explanation of this is that the CIA<br />

intervened because Mossedegh had nationalized foreignown<br />

e d 0 i I hoi din gsin 1 9 5 1 • But s eve r a I t h i n gs rna ke<br />

this scarcely credible. First, Iran continued to receive<br />

substantial American foreign aid throughout 1952,<br />

eve n afterna t ionali z a t ion. And sec 0 nd, the r e we r e<br />

n 0 Arne ric a n - 0 wned 0 i 1 compan i esin I ran a t t his time •<br />

Thus, intervention could not have occurred to protect<br />

Am e ric a n bus i n e s sin t ere s t s • I n fa c t, sinc e Am erica<br />

was an oil exporter at this time, the cut off of<br />

Iranian oil shipments proved to be a boon for American<br />

oil interests. What actually precipi tated the CIA move<br />

was Washington's increasing unease at Iran's leftward<br />

drift, symbolized by the signing of an oil sale agreement<br />

wi th Eastern European countries. Washington felt<br />

i t e sse n t i a 1 t hat a s tab 1e, non c omm un i s t I ran be pre ­<br />

served. 'It should also be pointed out that the restor-<br />

134


This is in conformity with the th'eory. However, the<br />

stu d y a Iso s howe d t hat rna ny 0 f the co un t r i e s wit h the<br />

highest inflation rates were also relatively weak:<br />

Vietnam, Brazil, Chile, <strong>and</strong> Ug<strong>and</strong>a.(51) The conclusion<br />

seems to be that there is no relationship between<br />

inflation on the one h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> imperialism, or at least<br />

the 0 p t ion 0 f pur sui n g anirn per i a lis tic po I icy, 0 nthe<br />

other.<br />

One major problem with the theory is theassurnpt<br />

ion t hat LDes sup ply raw rna t e ria1st0 the devel 0 pe d<br />

countr ies <strong>and</strong> the latter supply manufactured goods to<br />

the LOCs. Ths distinction is unfounded. All engage in<br />

bot h res 0 u r c e ext r act ion <strong>and</strong> rna nu fa c t uri ng • The distinct<br />

ion is one of degree, not kind. Currently, over<br />

25 percent of all exports from LOCs are manufactured<br />

goo d s, <strong>and</strong> t his fig u re i srising rap i d 1Y• Co un t r i e s<br />

such as Singpore, Hong Kong, Taiwan, South Korea <strong>and</strong><br />

Brazi 1 have all become major exporters of electronic<br />

e qui pm e n t s u chas TVs<strong>and</strong> r ad i 0 s • And aut om 0 b i I e product<br />

ion has recent ly been increasing at a yearly rate<br />

of 14 percent in Brazil <strong>and</strong> nearly 10 percent in<br />

Mexico, compared to only 4.4 percent in the U.S. <strong>and</strong><br />

3.4 percent in Britain. And the Philippines, South<br />

Korea <strong>and</strong> Malaysia are also becoming major producers of<br />

aut 0 mob i 1 e s. Con ve r s ely, devel 0 pe d co un t r i e s 1 ike the<br />

U.S. are major exporters of agricultural products or,<br />

in the case of Canada, major sources of raw<br />

materials.(52)<br />

Since inflation is supposed to stimulate the resource<br />

extraction industries while harming the manufact<br />

uri n g sec tor s, <strong>and</strong> sinc e nea r I y a I I nat ions are mix ­<br />

tures of both, inflation, even granting the logic of<br />

the the 0 r y, w0 u 1 d not n e c e s sa r i I Y rna k e a nat ion mo r e<br />

d e pen den t u p 0 n "k e y raw rna t e rialinput s from a br 0 ad. t1<br />

This would depend upon such factors as what resources a<br />

country needed but had to import, what manufacturing<br />

industries it possesses <strong>and</strong> the relative mixture of<br />

resource extraction <strong>and</strong> manaufacturing.<br />

But perhaps the kernel of truth in the theory is<br />

that as a nation enters a depression <strong>and</strong> goods pile up<br />

unsold while unemployment begins to rise, there naturally<br />

begins a frantic search for new markets as outlets<br />

for these goods. And new markets usually mean foreign<br />

markets. This is plausible <strong>and</strong> it is quite possible<br />

that such considerations were at least contributing<br />

factors in some of the wafS that have occurred in the<br />

last two' centuries. But motivations are difficult to<br />

138


determine <strong>and</strong> an examination of this aspect of the<br />

theory is not possible here.<br />

However, influenced by the New Left historians<br />

man y an arc his t s, a s we have seen , be 1 ie ve that Pres i ­<br />

dent Roosevelt intentionally maneuvered the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s into a war with Japan in order to stimulate the<br />

economy <strong>and</strong> reduce unemployment. In view of the overrid<br />

i n g his tor i c a limp 0 r tanceof Ame rica's en try i n t 0<br />

W0 rid Wa r I I, 0 nemus t ask: i s t his i.n t e r pretat ion consistent<br />

with the available evidence? This much is beyond<br />

dispute. Even as late as the early 1940's the<br />

economy was still sluggish <strong>and</strong> unemployment high. The<br />

Japanese code had been broken <strong>and</strong> the leaders in<br />

Was h i n g ton, inc Iud i ng Ro 0 s eve1 t, knew t hat the J a pane s e<br />

were preparing to attack the United <strong>State</strong>s, probably on<br />

Dec e mb e r 7, but the exact tar get wasst ill un c e r t a in.<br />

And, Kimmel <strong>and</strong> Short at Pearl Harbor were not adeq<br />

u.a tel yap p r i zed 0 f t his i n for rna t ion. The reason s for<br />

this have never been clear. In Infamy, the most<br />

recent study of Pearl Harbor, historian John Tol<strong>and</strong><br />

argues that as the Office of Naval Intelligence monitor<br />

ed the approach of the Japanese a t tack force, Roosevelt<br />

was faced with three options: [1] publicize the<br />

fact that the U.S. was tracking the Japanese carrier<br />

fleet. This "would indubitably have forced Japan to<br />

turn back;" [2] take appropriate military measures inc<br />

Iud i ngin for min g Ki mm e 1 <strong>and</strong> Sh0 r t • Sinc e the suec e s s<br />

of the Japanese attack depended upon secrecy, this too<br />

would have forced them to turn back; <strong>and</strong> [3] keep<br />

Kimmel <strong>and</strong> Short <strong>and</strong> "all but a select few in ignorance."<br />

Ths last option is logical only on the assumpt<br />

ion t hat i twa s Roos eve 1t 's i n ten t ion toge t Ame rica<br />

i n tot hewa r. Thus, the thesis t hat Ro 0 s eveltdesir e d<br />

war in order to stimulate the economy is at least consistent<br />

with the known facts surrounding the Pearl<br />

Harbor catastrophe. But this by no means proves the<br />

thesis, for it is not the only one that is consistent<br />

wit h the d a t a . Anot her ex pIanat ion i s t hat Ro 0 s eve I t<br />

sincerely believed that the total destruction of<br />

Western civilization was a distinct possiblity in the<br />

absence of American intervention against Nazi Germany.<br />

Since the country was badly divided on the issue he required<br />

some dramatic event which would unify the nation<br />

<strong>and</strong> galvanize the American people for the Crusade to<br />

save Western civilization. As Tol<strong>and</strong> puts it, "The<br />

first bomb dropped on Oahu would have finally solved<br />

the pro b 1 em 0 f get tin g a n Am e ric a - - hal f 0 f wh 0 s e<br />

people wanted peace -- into the crusade against<br />

Hitler ."(53) Roosevelt's mistake, says Tol<strong>and</strong>, is that<br />

139


explained by psychological, not economic, factors.<br />

What the I i be r tar ian the 0 r i e s ass e r tis a ca usa I<br />

con nee t Ion bet weeneer t a i n domest icecon om i c po lie i e s<br />

<strong>and</strong> international conflict <strong>and</strong> war. For the most part<br />

the theories are valid in the sense of being internally<br />

consistent. Moreover, the assumptions on which they<br />

are based are plausible. This is especially true of<br />

the autarky <strong>and</strong> planned scarcity theories. It is likely,<br />

for example, that the significant increase in government<br />

regulations in practically all nations during<br />

the 1930 t s was partially responsible for the drive for<br />

autarky by both Germany <strong>and</strong> Japan, <strong>and</strong> there is little<br />

doubt that the drive for autarky was an important cause<br />

of hostilities in both the Atlantic <strong>and</strong> the Pacific.<br />

The theor ies are able to explain the relationship<br />

between particular domestic economic policies <strong>and</strong><br />

international turmoil quite well. Similarly they can<br />

b e use d topred i e t t hat ce r t a i nee0 nom i cpo1 i c i e s are<br />

likely to result in foreign conflict. But the theories<br />

cannot claim that international conflict results only<br />

from these policies. Thus, if the theories are viewed<br />

not a s the e x pIanat ion 0 f impe ria lism<strong>and</strong> wa r but a s<br />

one explanation among several, they are on solid<br />

ground.<br />

It should also be pointed out that there is no<br />

logically necessary connection between the existence of<br />

a domestic elite <strong>and</strong> a policy of imperialism <strong>and</strong> war.<br />

It is quite possible for the elite to subscribe to a<br />

policy of international conciliation or even isolation.<br />

Similarly, it is conceivable for a nation even in the<br />

absence of an el i te to adopt a policy of aggressive<br />

nat ion a lis m • T h us, the findingsin Chapt e r I I I 0 f a<br />

governing elite in the United <strong>State</strong>s coupled with the<br />

conclus ion of Chapter IV of a non-imperialistic<br />

American foreign policy is in no way contradictory.<br />

Finally, despite all the words that have been<br />

written on both sides of the imperialism debate one is<br />

compel led to ask: what does it matter? Imperialism may<br />

be viewed as a species of the broader concept of intervention,<br />

i.e., the imposition of one nation's will on<br />

another through the use of force or the threat of its<br />

use. Since libertarianism is inherently nonintervent<br />

Ion i s t, i n t e r v e n t ion wo uIdse em t 0 be a far moreimportant<br />

concept for evaluating a nation's foreign polic<br />

y t han imp e r i. a lis m. Sin c e i tis 1e s s sus c e p t i blet0<br />

definitional ambiguity it is easier to document. The<br />

141


ev i dence is abundan t <strong>and</strong> the can'c 1 us ion is clear.<br />

Historically, all powerful statist societies, includi<br />

n g bat h the u. S •. <strong>and</strong> the U. S • S •R. in the twentie t h<br />

century, have been interventionist. The difference has<br />

been merely one of degree, not one of kind.<br />

142


Capitalism (Boston: Houghton MIff} in, 1951), pp.<br />

21-23 <strong>and</strong> 67-73; H.W. Speigel, The Growth of Economic<br />

Thought (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1971), pp.<br />

261-63; <strong>and</strong> I. H. Rima, Development of Economic<br />

Analysis (Homewood, Ill.: Irwin, 1972), pp. 99-101.<br />

(11)<strong>Mises</strong>, Omnipotent Government, p. 72.<br />

(12)John Flynn, As We Go Marching (New York:<br />

Free Life, 1973), pp. 199-200; also see <strong>Mises</strong>,<br />

Omnipotent Government, p. 66.<br />

(13 )Flynn, p. 199.<br />

( 1 4 ) A sid e from F} Yn nan d Mis e s, Om nip 0 ten t<br />

Government, also see Lionel Robbins, Economic<br />

Planning <strong>and</strong> International Order (London: Macmillan,<br />

1937); <strong>and</strong> my ffThe Nature of Modern Warfare," The<br />

Freeman (Apr i 1 1972), pp. 205-11, reprinted in the<br />

The L ib e r tar ian Al t ern a t i v e, e d .• T i b 0 r Machan<br />

(Nelson-Hall, 1974), pp. 350-56.<br />

(15)The classic book on this topic is <strong>Mises</strong>,<br />

Omnipotent Government.<br />

(16)See ibid. Also see Flynn, <strong>and</strong> Charles<br />

Callan Tansill, The Back Door to War (Chicago: Henry<br />

Regnery, 1952), especially pp. 339-50, 441-42. See pp.<br />

494-508 for a description of the role of autarky in<br />

producing the war in the Pacific. Also relevant is<br />

Watershed of Empire eds., Leonard Liggio <strong>and</strong> James<br />

Martin (Colorado Springs: Ralph Myles, 1976).<br />

Especially see the selections by Murray Rothbard <strong>and</strong><br />

Robert Freeman Smith.<br />

(17)Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations, 2 vols.<br />

(New Rochelle: Arlington House, n.d.); Schumpeter;<br />

Flynn; <strong>and</strong> Joseph Stromberg, "Amer ican Monopoly<br />

S tat ism ,It The Lib e r tar ian For um ( S e p t em be r 19 7 3 ), p •<br />

1-5.<br />

(18)Flynn, pp. 193-94.<br />

(19)Stromberg, p. 2; also see Schumpeter, pp.<br />

79 - 80 •<br />

(20)See Adam Smith, 2:207-62.<br />

(21 )Rober t F. Smi th, "American Foreign Relations<br />

1920-1942," Toward a New Past ed., Barton Berstein<br />

(New York: R<strong>and</strong>om House, 1968), p. 250. For other<br />

revisionist works dealIng with America's entry into the<br />

Second World War that have influenced the anarchists<br />

see Tans ill; Harry Elmer Barnes, ed., Perpetual War<br />

for Per pet ualP e ace ( C a I dwell, I da h0: Cax ton, 19 5 3 ) ;<br />

Will i am Hen r y C ham b e rIa in, Am e rica's Sec0 nd Cr usade<br />

(Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1950); Admiral Robert<br />

Theobald, "The Final Secret of Pearl Harbor," U.S.<br />

News <strong>and</strong> World Report (April 1,1954), pp. 44-93.<br />

Also important in thIS regard is the February 1976<br />

"revisionist" Issue of Reason. For a critique of the<br />

144


Imperialism in 1891, cd. T. Greene' (Lexington: Heath,<br />

1955, pp. 21-26.<br />

( 30 ) R. F. Sm i t h, p • 24 6 •<br />

(31)Parker T. Moon, quoted in Hagel, p. 1.<br />

(32)Flynn, pp. 162 <strong>and</strong> 213. It is important to<br />

be a r i n min d t hat 0 r wei I 's 1984 wa s wr itt en in 1948<br />

<strong>and</strong> that h.is original title was actually "1948." As<br />

James Martin explains, "Orwell was not writing science<br />

fiction but describing what was already fully developed<br />

in 1948." '" Defense' Origins of the New Imperialism."<br />

Revisionist Viewpoints (Colorado Springs: Ralph<br />

Myles, 1971), p. 6 fn.<br />

(33 )Quoted in Percy Greaves, "FOR's Wa'tergate:<br />

Pearl Harbor," Reason (February 1976), p. 20.<br />

(34)The l<strong>and</strong>mark book on this interpretation is<br />

Barnes, Perpetual War, Ope ci t. Also see Tansill,<br />

e s p e cia I I Y c hap t e r XXV, 11 Ro 0 s eveItSe e ksaPretext for<br />

War wit h Ge r man y ," <strong>and</strong> Chapter XXV I, " J a pan I s Ma ne uveredin<br />

t 0 Fir i ng the Firs t Shot a t Pea r I Harb0 r • " The<br />

best pre sen tat ion 0 f the even t s i rnm e d i ate I y pre c e eding<br />

<strong>and</strong> surrounding the attack on Pearl Harbor is<br />

T he 0 bald t s "The F ina I Secret of Pear I Harb 0 r , 11 0 p. cit.<br />

Also very good are Bruce Bartlett, "The Pearl Harbor<br />

Cover-Up," Percy Greaves, "FOR's Watergate: Pearl<br />

Harb 0 r ," <strong>and</strong> Ga r y Nor t h, 11 Wo rid Wa r I I· rev i s ion ism <strong>and</strong><br />

Vie t n am, n a IIi n Reason ( Feb r ua r y 19 7 6 ) • Ro 0 s eveItt s<br />

duplicitous foreign policy is admitted even by his<br />

admirers. Thomas Bailey, The Man in the Street (New<br />

Yo r k: 1 9 4 8 ), f ran k I Y a d mit s t hat "Fran k lin Ro 0 s eve 1 t<br />

repeat e d I y dec e i vedt h eArn e ric a n P eo pie d ur i n g the<br />

period before Pearl Harbor." Bailey likens this to<br />

"the physician who must tell the patient lies for the<br />

pat i e nt' sown good. • •The coun try wa s 0 ve rwhelm i ng I Y<br />

non-interventionist to the very day of Pearl Harbor,<br />

<strong>and</strong> an over t attempt to lead the people into war would<br />

have resulted in certain failure <strong>and</strong> almost certain<br />

o u s tin g 0 f Ro 0 s eve I tin 19 40, wit h conseq uen t de f eat 0 f<br />

his ultimate aims."<br />

(35)See Robert Bresler, The Ideology of the<br />

E x e cut i ve<strong>State</strong> (Men loPark, ea I .: Ins tit ute for Huma n<br />

Studies, 1973), pp. 2-4; also see Murray Rothbard, For<br />

A New Liberty (New York: Macmillan, 1973), p. 287.<br />

(36)Arthur Schlesinger, The Imperial Presidency<br />

(New York: Popular Library, 1973), p. 183.<br />

( 3 7 ) B res I e r, p. 6. On the dome s tic aut h 0 r itarian<br />

dynamic created by a foreign policy of imperialism see<br />

Will i am Mar ina t sex c ell e n t Egalita rian ism <strong>and</strong> Emp ire<br />

( Men loPark, ea I .: Ins tit ute for Hurna neSt udies, 197 5 ) ;<br />

aI-so see R<strong>and</strong>olph Bourne, "The <strong>State</strong>," The World of<br />

Ran dol P Ii B0 urn e, e d. L ill ian SchI iss e 1 ( New Yo r k: E.<br />

146


P. Dutton, 1965), pp. 243-85.<br />

(38)Bresler, pp. 2-3.<br />

( 3 9 ) G e 0 r geL u n d b erg, " Ame rica n For e i gnP0 I icy i n<br />

the L i g h t 0 f Nat ion a I I n t ere s tat the Mid- Cen t ur y , "<br />

Perpetual War for Perpetual Peace, ed. Harry Elmer<br />

Barnes (Caldwell, Idaho: Caxton, 1953), p. 183.<br />

(40)Jerome Slater, "Is United <strong>State</strong>s Foreign<br />

Policy 'Imperialist' or 'Imperial'?," Political<br />

Science Quarterly (Spring 1976), p. 69.<br />

(41)Williams, pp. 11 <strong>and</strong> 45.<br />

(42)Robert James Maddox, The New Left <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Or ig ins 0 f the Co I d War ( P r ince t on: P r ince t on Un i ve r ­<br />

sit Y Pre s s, 19 7 3 ), pp. 1 8 - 19 • Ma d d 0 x has presen ted a<br />

devastating critique of the New Left. He painstakingly<br />

examined the sources New Left historians have relied on<br />

to bolster their thesis <strong>and</strong> discovered that when the<br />

desired evidence did not exist, which was most of the<br />

time, the y s imp I y rna n u fa c t ured i t by s P lie i n g toge the r<br />

quotat ions from different individuals or from the same<br />

individual made at widely different times or about<br />

completely different subjects. In fact, he says, they<br />

have, on occas ion, even resorted to changing words in<br />

d ire c t quo tat ion s (se e, for e x amp 1e, p • 150 ). Ma d d 0 x<br />

concludes that" it is history by irrelevant evidence,<br />

m i sus e d quo tat i ons, j urn b led fig u res <strong>and</strong> d i. s t or t ion s of<br />

documentary materials" (p. 158). This charge is dir<br />

e c ted s p e c i f i c a I I Y a t L loyd Ga r d n e r 's Archit e c t s 0 f<br />

Illusion, but it is clear that he believes it applies<br />

to most of the New Left historians including Williams,<br />

Aporovitz <strong>and</strong> Kolka.<br />

{43 )Maddox, pp. 29 -30.<br />

( 44) S I a ter, p. 70, fn. For excerpts of NSC-68 see<br />

Daniel Yergin, Shattered Peace (Boston: Houghton<br />

Miffl in, 1977), pp. 401-02.<br />

(45)Slater, p. 72.<br />

(46)It;>id., pp. 71-72.<br />

(47)John Spanier, Games Nations Play (New York:<br />

Praeger, 1978), pp. 411-12.<br />

(48)See Slater, p. 72.<br />

( 49 ) S I ate r, pp. 82- 87. A I so see Da vi d Os t e r f e 1 d ,<br />

"Assessing the New International Order: Prospects for<br />

Third World Development," The Journal of Social,<br />

Pol i tica 1 <strong>and</strong> E con 0 m i cSt udies ( S p r i n g / S umm e r 19 8 2 ) ,<br />

pp. 3-26.<br />

(50)Alan Reynolds, "Problems of the Developing<br />

Countries," Journal of International Relations<br />

(Spring 1978), p. 92.<br />

(51)Henry Hazl itt, Man vs. The Welfare <strong>State</strong><br />

(New Rochelle: Arlington House, 1969), pp. 140-52.<br />

(52)John Kimball, "The Trade Debate: Patterns of<br />

147


u. S. T r a de," <strong>and</strong> Ge 0 f f r e y God s e l'1, It Torno r row's Big<br />

Power s: ' Con f u cia n W0 r k Et hie' T hr lis t s Sma lINa t ions<br />

Into Big League," both in· World Politics, 80/81, ed.<br />

Chau T. Phan (Guilford, Conn.: Dushkin Pub., 1980), pp.<br />

1 0 7 <strong>and</strong> 1 6 3 • A Iso reI e vantis P •T. Ba ue r 's 1<strong>and</strong>ma r k<br />

work, Dissent on Development (Cambridge: Harvard<br />

University Press, 1972).<br />

(53 )John Tol<strong>and</strong>, Infamy, Pear 1 Harbor <strong>and</strong> Its<br />

Aftermath (New York: Doubleday, 1982), pp. 72-73 <strong>and</strong><br />

318.<br />

(54)ln John Tol<strong>and</strong>. Hitler (New York:<br />

Ba 11ant i ne. 19 7 6 ). p • 27 7 •<br />

148


PART 'IWO<br />

The Individualist Anarchist Paradigm<br />

Having presented the individualist anarchists'<br />

cr i t ique of government we are now ready to examine<br />

their alternative to government•.Chapter V will present<br />

various arguments for government in order to evaluate<br />

better <strong>and</strong> more clearly the individualist anarchist<br />

paradigm. Chapter VI will present the views of<br />

the major predecessor of contemporary individualist<br />

anarchism: philosophical anarchism. 'And Chapters VII,<br />

VIII <strong>and</strong> IX will present <strong>and</strong> critically analyze the<br />

contemporary individualist anarchist proposals for a<br />

society without government.<br />

149


150


which we are concerned -- is why would individuals ever<br />

give. their consent to obey the state? Why don't they<br />

flee?<br />

Plato's answer, like Locke's, is utilitarian: We<br />

benefit from it. Thus, Plato's argument is that we<br />

must obey the state because of the benefits we receive<br />

from it. And what benefits do we receiv'e? Everything.<br />

"We (the state) brought you into being, •••<br />

brought you up, educated you, gave you <strong>and</strong> all the<br />

other citizens a share of all the beautiful things we<br />

could." And since everything the individual has comes<br />

from the state, Plato logically concludes that the individual<br />

owes total allegiance to the state: "you<br />

must • do wha t ever she comm<strong>and</strong>s; you mus t bear in<br />

quiet anything she bids you bear, be it stripes or<br />

p r i son; 0 r i f she I e ads you to wa r, to be wo unded 0 r to<br />

die, t his you mu s t do, <strong>and</strong> it.isri ght; • • • i n wa r<br />

<strong>and</strong> in cour t <strong>and</strong> everywhere you must do whatever ci ty<br />

<strong>and</strong> country comm<strong>and</strong>s, or else convince her where the<br />

r igh t lies. Violence is not allowed against mother or<br />

father, much less against your country."(2) Clearly,<br />

Plato's argument for the state begins with his recognition<br />

of the obvious utility of society coupled with his<br />

realization that society presupposes order.<br />

Plato is often considered the "first great politic<br />

a I phi los 0 Pher" 0 r "the 0 ne wh 0 wo r ked 0 ut the fir s t<br />

of the great systems of political thought."(3) But politics<br />

involves competition for power; it involves confl<br />

iet between both groups <strong>and</strong> value systems. Not only<br />

was P I a t 0 awareof t his, he explie i t I Y r e j e c ted it. I n<br />

a political society, Plato remarks in the Laws, "each<br />

party watches the other in jealous apprehension of insurrecti.on.<br />

• Such societies ••• are no constitut<br />

ion a 1 s tat e s • men wh 0 are for a pa r t y, we say,<br />

are factionaries, not citizens, <strong>and</strong> their so-called<br />

rights are empty words."(4) The strife which politics<br />

en t a i led i n t rod u c e din s tab iIi t yintothe po lis. I t<br />

dissolved public life into a "whirlpool" of "incessant<br />

movement of shifting currents." Politics, Plato argued,<br />

was evidence of a diseased polis. We can then<br />

find Sheldon Wolin correct when he says that Plato was<br />

not a political philosopher at all but a philosopher of<br />

antipolitics, or perhaps more accurately, "architectoni<br />

cs." (5) Wha t he des ired was the replacement of the<br />

unseemly strife <strong>and</strong> disorder of politics by a wellordered,<br />

harmonious social order, <strong>and</strong> such order required<br />

that the social units or classes be "ar·tfully"<br />

com bin e·d i n t 0 ani n t e g rat e d wh 0 Ie. Any" me dd ling <strong>and</strong><br />

152


i n t e r c han g e betweenthe t h r e e cIasse s (t r a desrna n, a ux ­<br />

iii a r y, gua r dian) would be the grea tes t damage to the<br />

city, <strong>and</strong> would rightfully be entitled evildoing in<br />

chief . The greatest evildoing towards one's own<br />

city is injustice ..• So this is injustice. On the<br />

other h<strong>and</strong>, let us put it in this way. The opposite of<br />

this, own-dealing of each class, money-makers, assistants<br />

<strong>and</strong> guardians, each one of these doing its own<br />

bus i n e s sin the city, w0 u I d be jus tice <strong>and</strong> wo u I d rna k e<br />

the cit Y jus t • " ( 6 ) Sinceo r d e r, .p 1a. t 0 ass ume s, r equires<br />

the conscious direction <strong>and</strong> integration of the<br />

social units, the state becomes the indispensible agent<br />

not only for justice but for the good life of every<br />

individual.<br />

Plato's argument can be put in syllogistic form:<br />

1. Civil society benefits every<br />

individual.<br />

2. Civil society presupposes order.<br />

3. Order, in turn, requires the conscious<br />

direction <strong>and</strong> integration of the parts.<br />

4 . Co n sci 0 u s d ire c t i on n e ce s sit ate s a<br />

d ire c tor <strong>and</strong> the ref 0 r e e n t.a i 1 s the<br />

state.<br />

5 • The s tat e i s the ref 0 ret h e e s s en t i a 1<br />

age n t for the at t a i n men t 0 f the good<br />

life of every individual.<br />

Rousseau's argument in the Social Contract is<br />

n ear 1 y ide n tic a Ito t hat 0 f P I a to' s • ( 7 ) n I ass ume t tt<br />

says Rousseau, "that me'n have reached a point at which<br />

the obstacles that endanger their preservation in the<br />

state of nature overcome by their resistance the forces<br />

whie h e a chi n d i v i d u a I can ex e r t wit h a view t 0 rna i n ­<br />

taining himself in that state. Then .this primitive<br />

con d i t ion can nolo n g e r subsis t, <strong>and</strong> the huma n raee<br />

would perish unless it changed its mode of existen<br />

c e . tt ( 8 ) R 0 us sea u 's vehie I e for c hanging t his ttmo de<br />

of ex i s tence tt is the social contract. "Rightly understood,<br />

n says Rousseau, the terms of the contract "are<br />

reducible to one only, viz., the total alienation to<br />

the whole community of each associate with all his<br />

rights." But he adds, since "each gives himself to<br />

all, he gives himsel f to nobody; <strong>and</strong> as there is not<br />

one associate over whom we do not acquire the same<br />

rights which we concede to him over ourselves, we gain<br />

the equivalent of all that we lose, <strong>and</strong> more power to<br />

preserve what we have."(g) Clearly, Rousseau, like<br />

Plato, believes that individuals enter into civil so-<br />

153


c i e t y b e c a use 0 fit s uti lit Y <strong>and</strong> t ha t a v i a b I e soc i e t y<br />

pre sup p 0 s e s or de r • The ref 0 r e , the state , be i ng the<br />

suppl ier of order, becomes the indispensable agent for<br />

the common good.<br />

Furthermore, both Plato <strong>and</strong> Rousseau deny that the<br />

comm0 n goodis s i rn ply the wi I I 0 f the rna j 0 r j t Y• For<br />

them the common good has an objective existence which<br />

mu s t bed i s C 0 vered, not c rea ted • For PIa t 0 i t wa s the<br />

"Form of the Good;" for Rousseau, the "General Will."<br />

Bot h bel i eve d t hat the ex i s ting, ear t h 1Y soc i e t y wo u I d<br />

fun c t ion bet t e r the m0 r e c losely itapprox i rna ted the<br />

" For m 0 f the Go 0 d " 0 r the "Genera 1 Wi 1 1 • " The' c r ucia 1<br />

difference between the two lies in their methods of<br />

dis c 0 v e r y • For PIa to, the idea 0 f the c ommo n go0 d, 0 f<br />

the well-ordered, just or ideal society can be grasped<br />

only by a few who, by virtue of this insight, receive<br />

the right -- even duty to govern. "In no community<br />

wh a t so eve r ," PIa to saysin the S ta tesman, "cou I d i t<br />

happen that a large number of people received this gift<br />

of political wisdom <strong>and</strong> the power to govern by pure intel<br />

ligence which would accompany it. Only in the h<strong>and</strong>s<br />

of the select few or of the enlightened individual can<br />

we look for the right exercise of political power which<br />

isit s elf the 0 net rue con s tit uti 0 n • n tI I t rna ke s no<br />

difference," he comments, "whether their subjects be<br />

willing or unwilling."(lO) Thus, for Plato, the discovery<br />

of the common good requires the existence of a<br />

rul i ng el i te, whose purpose it is to consult the unchanging<br />

<strong>and</strong> truthful "Form of the Good" <strong>and</strong> to construct,<br />

like an artist, he says, a society in its<br />

i rna g e • ( 11 ) What P I a t 0 desir e d wa s t he rep 1acemen t of<br />

the "opinions" of politics by the "truth" of philosphy.<br />

And the constituency of the philosopher-kings, as Wolin<br />

poi n t sout, w0 u 1 d not bet he mem be r s 0 f the c omm un i t Y<br />

but rather the "idea of the good community."(12)<br />

For Rousseau, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, everyone is, at<br />

least potentially, able to perceive the common good.<br />

But in order to do so individuals must ignore their<br />

private or particular will <strong>and</strong> consciously search only<br />

for the "General Will. tt "When a law is proposed in the<br />

assembly of the people,tt Rousseau says,<br />

what is asked of them is not exactly whether<br />

they approve the propos i tion or reject it,<br />

but whether it is conformable or not to the<br />

general will, which is their own; each one in<br />

giving his vote expresses his opinion thereupon;<br />

<strong>and</strong> from the counting of the votes is<br />

154


obtained the declaration of the general will.<br />

When, therefore, the opinion opposed to my<br />

ow n pre va i Is, t hat s imp I y shows t ha t I wa s<br />

mistaken; <strong>and</strong> that what I considered to be<br />

the general will was not so. Had my private<br />

opinion prevai led, I should have done something<br />

other than I wished; <strong>and</strong> in that case I<br />

should not have been free.(13)<br />

The tot a lis m 0 f bot h P I at 0 <strong>and</strong> B.ous s ea u is ev iden<br />

t. Both see order as intr icately connected wi th <strong>and</strong><br />

indispensable for the common good; both see a vigorous<br />

state with extensive regulations as necessary for<br />

order. Thus, the state becomes the sine qua non of<br />

the common good. Anytime the "private good" conflicts<br />

wi t h the "common good" the former must yield. To rei terate<br />

Plato's remark in the Crito, "you must do whatever<br />

(the state) comm<strong>and</strong>s."<br />

b. The personalist common good.<br />

A s 1 i g h t 1Y d ifferen t ve r s ion 0 f the C omm 0 n goodis<br />

presented by the Thomist philosopher, Jacques Maritain.<br />

Be i n gaThom i s t, Mar ita inac c e p t s Ar i s tot 1e f s d i c t urn<br />

that man is a social animal. Not only the good life<br />

but survival itself is possible only in a social context.<br />

This raises the question: "Does society exist<br />

for each one of us, or does each one of us exist for<br />

soc i e t y ? n ( 1 4 ) Any if u nil ate r a 1 an swe r ," Me. r ita i n r e ­<br />

plies, would lead to either chaos, as in the former<br />

case, or totalitarianism, as in the latter. What is<br />

r e qui red i s wh a the c a I Isa" b i I ate r a 1 an s w e r • "<br />

Maritain distinguishes between the "individual" <strong>and</strong><br />

the "p e r son 0 If The i nd i v i d ua lis but "a f r a gmen t 0 f the<br />

species, a part of the universe."(15) Since the whole<br />

is, by definition, more important than its individual<br />

components, the "individual" has value only as it contributes<br />

to the "good of the whole," i.e., only as a<br />

means. Thus, the "publ ic good" or the "proper good of<br />

the whole" "relates the parts to itself alone <strong>and</strong><br />

sacrifices them to itself."(16)<br />

But if the individual is only a part, the person,<br />

on the other h<strong>and</strong>, is a whole, or an end in himself.<br />

Mar i tain, therefore, arrives at the seemingly anamolous<br />

pos i t ion t ha t "society is a whole composed of wholes. 1f<br />

The If tension" between the human being as person <strong>and</strong> the<br />

human being as individual, between the common good <strong>and</strong><br />

the public good, is only apparent, he believes. It is<br />

resolved by a double or dialectical movement of "reci-<br />

155


procal subordination": the individua·l can be sacrificed<br />

for the common good; but the common good, in turn, must<br />

"flow back" to the person.(17)<br />

More concretely, the common good obtains when "the<br />

con ere t e per son g a ins the grea t est po s sib I e me as ur e ,<br />

compat ible with the good of the whole, of real independence<br />

from the servitudes of nature."(18)· This entails<br />

bot h rig h t san d cor rei a t i ve dutie s • Ma n 's righ t sinelude<br />

"the right to exist, to keep one's body whole, to<br />

found a fami ly ., the right of association, the<br />

right to the private ownership of materia.l goods." It<br />

a Iso inc 1 udes the rig h t t 0 wo r k <strong>and</strong> t 0 f r eely ch0 0 s e<br />

one's 0 c cup a t ion, the righ t to a "j us i wa ge " <strong>and</strong> the<br />

right to relief, unemployment insurance, sick benefits,<br />

social security <strong>and</strong> the like.(19) Since these rights<br />

are "grounded on the very nature of man," says<br />

Ma r ita in, they "arei na lienab Ie. " ( 20 )<br />

As for man' s d uti e s, Ma r ita'i n comme n t s t hat "unlike<br />

a farmer's cooperative or a scientific association,<br />

which require the commitment of only part of the<br />

interests of the members, civil society requires the<br />

citizens to commit their lives, properties <strong>and</strong><br />

h 0 nor • " ( 2 1 ) But, he rna i n t a ins, therei s no con t r ad i ction<br />

between the person's inalienable rights <strong>and</strong> the<br />

individual's duty to, if necessary, sacrifice even his<br />

life for the good of society:<br />

the sheer fact of existing is neither<br />

the supreme good nor anyone of the absolute<br />

goods to wh i ch the person as such is ordained.<br />

It is, however, the first prerequisite<br />

condition of the person's ordination to these<br />

goods. A human life is less precious than<br />

the moral good <strong>and</strong> the duty of assuring the<br />

salvation of the community••• (22)<br />

Wh i 1 e not eve r y t h i n g t hat i sinc 1udedin Ma r ita in' s<br />

version of the common good requires the state, certainly<br />

some, perhaps most, do.<br />

We h a vetw 0 dis tin c t ve r s ion S 0 f the c omm 0 n good<br />

jus t i fie a t ion for the s tat e . The per sona listeomm 0 n<br />

good of Maritain, building on the philosophical substructure<br />

laid by St. Thomas Aquinas, differs from the<br />

total ist commond good of Plato <strong>and</strong> Rousseau in its emphas<br />

i s on the completeness, wholeness <strong>and</strong> moral transcendence<br />

of the human person <strong>and</strong> its attempt to protect<br />

the inalienable rights of the person against the de-<br />

156


m<strong>and</strong>s of the majority by including them in the meaning<br />

oft he comm0 n good. T hus, for Ma r ita in, the r e ca n be<br />

rig h t s 0 r c I aimsaga ins t the s tat e, some t h in g wh i c h<br />

P I a t 0 <strong>and</strong> R 0 u sseau, wit h the i r em phas i son tot a I submission,<br />

could never grant. What these two versions of<br />

the comm0 n goodar g ume n t for the s tat e show is not so<br />

much an agreement on the content of the common good as<br />

the belief that the state is, regardless of the content,<br />

the indispensable agent for attaining the common<br />

good.<br />

2. THE ARGUMENT FROM NECESSITY<br />

A line of reasoning similar to the public-good<br />

jus t i f i cat ion for the s tate, a 1tho ugh f 0 c using rno r e on<br />

the uti lit Y tot h e i n d i v i d u a I rat her t han the mo r a I<br />

duty of sacrifice, is the argument from necessity advanced<br />

most articulately <strong>and</strong> consistently -- some would<br />

say ruthlessly -- by Thomas Hobbes.<br />

Hobbes ut iIi zed the phi losophical fict ion of the<br />

"state of nature." According to Hobbes' mechanistic<br />

psychology , man is i n e Ie c tab I y attracted to pleasure<br />

<strong>and</strong> repelled from pain. Since the experience of pleasure<br />

presupposes life, life becomes the greatest of all<br />

goods. The fatal flaw of life in the state of nature,<br />

he rna i n ta i ns, is tha t all men are by nature equal in<br />

the sense that any man can kill any other man. The result<br />

is complete insecurity <strong>and</strong> perpetual fear. The<br />

state of nature, says Hobbes in a particularly pungent<br />

pas sage, isac0 n d i t ion 0 f " war, wh ere eve r y rna n is<br />

Enemy to every man." It is a condition<br />

wherein men live without other security, than<br />

what the i r own s t r eng t h, <strong>and</strong> the i r own i n ve n ­<br />

tion shall furnish them withal! ••• And the<br />

life of man (is) solitary, poore, nasty,<br />

brutish <strong>and</strong> short.(23)<br />

This perpetual fear of violent death, endemic to<br />

the state of nature, is a powerfUl sensation. Since<br />

man is repelled from pain he naturally tries to extricate<br />

himself from this situation. His reason informs<br />

him that if there were a code of laws which indicated<br />

what each could <strong>and</strong> could not safely do, coupled with<br />

sufficiently powerful penalties to back it up, all<br />

would have their lives secured. ThUS, if all individuals<br />

-- except, of course, the sovereign -- would surr<br />

end e r the i r "n a t u r air i g h t Tl t 0 kill, the y wo u 1d no<br />

longer have to fear being killed. No longer required<br />

157


to fear one another, man could live' in peace. Reason,<br />

con tin u e s Hob b e s, a Iso i n for ms rna n how t 0 a t t a i nth i s<br />

con d i t ion: e a chi n d i v i d u a I wi 1 I r emo ve hi ms elf from<br />

the state of nature by contracting with others similarly<br />

situated to submit to a "common sovereign," who<br />

would be limited only by the extent of his power.<br />

Man contracts out of the state of nature because<br />

such a condition is absolutely intolerable. He submits<br />

to the sovereign because submission is instrumental in<br />

experiencing pleasure, i.e., because of the benefits<br />

a c c r u i n g fro m the ex i s tenceo f the s tat e • And wh a t<br />

benef i ts accrue? Hobbes' answer is, like Plato's,<br />

everything. Without the security supplied by the<br />

sovereign, says Hobbes,<br />

there is no place for Industry; because the<br />

fruit thereof is uncertain: <strong>and</strong> consequently<br />

no Culture of the Earth; no Navigation; nor<br />

use 0 f the commod i ties t hat rna y be imp 0 r ted<br />

by Sea; no commodious Building; no Instruments<br />

of moving, <strong>and</strong> removing such things as<br />

require much force; no Knowledge of the face<br />

of the Earth; no account of Time; no Arts; no<br />

Let t e r s; noS 0 C i e t y; <strong>and</strong> wh i chi s wo r s t 0 f<br />

all cont inuall feare, <strong>and</strong> danger of violent<br />

death.(24)<br />

In contrast to Plato's state, which would supply<br />

practically everything, Hobbes' sovereign would provide<br />

only security. However, this seemingly significant<br />

difference dissolves when we realize that, for Hobbes,<br />

such secur ity is the prerequisite for everything else.<br />

Hence, like Plato, Hobbes believes that all of the social<br />

benefits we experience on a daily basis flow from<br />

the state.<br />

The crucial difference between Hobbes <strong>and</strong> the<br />

common-good advocates is that the latter believe that<br />

since the individual benefits from the state he has a<br />

corresponding moral duty to obey. No such duty exists<br />

for Hobbes. Self-preservation is the only law. The<br />

individual is under no moral obligation to obey the<br />

sovereign. He does so only because <strong>and</strong> so long as his<br />

life is better secured by submission than revolt.<br />

3. THE ARGUMENT FROM CONVENIENCE<br />

An argument simliar to but more moderate than the<br />

Hobbesia'n-necessity justification of the state is pro-<br />

158


vided in John Lock's argument from convenience.<br />

L ike Hob b e s, L 0 c k beg ins wit h rna n ina s tat e 0 f<br />

nat u r e • A s we ha ve air e a d y seen, L0 c ke rna i n t a ins t hat<br />

individuals have the right to "life, liberty <strong>and</strong> property."<br />

The law of nature, he states, "teaches all<br />

Ma n kin d wh 0 wi lib u t con suitit t ha t be i ng eq ua I <strong>and</strong><br />

independent, no one ought to harm another in his Life,<br />

Health, Liberty or Possessions."(25) Furthermore, bel<br />

i eves Locke, man is naturally both. sociable <strong>and</strong> reasonable,<br />

<strong>and</strong> most people do consult the law most of. the<br />

time. Thus, in contrast to Hobbes, Locke depicts life<br />

in the state of nature as characterized not by perpetual<br />

war of all against all but, in general, by peaceful<br />

relations among individuals. Consequently, while<br />

Hobbes derived society <strong>and</strong> all of its benefits from the<br />

state, Locke sees society as prior to the state.<br />

Nevertheless, since not everyone consults the<br />

natural law all of the time, there is a nagging element<br />

of uncertainty for which the establishment of government<br />

is the remedy.(26) While Hobbes felt that life in<br />

the state of nature was "solitary, poore, nasty, brutish<br />

<strong>and</strong> short," Locke viewed it as inconvenient. Only<br />

the state, he argues, can eliminate this residual uncertainty<br />

by translating the moral natural law into "an<br />

established, settled, known Law." Only the state can<br />

prevent the abuse that naturally results from each individual<br />

being the judge in his own case by establishing<br />

a "known <strong>and</strong> indifferent Judge, with Authority to<br />

determine all differences according to the established<br />

Law." And finally, only the state can render the execution<br />

of this law less dangerous <strong>and</strong> uncertain by<br />

establishing an executive <strong>and</strong> investing him with the<br />

"Power to back <strong>and</strong> support the sentence, when right <strong>and</strong><br />

to give it ,due Execution."(27)<br />

For all of these reasons, for a legislature, for<br />

an execut i ve <strong>and</strong> for an independent judiciary, Locke<br />

believes that the state, while not perhaps necessary,<br />

is certainly very convenient.<br />

4. THE ARGUMENT FROM NATURAL RIGHTS<br />

An argument that bears some simi larity to the<br />

Lockean-convenience justification for government is the<br />

argument from natural rights advanced by Herbert<br />

Spencer.<br />

Spencer himself subscribed to the Lockean-natural<br />

159


ights position: "Clearly the con'ception of 'natural<br />

rights' originates in the recognition of the truth that<br />

if life is justifiable, there must be a justification<br />

for the performance of acts essential to its preservation;<br />

<strong>and</strong>, therefore, a justification for those liberties<br />

<strong>and</strong> claims which make such acts possible."(28)<br />

But if every individual does in fact'have a natural<br />

right to "life, liberty <strong>and</strong> property," then they<br />

must also. have a corresponding obligation to refrain<br />

from interfering with the equal rights of others. This<br />

is what Spencer refers to as the "law of equal liberty."<br />

While similar to traditional Lockean doctrine in<br />

its emphasis on individual freedom, the argument from<br />

natural rights has the merit of rendering(29) the<br />

Lockean social contract expedient for justifying government<br />

irrelevant. For if these natural rights are<br />

indeed universally valid, it makes no difference<br />

whether any particular individual personally consented<br />

to obey the state or not. So long as the state protects<br />

rather than violates these rights it is legitimate,<br />

<strong>and</strong> its policies are legitimately binding on all<br />

individuals.(30)<br />

5 • THE ARGUMENT FRQ\1 UT I L I TY<br />

Whatis often thought to be one of the most powerful<br />

arguments for government is utilitarianism, an argument<br />

advanced in one form or another by numerous<br />

wr i ters, but commonly associated with the late eighteenth<br />

century leader of the English Philosophical<br />

Radicals, Jeremy Bentham.<br />

Bentham contemptuously dismisses natural law, tradition<br />

<strong>and</strong> contract, stating that they are nothing more<br />

than "nonsense." The only st<strong>and</strong>ard of right <strong>and</strong> wrong,<br />

Bentham asserts, following Thomas Hobbes <strong>and</strong> David<br />

Hume, is the "principle of utility." "All other principles<br />

than that of utility must be wrong."(31) And<br />

what, precisely, is meant by utility? Bentham's answer<br />

is, simply, the excess of pleasure over pain. "A thing<br />

is said to promote the interest •.. of an individual<br />

when it tends to add to the sum total of his pleasures;<br />

or, what comes to the same thing, to diminish the sum<br />

total of his pains." Thus, pleasure <strong>and</strong> pain are, he<br />

proclaims, the "st<strong>and</strong>ard of right <strong>and</strong> wrong," of good<br />

<strong>and</strong> evil.(32) Bentham now makes two crucial assumptions:<br />

first, he maintains that the only differences<br />

bet we e n va r i ous types of pI easures <strong>and</strong> pa i ns ar e quantitative',<br />

<strong>and</strong> not qualitative, <strong>and</strong> that these quanti-<br />

160


Mulford Sibley pungently notes, this can be justified<br />

on moral or natural rights, but certainly not on utilitar<br />

ian, grounds. (37) One may speak in hypothetical<br />

t e r ms, a sec 0 nom i s t sseem so f 0 nd 0 f do i ng, 0 fin d i v i ­<br />

dual "utiles," but, even granting the very dubious proposit<br />

ion that one may "quantify" onels "utility scale,"<br />

we sti 11 have no warrant for supposing that one individ<br />

uaI' ssen sat ion s 0 f pIe a sur e <strong>and</strong>. pa i n,. <strong>and</strong> t h us his<br />

"ut iIi ty scale," is the same as another's. "We do not<br />

need to ·be slavish behaviorists," Professor Lionel<br />

RObbins comments,<br />

to realize that here is not scientific eviden<br />

c e • Therei s nomeans 0 f t est i n g the rna gnit<br />

ude of At s sa t i sfact ion as compared wi th<br />

B' s. I f we tested the state of their bloodstreams,<br />

that would be a test of blood, not<br />

satisfaction. Introspection does not enable<br />

A to measure what is going on in B's mind.<br />

There is no way of comparing the satisfaction<br />

of different people.(38)<br />

How, for example, can we really know whether the<br />

amount of pleasure Jones receives from being exposed to<br />

the aroma of P-U Pipe Tobacco is greater or less than<br />

the pain or discomfort Smith undergoes by the same exposure?<br />

Thus, the "greatest happiness" formula, upon<br />

which the entire Benthamite-utilitarian ediface is<br />

bu i It, is i tsel f based upon an unproven, unprovable <strong>and</strong><br />

clearly arbitrary assumption.(39) In short, despite<br />

its seeming simplicity <strong>and</strong> plausibility, Bentham's uti­<br />

I i tar ian i sm affords no test whatsoever as to whether<br />

government action is justified in any particular case.<br />

A mu c h mo res0 phi s ticated ver s ion 0 f the c I ass i ca I<br />

ut iIi tar ian doctrine is found in the "collective goods"<br />

<strong>and</strong> "externalities" or "neighborhood effects" arguments<br />

of many contemporary economists <strong>and</strong> social scientists.<br />

The government, it is argued, is necessary to supply<br />

certain goods <strong>and</strong> services that are generally considered<br />

to be (a) essential, or at least highly desirable,<br />

<strong>and</strong> (b) incapable, or impracticable, of being<br />

supplied on the market. This incapacity derives from<br />

the bel ief that particular goods <strong>and</strong> services cannot,<br />

by the i rna t u res, bed i v idedin t 0 rna r gina I un its <strong>and</strong><br />

sol d t 0 i n d i v i d ua I buyer s . Co nseq ue n t I y, inor de r for<br />

such a good to be supplied to anyone, it must be suppI<br />

ied to everyone, i.e., it is a collective good. The<br />

reasoning behind the collective goods justification for<br />

162


government is as simple as it is persuasive. If payments<br />

for the collective good were voluntary the rational<br />

individual will, quite naturally, cease payment,<br />

since he would continue to receive the benefits of the<br />

good or service irrespective of his individual contribution.<br />

But since everyone will reason in the same<br />

fashion, no one will pay <strong>and</strong> the collective good, which<br />

everyone presumably des ires -- <strong>and</strong> in fact considers<br />

essential -- will not be provided to anyone. National<br />

defense is a good example. If·Jones were to purchase<br />

pro t e c t i· 0 n f r om a n u c I ear at tack , then his next door<br />

neighbor, Smith, will receive simultaneous protection,<br />

regardless of his payment, <strong>and</strong> vice versa. It is impossible<br />

to defend one without likewise defending the<br />

other. Thus, Jones would leave payment up to Smith <strong>and</strong><br />

Smi th would leave it up to Jones. The result is that<br />

neither would pay, <strong>and</strong> thus, the "collective good" of<br />

nat ional defense, which both desire, would be supplied<br />

to neither. Therefore in the area of collective goods,<br />

rational action leads to irrational results.<br />

Now it is certainly conceivable, especially in a<br />

very simplified two-person interface situation like<br />

that above, that Jones <strong>and</strong> Smith could arrive at some<br />

comprom i seag r e em entin wh i c h bo t h wo u Idshare a po r ­<br />

tion of the cost. But such agreements become progressively<br />

more difficult, <strong>and</strong> thus costly, the greater the<br />

number of people involved, so that while providing<br />

the s ego 0 d son the rna r ke t rn i gh t . bethe 0 ret i c a I I Y conc<br />

e i v a b Ie, i tis p ragmat i c a I I Y i rn p0 s sibIe. As Go r don<br />

Tullock points out:<br />

In many cases the bargaining costs are so<br />

h i g h t hat i nor din a r y s pee c h we wo uIdsa y<br />

that bargains were impossible. We turn,<br />

therefore, to some type of collective<br />

decision-making process; that is, some<br />

arrangement under which individuals are<br />

compelled to carry out the wishes of others.<br />

Thus we finally come to the role of the<br />

state, <strong>and</strong> this role superficially appears to<br />

be a very modest one -- that of reducing the<br />

costs of bargaining.(40)<br />

In short, certain goods <strong>and</strong> services, like national<br />

defense, police <strong>and</strong> court services, pollution control,<br />

education, roads, parks <strong>and</strong> the like, are thought<br />

to be both (a) essential <strong>and</strong> (b) collective, or at<br />

least "quasi-collective." It is therefore argued that<br />

the y can not be sup P lie d wit h 0 u t some deg r e e 0 f coe r-<br />

163


i n d 00 r s, <strong>and</strong> an ext e r na I dis e con omy ins umme r when he<br />

must put up with the smell or close his own windows.<br />

No one seriously proposes to eliminate, or even to<br />

require compensation for, all externalities. The governmen<br />

t, ace 0 r din g tot h e mo de r nut iii tar ians, wo u I d<br />

only concern itself with the most serious externalities,<br />

i. e., on 1 y when the expected cos t of government<br />

act ion is less than the actual cost of the externality.<br />

(44) Thus, whi I e We II s could smoke his pipe wi th<br />

his win dowsope nor c losed, far me r Pit c h for k wo u 1d no<br />

doubt be required to bear his "fair share" of the cost<br />

of the dam, <strong>and</strong> Fred Middleclass might receive compensation<br />

from Golden Arch Hamburgers.<br />

In brief, the modern variant of the utilitarian<br />

creed argues that "the role of government," as Milton<br />

Friedman says,<br />

i s t 0 do s 0 met h i ng t hat the ma r ke t cannot do<br />

for itself, namely, to determine, arbitrate,<br />

<strong>and</strong> en for c e the r u I e s 0 f t he game. We may<br />

also want to do through government some<br />

things that might conceivably be done through<br />

the market but that technical or similar condi<br />

t ion s r end e r i t d iff i cui t to do in t ha t<br />

way. These all reduce to cases in which<br />

strictly voluntary exchange is either exceedingly<br />

costly or practically impossible.<br />

There are two general classes of such cases:<br />

monopoly <strong>and</strong> similar market imperfections<br />

[ col lee t i vego 0 d s] <strong>and</strong> ne i ghb0 rh00d e f fee t s<br />

[externalities].(45)<br />

6. THE ARGUMENT FROM LIBERATION<br />

Laissez-faire liberalism, whether from the Lockean<br />

natural rights or the Benthamite utilitarian variety,<br />

held sway in theory, if not always in practice,<br />

throughout much of the nineteenth century. This view,<br />

a s we ha ve seen, emphas i zed the freedom of the ind i vidual<br />

from outside coercion by others or by the state<br />

itself. No individual had any legal claim on any<br />

o the ran d the 0 n 1 y lega lob I i gat ion wa s t 0 I e a veea c h<br />

other alone. The only proper function of the state,<br />

especially as far as the Lockean natural rights advocate<br />

was concerned, was simply to supply a framework<br />

wherein the freedom of the individual in the sense of<br />

freedom from outside force would be secured.<br />

165


A transformation of this classical liberal view of<br />

freedom occurred largely, but certainly not solely,<br />

through the influence of the British Idealist philosopher,<br />

Thomas Hill Green. Green was instrumental in alt<br />

e r i n g the c omm 0 n mea n i ng 0 f the t e r m libe r t y from the<br />

negative view adhered to by liberals from Locke <strong>and</strong><br />

the Bent ham i t e Ra d i c a 1st0 Her be r t S pen c e r, to a pos i ­<br />

tive view, which has come to prevail in our century.<br />

Liberty did not mean, said Green, freedom from outside<br />

constraint but freedom to do certain things. We shall<br />

probably all agree, says Green, that freedom, "rightly<br />

understood," is the greatest of all blessings. But<br />

we s h 0 U I d car e f u I I Y conside r wh a t we me a n by<br />

it. We do no t mean merely freedom from restraint<br />

or compulsion ••• We do not mean a<br />

freedom that can be enjoyed by one man or set<br />

of men at the cost of freedom to others.<br />

When we speak of freedom as something to be<br />

highly prized, we mean a positive power or<br />

capaci ty of doing or enjoying something worth<br />

doing or enjoying••• (46)<br />

Phi los 0 phi c a I I y, the j ump from L0 c kean i nd i v i d ua I ­<br />

ism toG r e en ian 0 r gani cism, from wh a t Sabine t e r ms the<br />

old to the new liberalism(47) is not as great as it may<br />

seem at first. For Green explicitly rejected Hegel's<br />

glorification of the state <strong>and</strong>, in a statement that<br />

could have been written by Locke himself, noted that<br />

"we cannot significantly speak of freedom except with<br />

reference to individual persons."(48) Thus, in retaining<br />

individual freedom as the goal of state action,<br />

Green remained true to the spirit of liberalism. But<br />

in altering the definition of freedom to cope with the<br />

conditions of poverty, disease <strong>and</strong> ignorance he be­<br />

Ii eyed wer e cr ea ted <strong>and</strong> perpetuated by the Industr ial<br />

Revolution, he deviated from the letter of the old liberal<br />

doctrine. It is in the significantly invigorated<br />

role of the state, entailed by his positive view of<br />

freedom, that Green's radical departure from classical<br />

libera lis m i s to be f 0 un d . I tis, in 0 the r wo r ds, not<br />

in the philosophical principles or goals but in the<br />

methods of implementing or realizing them that the<br />

differences between the old <strong>and</strong> new liberalisms are<br />

found.<br />

Following the tentative suggestions of John Stuart<br />

Mill in On Liberty(49) that tl a <strong>State</strong> ought to be considered<br />

as a great benefit society, or mutual insurance<br />

company,· for helping (under the necessary regulations<br />

166


for prevent ing abuse) that large proportion of its<br />

members who cannot help themselves," Green maintained<br />

that the <strong>State</strong> ought not always to be seen simply as an<br />

agent for I imiting individual freedom. On the contrary,<br />

it can bea vital <strong>and</strong> positive force in extending<br />

f r e e d 0 m • The c I ass i c a IIi be r a Is, he rna i n t a i ned, had<br />

only a "one-sided view of the function of laws; the<br />

view viz., that their only business is to prevent<br />

interference with the liberty of the individual."<br />

Cia s sicall i b era 1 ism was i n dee d v111 ua bleinthatit<br />

he I ped to get rid of many" laws which •.. were really<br />

mischievous." But its one-sidedness limited its<br />

usefulness.<br />

Ha v i n g don e its wo r k, the the0 r y now tend s to<br />

become obstructive, because in fact advancing<br />

c i v iIi z a t ion b r i ngs withit more<strong>and</strong> morei nterference<br />

with the liberty of the individual<br />

to do as he likes, <strong>and</strong> this theory affords a<br />

rea son for res i s tin g a I I posit i ve ref 0 r ms ,<br />

all reforms which involve an action of the<br />

state in the way of promoting conditions<br />

favorable to a moral life.(50)<br />

The nega t i ve view of freedom, for example, has as<br />

its corollary the absolute right of contract. But<br />

often the existing economic conditions weight the terms<br />

of the contract against the worker. The result is a<br />

perpetuation of such unnecessary, <strong>and</strong> therefore inexcusable,<br />

social maladies as poverty <strong>and</strong> disease. By<br />

I imi t ing such rr freedom, rr or rr ignorant license," the<br />

state may, says Green, actually increase the "general<br />

freedom of its members." Every injury to the health of<br />

the individual is, he argues in his lecture, "Liberal<br />

LegiSlation <strong>and</strong> <strong>Freedom</strong> of Contract,"<br />

a public injury. It is an impediment to the<br />

general freedom. to make the best of<br />

ourselves. <strong>Society</strong> is, therefore, plainly<br />

within its rights when it limits freedom of<br />

contract for the sale of labor, so far as is<br />

done by our laws for the sanitary regulation<br />

of factor i es, workshops, <strong>and</strong> mines. It is<br />

equally within its right in prohibiting the<br />

1a bo r 0 f women <strong>and</strong> young persons beyond certain<br />

hours<br />

It is similar for such things as education. Without a<br />

basic education,<br />

167


if he knew that he was poor, he would most likely<br />

propose the contrary principle." The principle of<br />

fairness dictates that all prior knowledge of one's<br />

f u t u res 0 cia I posit ion be wit hhe I d . Now, "s ince all<br />

are similarly situated <strong>and</strong> no one is able to design<br />

principles to favor his particular condition, the<br />

principles of justice are the result of a fair agreement<br />

or bargain."(53)<br />

And what would the rat ional jndividual in this<br />

" 0 rig ina 1 posit ion" c h 0 0 s e ? Two pr inc i pies wo u I d be<br />

c h 0 sen, Rawlsi n for msus wit h 0 u thesita t ion : " the<br />

fir s t r e qui res e qua 1 ·i t yin the ass i g nmen t of bas i c<br />

rig h t san d d uti e s, wh i lethe sec0 nd hoi d s t hat soc i a 1<br />

<strong>and</strong> economic inequalities, for example inequalities of<br />

wealth <strong>and</strong> authority, are just only if they result in<br />

compensat i ng benef its for everyone, <strong>and</strong> in particular<br />

for the least advantaged members of society."(54) Quite<br />

c I ear I y, the sec 0 n d prj n c i pie, wh i c h Raw1ste r ms the<br />

"difference principle," means that a truly just, or<br />

Rawlsian, society would have strict limits on the range<br />

of permissible economic inequalities.<br />

Just how much inequality would be permissible<br />

under the "difference principle" is difficult to say.<br />

For tunate 1y, i tis i r rei e van t for 0 ur pur pos e s • Wh a t<br />

is clear is that Rawls embraces what Robert Nozick has<br />

termed an "end-state" or patterned theory of justice.<br />

That is, a society is considered just provided the dist<br />

r i bu t i on of weal th is in accordance wi th a part icular<br />

pattern or design.(55) The important point here is<br />

that, as Nozick points out, "no end-state or distributional<br />

patterned principle of justice can be continuously<br />

realized without continuous interference with<br />

people's I ives."(56) Since a patterned theory of justice<br />

I ike Rawls' presupposes "continuous interference"<br />

to maintain the pattern it obviously necessitates a<br />

large <strong>and</strong> very active state.<br />

Rawls is perfectly aware of this as the functions<br />

he assigns to his state indicate. Beyond the usual<br />

fun c t ion s 0 f governmen t, RawI s propos esan " a I I 0 cat ion<br />

branch" changed with, among other things, "identifying<br />

<strong>and</strong> correcting, say by suitable taxes <strong>and</strong> subsidies <strong>and</strong><br />

by changes in the definition of property rights, the<br />

more obvious departures from efficiency caused by the<br />

fai lure of prices to measure accurately social benefits<br />

<strong>and</strong> cos t s . " The r e wo u I d a Iso be·a "s tab iii za t ion<br />

bra n c h" des i g ned to" b r i ng abo u t rea sona b I Y full employment,"<br />

<strong>and</strong> a "transfer branch," assigned the re-<br />

169


spons i b iIi ty .of insuring everyone a "social minimum."<br />

And finally there would be a "distribution branch"<br />

whose task would be "to preserve an approximate justice<br />

in distributive shares by means of taxation <strong>and</strong> the<br />

necessary adjustments in the rights of property."(57)<br />

What is of concern here is not so much the size of<br />

the s tat e 0 r the pa r ticu 1a r act i v i tiesit wo u 1dunder ­<br />

take as the realization that if justice can be shown to<br />

m<strong>and</strong>ate a particular pattern of wealth distribution,<br />

thenthestate, wh i c h the pa t t ernedthe 0 ryen t a i Is, i s<br />

ipso facto, justified.<br />

8. CONCLUSION<br />

The above br i ef survey certainly makes no claims<br />

t 0 compIe ten e s s • Nomen t ion wa s rna de 0 fAr i s tot 1e 0 r<br />

St. Augustine, Burke or Hegel. But the survey did<br />

pre sen t a va r i e t y 0 far g ume n t s for go ve r nme n t from a<br />

variety of viewpoints:<br />

1. The "common good" argument of Plato,<br />

Jean-Jacques Rousseau, <strong>and</strong> Jacques<br />

Ma r ita i nth a taIlor mos t 0 f the compon<br />

e n t s 0 f the "g 0 0 d 1 i f e" r eq u ire conscious<br />

direction <strong>and</strong> coordination <strong>and</strong><br />

thus presuppose the state;<br />

2. The "necessity" argument of Thomas<br />

Hobbes that while not all of the benefits<br />

of society presuppose the state,<br />

the y d 0 presupp0 s e 0 r de r wh i c h, i n t urn,<br />

presupposes the state;<br />

3. The" convenience" argument of John Locke<br />

that while order doesn't necessarily<br />

presuppose the state, the state does<br />

render the natural social order more<br />

stable;<br />

4. The "natural rights" argument of Herbert<br />

Spencer that the state is, if not<br />

necessary, at least justified provided<br />

i tis 1 i mitedt 0 the pro t e c t ion 0 f rna n ' s<br />

rights of "life, liberty <strong>and</strong> propertyll;<br />

5. The llmodern util.itarian" argument of<br />

Gordon Tullock <strong>and</strong> others that the state<br />

i s n e c e s s a r y t 0 suppIemen t the s h 0 r t comings<br />

of the market in two crucial areas,<br />

170


collective goods <strong>and</strong> externalities;<br />

6. The" I iberat ion" argument of T. H. Green<br />

that a strong <strong>and</strong> vigorous state can<br />

augmen t i nd i vidual freedom by el iminating<br />

obstacles to liberty; <strong>and</strong><br />

7 • The" e con 0 m i c justice n a r g ume n t 0 f J 0 hn<br />

Rawls that a strong <strong>and</strong> vigorous state<br />

is necessary in order to. pr.eserve the<br />

pattern of wealth distribution compatible<br />

with a just society.<br />

This compilation or arguments for government will<br />

prove to be an invaluable aid in assessing the capabili<br />

ties, the s t r eng t hs a s we I I as the we a kne sses, 0 f the<br />

individualist anarchist paradigm, <strong>and</strong> we will return to<br />

it after our presentation of that paradigm.<br />

171


FOOTNOTES<br />

(l)Plato, "The Crito," Great Dialogues of Plato,<br />

eds. Eric Warmington <strong>and</strong> Philip Rouse (New York:<br />

Mentor, 1956), p. 456.<br />

(2)Ibid. The totalitarian implications of<br />

P I a to' s phi los 0 P h Y a r. e mad e .. c I ear in' KariP0 pper's<br />

excellent, if controversial, The Open <strong>Society</strong> <strong>and</strong> its<br />

Enemies, The Spell of Plato, Vol. 1, (Princeton:<br />

Princeton University Press, 1966).<br />

(3)Mulford Sibley, Political Ideas <strong>and</strong><br />

Ide 0 log i es (N e w Yo r k: Ha r per <strong>and</strong> Row, 19 70 ), p. 61.<br />

Also see George Sabine, A History of Political Theory<br />

(New York: Henry Holt <strong>and</strong> Co., 1937), p. 35: The ancie<br />

n t Gr e e k s c h 0 0 Is"rna r k the beg inn i n g 0 fEur 0 pean phi­<br />

10sophy, especially in its relations with politics <strong>and</strong><br />

o the r soc i a 1st u die s • I nth i s fie I d the wr i tings 0 f<br />

Plato <strong>and</strong> Aristotle were the first great pioneering<br />

operations in the European intellect."<br />

(4)ln Sheldon Wolin, Politics <strong>and</strong> Vision<br />

(Boston: Little, Brown <strong>and</strong> Co., 1969), p. 40.<br />

(5)Wolin, pp. 38-43.<br />

(6)Plato, "The Republic," Great Dialogues of<br />

Plato, eds. Eric Warmington <strong>and</strong> Philip Rouse (New<br />

York: Mentor, 1956), p. 233.<br />

(7)The identity is not, of course, accidental.<br />

Rousseau acknowledges that his primary influence was<br />

PIa to. See Robe r t Ni s bet, " Ro us sea u <strong>and</strong> the Pol i tica I<br />

Tradi t ion," in Tradition <strong>and</strong> Revolt (New York: R<strong>and</strong>om<br />

House, 1968), p. 29 fn 22. Nisbet's article is the<br />

c I ear est <strong>and</strong> be s t pre sen tat ion 0 f Ro usseau's tho ugh t<br />

that I have read. While Nisbet makes clear the totalitar<br />

ian imp 1 i cat ionsin Ro usseau' s tho ught, the t remendous<br />

impact of Rousseau on later European thought <strong>and</strong><br />

action, especially during the French Revolution, is<br />

out 1 i ned i n J. L. Ta 1m0 n 's rna s t e r f u1study, The 0 rigins<br />

of Totalitarian Democracy (New York: Norton, 1970).<br />

(8)Jean-Jacque Rousseau, The Social Contract<br />

(New York: Washington Square Press, 1967), p. 17.<br />

(9)Ibid., p. 18 •<br />

. (10)Plato, "The <strong>State</strong>sman," Political <strong>and</strong> Social<br />

Philosophy, eds. Charles King <strong>and</strong> James McGilvray (New<br />

York: McGraw-Hill, 1973) pp. 36 <strong>and</strong> 41. We need not<br />

deal here with how the select few are to be discovered.<br />

Suffice it to say that in Book II Section 7 <strong>and</strong> Book<br />

III Section 8 of TIThe Republic,TI Plato does outline in<br />

considerable detai I a rigorous educational ordeal for<br />

this purpose.<br />

(11)Plato, l1The Republic,TI pp. 298-99.<br />

172


(12)Wolin, p. 46.<br />

(13)Rousseau, p. 113.<br />

( 1 4 ) J a c que sMa r ita in, The Per son <strong>and</strong> the Commo n<br />

Goo d (N 0 t reDarne, I n d .: Not r e Dam e Pre s s, 19 7 2 ), P .<br />

11. For a clear, if less than critical, presentation<br />

of Maritain'srather complicated <strong>and</strong> sometimes difficult<br />

argument see Charles Fecher, The Philosophy of<br />

Jacques Maritain (Westminster, Md.: Newman Press,<br />

1953), pp. 197-226.<br />

(15)Maritain, p. 38.<br />

( 16) I bid., pp.50- 51 •<br />

( 17) I bid., pp. 65- 66 •<br />

(18)Ibid., p. 54.<br />

(19)See Jacques Maritain, Man <strong>and</strong> the <strong>State</strong><br />

(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1951), p. 114.<br />

(20)Ibid., p. 101.<br />

(21 )Mar ita in, The Person <strong>and</strong> the Common Good, p.<br />

54. Also see p. 68.<br />

( 2 2 ) I bid ., p p. 6 6 -67 • "And wh en • • . rna n f r eel y<br />

accepts death," Maritain remarks, "not as an enslaved<br />

fan a tic 0 r b lin d vic tim, but a s a rna n<strong>and</strong> a cit i zen ,<br />

for the sake of his people <strong>and</strong> his country, in that<br />

very act of extraordinary virtue, he affirms at the<br />

same time the supreme independence of the person in re­<br />

I a t ion tot h e t h i n g s 0 f t his wo rid. I n los i ng itself,<br />

in the temporal sense, for the sake of the city, the<br />

per son sacr i f icesits elf, inthe m0 s t rea I <strong>and</strong> com pie t e<br />

fashion. Yet the person is not defeated. The city<br />

still serves it because the soul of man is immortal <strong>and</strong><br />

because the sacrifice gives grace one more change." p.<br />

66.<br />

(23)Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (New York:<br />

Washington Square Press, 1969), PP. 84-85.<br />

(24)Ibid. For a modern variation of the Hobbesian<br />

a r gum e n t see Win s t on Bush, "I nd i v i d ua I We I farei n<br />

Anarchy," Explorations in the Theory of Anarchy, ed.<br />

Gordon Tullock (Blacksburg: Center for the Study of<br />

Public Choice, 1972), pp. 5-18.<br />

( 25 ) J 0 h n L 0 c k e, " Second Tr eatis e ," Two Tr ea tises<br />

of Government, ed. Peter Laslett (New York: New<br />

Arne rican Lib r a r y, 1963), p. 311.<br />

( 2 6 ) I tis c I ear t hat therei s rnorethan a g r a i n 0 f<br />

truth in Professor Leo Strauss's observation that Locke<br />

is really Hobbes in sheep's clothing. But, while Locke<br />

may be Hobbes in sheep's clothing, he is not just that.<br />

See Leo Strauss, Natural Right <strong>and</strong> History (Chicago:<br />

University of Chicago Press, 1953).<br />

(27)Locke, pp. 395-99.<br />

(28)Herbert Spencer, The Man Versus the <strong>State</strong><br />

(Caldwell, Idaho: Caxton, 1960), p. 196.<br />

173


(29)Or should render. Spencer unfortunately<br />

muddied the waters of his own argument by introducing a<br />

contractual argument for government. But, as Ellen<br />

Paul has persuasively argued, the natural rights position<br />

is in conflict with the contract position: "If<br />

natural rights are proved then consent of individuals<br />

to government is purely extraneous to the question of<br />

legi t imacy" <strong>and</strong> is ,. therefore, "in contradiction to a<br />

natural rights position." See her, "Contra Spencer <strong>and</strong><br />

Nozick: The Time Frame Theory of Governmental Legitimac<br />

y " ( Pap e r Pre sen ted a t the Arne rica n Ass 0 cia t ion for<br />

the Philosophic Study of <strong>Society</strong>, October 6, 1977), pp.<br />

1 0 - 11. A Iso see Wi I I i am son Eve r s, " Soc i a I Con t r act: A<br />

Cr i t ique," The Journal of Libertarian Studies (Summer<br />

1977), pp. 185-94. For the same argument from a utilitar<br />

ian po i n t of view see Oa vi d Fr i edman, The Mach i nery<br />

ofF r e e d om (N ew Yo r k: Har per <strong>and</strong> Row, 1973), pp. 173­<br />

78.<br />

(30) Some con temporary phi losophers who argue in a<br />

Spencerian-natural rights vein are Robert Nozick,<br />

Anarchy, <strong>State</strong> <strong>and</strong> Utopia (New York: Bas i c Books,<br />

1974), <strong>and</strong> John Hospers, Libertarianism (Santa<br />

Barbara, Cal.: Reason Press, 1972). Also of interest<br />

is Ellen Paul, Ope cit., <strong>and</strong> Jeffrey Paul, "Anarchism<br />

<strong>and</strong> Nat u r a I Rig h t s ," ( Pape r Presen ted a t the Ame rica n<br />

Association for the Philosophic Study of <strong>Society</strong>,<br />

October 6, 1977).<br />

(31)Ibid., pp. 17-18.<br />

(33)Ibid., p. 18.<br />

(34) John Hallowell, Main Currents in Modern<br />

Political Thought (New York: Rinehart <strong>and</strong> Winston,<br />

1950), p. 213.<br />

(35)This is the sense which renders utilitarianism<br />

tautological. Individuals are assumed always to act so<br />

a s toma x i m i z e the i rut iii ties; but 0 ned i s cove r s wh a t<br />

i n d i v i d u a 1 s bel.i eve w i I I rna x i mi z e the i rut iii ties by<br />

looking at their actions. See <strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>, Human<br />

Action (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1963), pp. 11-29.<br />

(36)See J. W. Allen, "Jeremy Bentham," The Social<br />

<strong>and</strong> Pol i tica I Idea s 0 f Some Representat i veTh inke r s 0 f<br />

the Rev 0 1 uti 0 n a ryE r a, e d. F. J. C • He a r n s haw (N ew<br />

York: Barnes <strong>and</strong> Noble, 1967), pp. 192-93.<br />

(37)Sibley, p. 493.<br />

(38 )Lionel Robbins, The Nature <strong>and</strong> Significance<br />

of Economic Science (London: Macmillan <strong>and</strong> Co., 1962),<br />

pp. 139-40.<br />

(39)For a brilliant critique of utilitariansim<br />

from a slightly different angle see John Rawls, A<br />

Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University<br />

Press, 1911), pp. 22-23.<br />

174


176


CHAPTER VI<br />

Philos 0phicaI Anarc hism<br />

Whi Ie it is erroneous to consider anarchism merely<br />

as a particular type of socialism, it is no doubt true<br />

t ha t, with a few notable except ions such as Max<br />

S t i r n e r, John Hen r y Ma c k ay, Gu s tav· de" Mo 1 ina r i, <strong>and</strong><br />

more currently, S. E. Parker, European anarchism has<br />

been collectivist-oriented, advocating small workercontrolled<br />

communities where property would be owned by<br />

the community rather than the individual. While less<br />

pro n 0 u n c e din Pro u d h 0 nthani n Ba k un in, <strong>and</strong> s om ewha t<br />

less in Bakunin than in Kropotkin, this collectivist<br />

or i en tat ion i scI ear 1 y the do minant t r ad i t ion amo n g<br />

European anarchists.<br />

This orientation can probably be attributed, in<br />

large part at least, to environmental factors. Regulat<br />

ion, wh e the r b y the c e n t r a 1state 0 r by s om e 0 the r<br />

g 0 v ern men t a I b o.d y, wa san eve r - presen t f act 0 f I i f e<br />

throughout European history. Consequently, there was<br />

I ittle separation between state <strong>and</strong> society. Oppenheimer,<br />

for example, remarks that in Germany "the two<br />

terms were used as synonymous." And Emil Kauder points<br />

out that in Austria the Hapsburg monarchy refused to<br />

permi t the publ i cat ion of any textbo.ok based on the<br />

principles of Adam Smith until 1848. "In the eyes of<br />

the Vie n nacen s 0 r ," Ka ude r says, "Adam Smit h wa s arevolutionary.<br />

The principle of laissez faire ran coun-.<br />

ter to old Austrian statesmanShip <strong>and</strong> social<br />

philosophy."(l)<br />

Our i n g the feu d a I per i 0 d the r ewe r e rna nor sund e r<br />

the absolute control of the lords. The modern state<br />

emerged when the rising capitalist class found it necessary<br />

to destroy feudal ism in order to extend their<br />

markets. To do so, however, required the concentration<br />

of power in the central government. And so long as<br />

they controlled the state, they found little interest<br />

in decentral izing power once the destruction of the<br />

feu d a 1 s y s t em had bee n c om pIe ted. T his mean t t ha t<br />

nearly all markets were strictly regulated by the state<br />

<strong>and</strong> for the i n t ere s t s 0 f the capitali s telass. ( 2 ) I t<br />

also meant that being regulated by the state, markets<br />

could not fulfill their crucial function of indicating<br />

priorities <strong>and</strong> coordinating production by means of the<br />

dissemination of economic information throughout the<br />

177


society. It is not surprising, "therefore, that the<br />

European anarchists did not adhere to individualist<br />

premises. Their only experience with a market economy<br />

was one hampered by government restrictions established<br />

p rima r i I Y for the bene fit 0 f pa r ticu Ia r mem be r s 0 f the<br />

capitalist class. But the only alternative to the<br />

market as a method of economic coordination is some<br />

foro m 0 f d ire c t con t r 0 I, <strong>and</strong> sinc e the s tat e wa s to be<br />

eli mina t ed, there was no poss i ble method of implementing<br />

economic coordination on a large scale. Hence, it<br />

was quite natural for the European anarchists to opt<br />

for small autarkic or semi-autarkic, worker-controlled<br />

communities where production would be directly controlled<br />

by all the members.<br />

American anarchism was just as individualist as<br />

E u r 0 peananarchism wa s collec t i vis t • And t his too can<br />

probably be explained by environmental factors. Attempts<br />

were made to transplant the European feudal<br />

structure in colonial America by means of royal <strong>and</strong><br />

proprietary colonies that regulated nearly every aspect<br />

of 1 ife<strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>ed a rigid conformity. The Puritans<br />

oft heM a. s sachuse t t s Ba y Co Iony, says Eun ice Sc h us t e r ,<br />

"dem<strong>and</strong>ed of each individual absolute conformity to a<br />

s t ric t cod e 0 f tho ught<strong>and</strong> act ion - - a code i mm uta b Ie,<br />

divinely conceived, <strong>and</strong> ordained by God."(3) But these<br />

"feudal thrusts,tI almost without exception, failed due<br />

to one condi t ion absent in Europe, the open frontier.<br />

Hence, says Rothbard, "not only relative freedom, but<br />

e ve n 0 u t rig h tanarchistins tit uti ons grew up ear Iyin<br />

the interstices between the organized, despotic English<br />

colonies."(4) Individualism can be seen as a natural<br />

outgrowth of frontier conditions. As Schuster notes:<br />

The per i 0 dun dere 0 nsidera t ion wa s a period<br />

of westward expansion. Only a small portion<br />

of the country had even been observed by<br />

white men. To the West lay l<strong>and</strong> to be had<br />

for the t a kin g 0 fit • The We s t wasst i I I a<br />

haven of escape. If conditions became unb<br />

ear a b Ie, 0 r bus i n e s s f a i led, i t wasst ill<br />

poss ible for a courageous, adventurous family<br />

to assemble its worldly goods <strong>and</strong> try its<br />

fortune in the West. If they survived the<br />

attacks of the Indians, the rigors of the<br />

climate, crop failures, <strong>and</strong> all the trials of<br />

pioneer life, they did so by good fortune <strong>and</strong><br />

the i r own ph Ysica 1 s t r eng t h . In genera 1 the y<br />

did not wa n t the go ve r nrne n t to in t e r fer e wit h<br />

them. The government had not assisted them<br />

178


in the ir personal struggle. They asked only<br />

complete personal sovereignty. And although<br />

practice tended to build up fairly rigid<br />

codes of social behavior, an individualism<br />

which broached no 'organized or governmental<br />

force was the natural product of pioneer<br />

life.(5)<br />

T h us, the con d i t ions 0 fAme rica n I i f e produee d a<br />

pragmatic individualism that "asked government to int<br />

e r fer eon I y when i t wa s toth e a dvan t 8. ge 0 f the particular<br />

group to do so."(6) This individualism resulted<br />

in an antistatist ethos that at times reached outright<br />

anarchism. It is therefore not surprising to<br />

fin d, a s Cor inn e J a c k e r has r ema r ked, t hat "the mo s t<br />

recent form of anarchism to develop, individualist<br />

anarchism, waS found almost entirely in the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s."(7)<br />

The difference between the two broad types of anarchism<br />

can be briefly summed up in the fact that while<br />

col lee t i vis t .a narchism rna n i f estsits elf inthe for m 0 f<br />

a radical democracy, philosophical anarchism gives prima<br />

c y tothe" s 0 vere i gn t y 0 f the i nd i v i d ua I • "<br />

American or philosophical anarchism can be divided,<br />

chronologically, into two distinct stages. The<br />

first stage can be dated from the early seventeenth<br />

century to the first half of the nineteenth century.<br />

It was generally religious in its inspiration <strong>and</strong> "negative"<br />

in that while it supplied some excellent critiques<br />

of secular authority, its only alternative to<br />

government lay in rather vague exhortations to live<br />

according to the Christian Law of Love.<br />

Early representatives of this negative anarchism<br />

would include the Antinomians, led by Anne Hutchinson,<br />

who settled in Rhode Isl<strong>and</strong> in the 1630's <strong>and</strong> the early<br />

Quakers, who settled in Pennsylvania in the 1680's.<br />

Bot h g r 0 ups r e qui r ed t ha t the i nd i v i dua I follow God's<br />

Law, wh ich was, in the words of Quaker Robert Barclay,<br />

"written within, on the table of the heart."(8) This<br />

clearly placed the individual above all man-made<br />

law.(9) Later figures would include the Transcendentalists,<br />

such as Ralph Waldo Emerson <strong>and</strong> Henry David<br />

Thoreau, radical abolitionists like William Lloyd<br />

Gar rison <strong>and</strong> Henry C. Wr i ght, <strong>and</strong> such exponents of<br />

Christian communalism, or "religious perfectionism," as<br />

J 0 h n Hum p h r e y N0 yes <strong>and</strong> Ad i n Ba I lou, f 0 un d e r s 0 f the<br />

Oneida <strong>and</strong> Hopedale Communities, respectively.(lO)<br />

179


The s h 0 r t com i n g s 0 f wh a t S c h us t erap t I Y dubs t his<br />

"adolescent anarchism" are evident in the reply of Adin<br />

Ballou to the question "What are you going to do with<br />

the w0 1 v e s<strong>and</strong> t i g e r s 0 f h uma n kind ? " "I ha ve a righ t<br />

toe x p e c t, <strong>and</strong> I doc0 n f iden t 1Y ex Pe c t ," wrot e Ba 1 lou,<br />

"that in practi·cing the sublime virtue of non-resistance<br />

for the kingdom of heaven's sake, God will keep<br />

all that I commi t to him in perfect safety, even here<br />

on earth, as long as it is for my good to be exempted<br />

from loss <strong>and</strong> suffering. I do firmly believe that in<br />

acting out these principles steadily <strong>and</strong> consistently,<br />

I shall continue longer uninjured, longer in the enjoyment<br />

of life, longer safe from the depredations, assaults<br />

<strong>and</strong> murderous violence of wicked men, than with<br />

all the swords, guns, pistols, dirks, peace officers,<br />

sheriffs, judges, prisons <strong>and</strong> gallows in the world. If<br />

t his i s the fa i tho f a f 001, then I am will ing to be<br />

accounted a fool, till time shall test the merits of my<br />

posit ion • "( 11 ) C1ear 1y, s u c h ana r chi s m wasapp I i cab 1e<br />

only to a select few, living in small communities <strong>and</strong><br />

capable of adher ing to an extremely high st<strong>and</strong>ard of<br />

individual behavior. Its plight was best summed up by<br />

Will i am Maccall: "Benevolence shows well on one of the<br />

C h r i s t i an graces , but it cuts a poor figure as apr i me<br />

social force."(12)<br />

But beginning in the second quarter of the ninetee<br />

nth c e n t u r y, the foe u s 0 fanarchism s h i f ted from<br />

religion to economics, from "benevolence" to "selfish<br />

interest." The thrust of anarchist thought likewise<br />

shifted from the merely negative critique of government<br />

tot h e d eve I 0 pm e n t 0 f posit i ve a 1 t erna t i ve s t hat co u 1d<br />

be implemented in the absence of the state <strong>and</strong> serve to<br />

insure harmonious action among individuals.<br />

1. JOSIAH WARREN AND THE OUTL I NESFOR INDIVIDUAL<br />

SOVEREIGNTY<br />

After listening, in 1825, to a speech in Cincinnati,<br />

Ohio, by Robert Owen, Josiah Warren joined the<br />

socialist Owenite community at New Harmony, Indiana.<br />

Warren spent about a year there, after which he returned<br />

to Cincinnati to reflect upon the causes of the<br />

sudden collapse of the Owenite experiment. Warren's<br />

thought can be seen as a reaction to his experiences at<br />

New Harmony.<br />

The failure to recognize individual property<br />

rig h t s, War r en bel i eved, 1a y a t the heart 0 f the fa i lure.<br />

Communal ownership entailed the accumulation of<br />

180


es p 0 n sib iii ties wh i c h rna d e i timp0 s sib I e ,t 0 t r ace the<br />

impact 0 fan yind i v i d ua I 's act ion s . Co nseq uen t 1y, a I 1<br />

feelings of individual initiative <strong>and</strong> responsibility<br />

were lost. Furthermore, communal ownership was intended<br />

as a means to insure social cooperation. But, in<br />

Warren's view, a worse method could hardly have been<br />

found. When individual responsibilities <strong>and</strong> individual<br />

interests are accumulated, disagreements can be solved<br />

on I y bye 0 n f 1 i ct. " I f my i n t eres t we r e un i ted wit h<br />

yours," says Warren, "<strong>and</strong> we differ at any point in its<br />

management •• one must yield <strong>and</strong> the other must decide,<br />

or, we must leave the decision to a third party,"<br />

viz., a government.(13) But disagreements, he held are<br />

an inevitable fact of nature. "There are no two obj<br />

e c t sin the un i v er s e wh i c h are pr e cisely alike ," a rgues<br />

Warren's follower, Stephen P. Andrews. "Each has<br />

its own constitution <strong>and</strong> peculiarities, which distinguish<br />

it from every other. Infinite diversity is the<br />

universal law."(·14) But if individuality is indeed an<br />

immutable law of nature it follows that the more interests<br />

are combined the larger <strong>and</strong> more intense the scope<br />

of conflict. And the larger the conflict, the greater<br />

the need for more <strong>and</strong> stronger government. But government<br />

cannot create social cooperation; it can only enforce<br />

conformity. Further, the more government, the<br />

less control each individual has over his own life <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore the less free he is. The solution, thought<br />

Warren, lay in the opposite direction: the disconnection,<br />

rather than the aggregation, of interests.<br />

Since" infin·ite diversity is the universal law,"<br />

harmony can only be attained by allowing each individual<br />

the greatest possible freedom to follow his own conscience<br />

<strong>and</strong> his own desires. Harmony, in other words,<br />

can preva i I only when every individual is his own sovereign.<br />

The "sovereignty of the individual" .clearly<br />

does not mean the power to attain any goal desired by<br />

the individual. Rather, it means the freedom from restraints<br />

imposed by others upon the use of one's own<br />

life <strong>and</strong> property. Only when society is broken down<br />

into its individual parts can the law of cause <strong>and</strong> effect<br />

operate <strong>and</strong> the consequences of each individual's<br />

actions be made to redound upon himself, alone. If A<br />

can shift the costs of his actions onto B, then B is<br />

not sovereign <strong>and</strong>, therefore, not free. He is a slave<br />

w0 r kin g for the ben e fit 0 fA. Thus, f r e e dom en t a i I s<br />

each individual "living <strong>and</strong> acting at his own<br />

cos t • " ( 1 5 ) Clear I y , such a s 0 ci e t y is cons i s ten t on 1y<br />

wi th the recogn it ion of private property. As Andrews<br />

writes, "The essential condition of freedom is discon-<br />

181


neetion -- ,individualization -- disintegration of int<br />

ere s t s • T he e sse n t iale0 nd i t i on of dis eonnee t ion i s<br />

that that be given to each which belongs to eaeh."(16)<br />

But disconnection should not be construed as implying<br />

isolation. On the contrary, it is argued that only<br />

when society is completely individualized can the individual<br />

parts be free to work in harmony, voluntarily<br />

combining when it is to their benefit, <strong>and</strong> acting individually<br />

when it is not. "All harmonic unity is a result<br />

of growth from the prior individuality of the<br />

separate monads."(17) Thus, Warren believed that the<br />

individualization of society permits a highly flexible<br />

social structure capable of achieving harmony 'without<br />

either requiring or enforcing uniformity. Individualizat<br />

ion even permits cooperation among people with wide­<br />

I y dis par ate goa Is. " The 1abo r e rsin a rna n ufa c t uri ng<br />

est a b 1 ishmen t ," And r e ws poi n t sout, " ha ve no c ommo n<br />

interest, no partnership, no combined responsibilities.<br />

The ir interests are completely individual ized, <strong>and</strong> yet<br />

they work together."(18)<br />

In shor t, Warren bel ieved that society could be<br />

harmonious only if every individual were given the<br />

freedom to follow his own interests. But he could be<br />

free only if he were not involuntarily dependent upon<br />

or burdened by anyone else. Hence, the soveriegnty of<br />

the individual required the complete individualization<br />

of society which, in turn, implied that every individ<br />

ualbear the cos t 0 f his own act ions • As Wa r r en put<br />

it:<br />

When one's person, his labor, his responsibilities,<br />

the soil he rests on, his food, his<br />

pro per t y, <strong>and</strong> all his i n t eres t s are sod i sconnected,<br />

disunited from others, that he<br />

can control or dispose of these at all times,<br />

according to his own views <strong>and</strong> feelings,<br />

without controlling or disturbing others; <strong>and</strong><br />

when his promises are sacred to himself, <strong>and</strong><br />

his person is not approached, nor his time<br />

<strong>and</strong> attention taken up, against his inelinat<br />

ion, thenth e i n d i v i d ua 1 rna y be said t 0 be<br />

practically sovereign to himself.(19)<br />

The crucial concept in Warren's ideas is that of<br />

cost. Individuals can only remain sovereign when each<br />

bears the cost of his own actions. This means that in<br />

any exchange cost is the only just or "equitable l1<br />

p ric e, for i f 0 nere c e i v e s rno ret han the cos t 0 f the<br />

good to him he is shifting the cost of his actions onto<br />

182


another, thereby violating the latter's sovereignty.<br />

Since the only equitable price was that determined by<br />

the cost to the producer rather than the value to<br />

the receiver the profit system, i.e., the view that<br />

"value is the limit of price," is accordingly denounced<br />

asa" s y s tern 0 f c i v iii zed can nibali s m by wh i c h the<br />

masses of human beings are mercilessly ground to powder<br />

for the accumulation of the wealth of the few."(20)<br />

Fur the r, wh i 1e cos t wa s t 0 bethem0 r a Ide t e r minant 0 f<br />

price, Warren believed that cost, in turn was determined<br />

by labor. He did recognize, however, that an hour's<br />

labor in one occupation might not be equal to an hour's<br />

labor in another, <strong>and</strong> modified his labor theory of<br />

va I ue to compensate for such di fferences. The equitable<br />

or just price was not based simply on the number of<br />

hours worked, but on "equivalent labor," <strong>and</strong> the most<br />

"repugnant" occupations, being the most "costly," were<br />

therefore to be accorded propo r t iona I Iygrea t errern un ­<br />

eration. If the labor of A is "doubly as costly to<br />

comfort, clothing, tools, etc.," as the labor of B, he<br />

remarks, then five hours of A's labor ought to exchange<br />

for ten hours of labor by B. This "would constitute<br />

the equitable reward of labor to both parties."(21)<br />

True to his principle of individual soverei.gnty,<br />

Warren believed that the only way to determine the<br />

equivalence of different labor was to allow each indiv<br />

i d u a Ito est irna t e the cos t 0 f his own I abo r • Corn pet i ­<br />

tion, he believed, would tend to insure honesty:<br />

I f A set s his est i mat e 0 f the rna king 0 f a<br />

certain kind of coat at 50 hours, <strong>and</strong> B sets<br />

his at 30 hours, the price per hour, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

known qualities of workmanship being the same<br />

in both, it is evident that A could get no<br />

business while B could supply the dem<strong>and</strong>. It<br />

is evident at A has not given an honest estimate,<br />

or, that he is in the wrong position<br />

for the general economy ••• (22)<br />

The final price of a good, said Warren, would then<br />

be set at the average number of hours expended on its<br />

product ion. Thus, if the average number of hours for<br />

the production of a pair of shoes is, say, ten hours,<br />

<strong>and</strong> if one individual can produce them in only six, he<br />

can still, in justice, charge ten hours of labor.(23)<br />

Such are the principles which Warren believed constituted<br />

a viable exchange system. Price was to be based<br />

on the number of hours worked, modified by both the<br />

f1repugnancefl as well as the intensity of the labor. The<br />

183


final price would include all labor' expended including<br />

wear <strong>and</strong> tear, or depreciation, on the tools utilized<br />

in production.<br />

Two other points should be noted. First, if individuals<br />

are to be sovereign, they must be permitted to<br />

dispose of themselves as they wish. Hence, they could<br />

hire themselves out if they so desired. Warren, therefore,<br />

had no objection to the wage system, <strong>and</strong> his doctr<br />

ines lack the class consciousness found in much of<br />

the other radical literature of the period. Second, it<br />

follows from his labor theory of value that "allnatural<br />

wealth" should be "rendered free <strong>and</strong> accessible to<br />

all without price." Thus Warren anticipated Henry<br />

George in condemning any unearned increment accruing<br />

from the ownership of l<strong>and</strong>. A person could charge for<br />

the cos t 0 f imp r 0 vern e n t she rna d e inthe 1<strong>and</strong>, but he<br />

could not justly charge a price for the value of the<br />

1<strong>and</strong> itself. Wa r r en wa s t rue to his pr inc i pies wh e n he<br />

sold his property, several city blocks in the heart of<br />

the Cincinnati business district, at the cost of his<br />

own labor rather than at its value resulting from its<br />

prime location.(24)<br />

Warren <strong>and</strong> his followers also believed that exchange<br />

based on the cost pr inciple would eliminate<br />

speculation <strong>and</strong> price fluctuations <strong>and</strong> provide a secure<br />

<strong>and</strong> ce r t a i n f ram ewo r k for even econom i c deve I opmen t •<br />

"Cost is a thing which looks to the past," says<br />

And r e ws, "a n d i, s theref 0 r e c e r t a in. Val ue isath i ng<br />

which looks to the future <strong>and</strong> is therefore contingent<br />

<strong>and</strong> uncertain. A bushel of potatoes lies before us.<br />

It is poss ible to est imate wi th accuracy how much human<br />

labor it ordinarily takes to produce that amount of<br />

that article, <strong>and</strong> how disagreeable the labor is compared<br />

with other kinds, <strong>and</strong> then we have the st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

cos t 0 f the art i c 1e; but wh 0 wi I I un d.e r t a ke to say wh a t<br />

the val u e 0 f t hat bus heli s as itst<strong>and</strong>sin the rna r ­<br />

ket?" Thus, "every exchange based on the comparison of<br />

values," is seen as merely "speCUlation upon probabilities<br />

of the future <strong>and</strong> not a scientific measurement of<br />

that which already exists."(25) The result of the<br />

value principle is therefore perpetual price fluctuat<br />

ionsan d the con c 0 mm itan t g 1u t s<strong>and</strong> famin e s . " Val ue<br />

being iniquitously made on the basis of price," summarized<br />

Warren<br />

produces all the ruinous fluctuations in<br />

t r a de, the un c e r t a i n t y 0 f the rewa r d 0 fin ­<br />

dustry, <strong>and</strong> the inadequacy of Its reward; it<br />

184


produces poverty, <strong>and</strong> the fear of poverty,<br />

a va ric e, <strong>and</strong> the all - a b so r bin g pu r sui t 0 f<br />

proper ty, wi thout regard to the rights or<br />

sympathy for the sufferings of others, <strong>and</strong><br />

trains us, in the absence of all knowledge or<br />

rule or right, mutually to encroach upon <strong>and</strong><br />

invade each other; allof which, including<br />

the encroachments of governments, give rise<br />

to the INSECURITY OF PERSON AND PROPERTY. (26)<br />

But the adoption of the cost principle would terminate<br />

a I I Pric e flu c t u a t ion by prov i din g a concr e t e<br />

<strong>and</strong> "scientific" basis for price determination. "All<br />

labor being equally rewarded according to its cost,"<br />

says Warren, "there would be no destructive competition<br />

-- markets would be steady•••"(27) The cost principle<br />

was viewed, therefore, as the means to insure a<br />

scientific <strong>and</strong> harmonious adaptation of supply <strong>and</strong><br />

dem<strong>and</strong>. Warren felt that the implementation of the<br />

cost principle would immensely facilitate production.<br />

And, be i ng i nfl uenced by the environmental determinism<br />

of Robert Owen, he believed that men were essentially<br />

products of their environment. Since the increase in<br />

pro d u c t ion wo u 1d r a isethest<strong>and</strong>a r d 0 f 1 i v i n g , i t wo u1d<br />

eliminate crime, except for occasional cases of social<br />

deviants who should be treated in hospitals rather than<br />

placed in prisons, <strong>and</strong> thus remove the need for governmen<br />

t. As he summar ized his own view of the cost principle:<br />

Co s t be i n g the 1 i mit 0 f p ric e wo u 1d .pu t a<br />

stop to ·all fluctuat ions in pr ices <strong>and</strong> in<br />

trade, compel everyone to produce as<br />

much as he consumed, would distribute the<br />

bur the r n 0 f 1abo r among all , <strong>and</strong> r educe t he<br />

amount of labor of each to one, two or three<br />

ho u r s per day, would rai se everyone ABOVE THE<br />

TEMPTATION TO INVADE ANOTHER, <strong>and</strong> everyone<br />

w0 u 1d, con seq u e n t 1y, fee 1 sec u refr om any<br />

encroachments -- government <strong>and</strong> laws would<br />

not then be thought necessary, in order to<br />

restrain men from encroaching on each other,<br />

<strong>and</strong> t his e x c use for theirexis ten c e wo u I d be<br />

swept away."(28)<br />

Warren's attempts at the practical implementation<br />

of his principles shed more light on his ideas. He<br />

ope rat e d severa I "Time S tor e s , " as he cal led them. The<br />

fir s twa s beg u n inCinc inn a t i in 1827 , <strong>and</strong> a 11 we r e<br />

operated on the principle of disconnection. The cost<br />

185


er day it might only buy two bushels. Further, the<br />

fact that the right to issue money was monopolized by<br />

chartered banks meant that its money could be sold at<br />

far above its cost. Warren believed that a circulating<br />

me dIu m wh i c h wa stir e presen tat I ve 0 fad e fin I t e qua ntit Y<br />

of propertytlwould prove to be a stable <strong>and</strong> therefore a<br />

jus t me c han ism for f a c iIi tat i ngin d irec t ex chan g e •<br />

T his tI de fin i t e qua n tit Y 0 f pro per t y tI wo u I d be 1a bo r<br />

hours. Once exchange ratios between occupations were<br />

est a b lis h e d b Y mea n s 0 fin d i v i d ua I .est i rna t e s 0 f cos t s<br />

<strong>and</strong> a n a v era g e p ric e i n h 0 u r s for e a c hoc c u pa t ion<br />

emerged, labor notes could circulate. in place of money.<br />

AIl that was r e qui red was to choose If s omepart i cuIa r<br />

kind of labor, the average repugnance of which is most<br />

easily ascertained • <strong>and</strong> use it as a st<strong>and</strong>ard of<br />

comparIson .• for measuring the relative repugnance<br />

of other kinds of labor."(32) Warren believed that<br />

t his n s tan dar d nco U I d be f 0 undIn co r n • I fit we r e<br />

the n f 0 u n d t hat the a v era g e pro d u c t ion 0 f cor n wa s<br />

twenty pounds per hour, any occupation whose average<br />

repugnance was rated by the estimates of the members of<br />

the community at one half more difficult would then<br />

receive the equivalent in labor to thirty pounds of<br />

corn. Any occupat ion rated one-half less difficult<br />

w0 u 1 d on 1 y r ec e i v e the labor equi valent of ten pounds<br />

of corn. Each individual would be perfectly free to<br />

iss u e his ow n I abo r not e s wit h his I abor, but Wa rr en<br />

saw no diffiCUlty here. Anyone who exaggerated the<br />

repugnance of his labor, refused to honor, or overissued,<br />

his own notes, would be unable to find anyone<br />

wi 11 ing to accept them.(33) Warren therefore believed<br />

that necess i ty would compel honesty in the issue of<br />

notes. These notes would then circulate as dollars do<br />

now, but having the advantage of representing something<br />

definite <strong>and</strong> stable. Hence, if A issued a labor note<br />

to B in payment for a service <strong>and</strong> B didn't require A's<br />

type of labor, he could exchange it for an equivalent<br />

amount of labor from C, who needed the type of labor<br />

offered by A.(34)<br />

By making each man his own banker, Warren saw<br />

another advantage in his labor note system: it would<br />

break the government-banker money monopoly <strong>and</strong> thereby<br />

red u c e i n t eres t tot he cos t 0 f rna kin g the t ran sac t ion.<br />

The t1costtl of any loan transaction, however, would include<br />

all sacrifice or burden endured by the lender,<br />

including that of uncertainity or risk. But since information<br />

on dem<strong>and</strong> would be available to all, no unwanted<br />

goods would be produced. Investment would<br />

therefore be riskless <strong>and</strong> the cost or sacrifice to the<br />

187


lender would be el iminated, resulting in the virtual<br />

elimination of interest. Further, since everyone would<br />

be able to issue his own notes, there would be "plenty<br />

of cirCUlating .medium always at h<strong>and</strong>." Hence, "exchange<br />

<strong>and</strong> d i vis i on of labor would not be I imi ted for<br />

want of money."(35) The result would be constant<br />

prosperity.<br />

s uchi s t he 0 uti i n e 0 f J 0 s i a h Wa r r en's a I t erna t i ve<br />

to government. As Stephen Pearl Andrews sums up<br />

Warren's outlook, the basis of social harmony is human<br />

Ii ber ty. And human I iberty is grounded in "the Sovereignty<br />

of the Individual; <strong>and</strong> the sole basis upon which<br />

the e x e r cise 0 f t ha t S 0 vere i gn t y can res t .i sEq u i t y, - ­<br />

the render i ng to each of that which is his. The Cost<br />

Principle furnishes the law of that rendering. That,<br />

<strong>and</strong> t h-a t a Ion e, a d min i s t e r sEqu i t Y• Hen ce, i t PI aces<br />

all in a condition of independence. It dissolves the<br />

re I a t i on of protectors <strong>and</strong> protected by render i ng prot<br />

e c t ion un nee e s s a r y • " ( 3 6 ) Itsh0 u ld a Iso be po i n ted<br />

out that while they felt that free competition tended<br />

to reduce pr ice to cos t, it would not do so in every<br />

case. And while they argued that the only just determinant<br />

of price was that of cost, they could find no<br />

way other than persuasion to enforce the cost principle.<br />

Every individual, said Andrews, "must be left<br />

absolutely free to commit every conceivable<br />

breach of the principle itself, since absolute freedom<br />

is another of the essential principles of harmonious<br />

society."(37)<br />

Wh i let h e soc i a - e conom i c ideas 0 f Wa r r en eX e r ted<br />

an immense influence on later philosophical anarchists,<br />

by 1862 all of the Equitable communities had been terminated.<br />

Moreover, Warren's "labor check" system, with<br />

1abo r not e s s i g ned by the iss u e r, <strong>and</strong> his "wa n t - ad"<br />

method of balancing supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong> were suitable<br />

only for small, non-industrialized communities populated<br />

by jacks-of-all trades. While Warren's philosophical<br />

principles -- the "sovereignty of the individual,"<br />

"cost the 1 imi t of pr ice ,n private property <strong>and</strong> free<br />

compet i t ion -- remained at the heart of philosophical<br />

anarchism throughout the nineteenth century, it quickly<br />

became ev i dent to Warren's successors that in order to<br />

make them relevant in the age of industrialization <strong>and</strong><br />

urban life, the practical aspects of his proposals required<br />

modification.<br />

188


- 2. WILLIAM B. GREENE AND CURRENCY AND BANKING REFORM<br />

An early modification of Warren's thought emerged<br />

in the banking ideas espoused primarily by William B.<br />

Greene, al though Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner <strong>and</strong> Ezra Heywood,<br />

whose ideas along with those of Greene were largely a<br />

prod u c t 0 f what Jame s Ma r tin t e r ms the "cur r enc y r a d i ­<br />

c a lism t hat ace 0 mpan i ed<strong>and</strong> f 0 1lowed the bus i ne s s<strong>and</strong><br />

financial panic of 1837,"(38) advocated reforms along<br />

parallel lines. All three believed. that the business<br />

cycle was a direct result of the "money monopoly"<br />

Which, in turn, was seen as a product of legal privilege<br />

conferred by the government upon banks. Thesep<br />

r i v i legesc 0 n sis ted 0 f the res t ric ting 0 f ba nking<br />

rights to those banks chartered by the state, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

passage of legal tender laws. Their proposals were<br />

designed, at least in part, to make Warren's labor<br />

exchange ideas applicable to an industrial iociety.<br />

A s Gr e e n e saw it, the 0 n I y pur po s e 0 f a ban k wa s<br />

to serve as a clearing-house for borrowers <strong>and</strong> lenders.<br />

The borrowers were those with just their own labor but<br />

n 0 cap it.a I. The len d e r s had tools <strong>and</strong> raw rna t e ria I s<br />

but no I abo r e r s. One wit h 0 u t the 0 the r wasuse I e s s .<br />

The funct ion of the bank was to provide the service of<br />

bringing the two together. If banking were free,<br />

Greene believed, competition would eliminate interest<br />

<strong>and</strong> reduce the payment to the bank to the cost of its<br />

services, which was estimated at below one percent.<br />

However, by getting the government to require a charter<br />

for all banks, creditors were able to all but eliminate<br />

compet it ion in the supply of loans <strong>and</strong> therefore to<br />

prevent the fall in the rate of interest. Thus state<br />

bank charters placed the creditors in what Greene<br />

called the position "to enable the few to bring the<br />

many under tribute."(39)<br />

Even more important, however, were the legal tender<br />

laws. Since all exchange, inclUding that for<br />

m0 n e y, was e sse n t i all y not h i ng morethan .ba r t e r, a I I<br />

property, they argued, was money. And if any individual<br />

should choose to conduct his exchanges in values<br />

other than gold or silver, they believed that he should<br />

ha vet ha t r i gh t. Lega I tender laws were seen as drastically<br />

altering the conditions of exchange by legally<br />

placing the owners of those particular types of metals<br />

in a monopoly position. By declaring that only gold or<br />

silver were money <strong>and</strong> that all transactions had to be<br />

made in those metals, the amount of money in circulation<br />

was arbitrarily restricted. This served to bene-<br />

189


fit the creditors in three ways: [1] by reducing the<br />

amount of money that could be loaned it kept the interes<br />

t ra te high; [2] it enabled those pr i vi leged few possessing<br />

the metals to control the monetary system. And<br />

since the business of the nation could not be conducted<br />

by simple or direct barter it therefore enabled them to<br />

con t r 0 1 n ear 1y eve r y aspe c t 0 f the e conom i c a f fair s 0 f<br />

the country. As Heywood remarked, "since money is the<br />

common measure of products, <strong>and</strong> eXhange must be made in<br />

the accepted currency, it is apparent that if speculation<br />

control this medium, dictating its nature, amount,<br />

<strong>and</strong> value, they are masters of both labor, <strong>and</strong> trade,<br />

<strong>and</strong> can tax us on the chance to do business, ,<strong>and</strong> also<br />

for the privilege of living";(40) <strong>and</strong> [3] combined with<br />

other laws allowing the owners of specie to issue notes<br />

up to twice the face value of the specie, the legal<br />

ten d e r I a ws per mit ted c red ito r s toea r n pr 0 fit s by<br />

s pecui a tingin 0 the r p eo pies' mi s e r y: "N ow the banks<br />

have everything in their h<strong>and</strong>s," said Greene,<br />

They make great issues, <strong>and</strong> money becomes<br />

plenty; all other commodities<br />

become dear. Then the capitalist sells what<br />

he has to sell, while prices are high. They<br />

draw in their issues, <strong>and</strong> money becomes<br />

s car c e , allot her c omm 0 d i ties become<br />

cheap. The commun i ty becomes distressed for<br />

money, individuals are forced to sell property<br />

to raise money -- <strong>and</strong> to sell at a loss on<br />

account of the state of the market: then the<br />

capitalist buys what he desires to buy, while<br />

everything is cheap • The operation of<br />

the banking system is evident ••• (41)<br />

s u c h s p e cui a t ion wasseen as the ca use 0 f the bus i n e s s<br />

cycle with all its attendant fluctuations <strong>and</strong> uncertainties.<br />

Moreover, the legal limitation of money to<br />

gold <strong>and</strong> silver reduced the supply of money, theyargued,<br />

below that which was necessary to purchase all of<br />

the goods produced, thereby intensifying the business<br />

cycle.<br />

Perhaps the most interesting arguments against<br />

government banking laws were advanced by Lys<strong>and</strong>er<br />

Spooner. Adhering to a Lockean natural rights position,<br />

Spooner argued that every individual owned his<br />

own body, <strong>and</strong> by extension, whatever he produced by his<br />

own labor, whether physical or mental. If a person<br />

really owned his property, it followed that he had a<br />

right to contract to dispose of it in any voluntary way<br />

h e c h 0 s e . Con seq u e n t 1 y, hear g uedin his Co n s tit utional<br />

L'aw Relative to Credit, Currency <strong>and</strong> Banking,<br />

II To iss u e b ill S 0 fer e d it, t hat 1 S, prom iss 0 r y not e S ,<br />

190


i sana t u ra I r j g h t . The righ t of bank i ng , or of<br />

con t rae tin g deb t s b Y g i v i n g prom iss 0 r y not e s for the<br />

payment of money is as much a natural right as that of<br />

manufacturing cotton." Everyone, as Spooner saw it,<br />

had an equal right to enter the banking business <strong>and</strong> to<br />

issue his own money. Hence, government grants of legal<br />

pr i vi leges to banks, whether in the form of bank chart<br />

e r s 0 r leg a I tend e r I a ws_, werea v i 0 I a t ion 0 f nat ur a 1<br />

rights.(42)<br />

Spooner attacked legal tender laws with special<br />

vi gor. The Cons tit ut ion grants to Congress the power<br />

to coin money, but it does not, he noted, give Congress<br />

the power flto establish monopolies of any kind whatsoever."<br />

Consequently, he concluded, flCongress has no<br />

power to outlaw any private coinage of currency.fI "Nor<br />

could there consistently have been any such prohibition<br />

unless on the supposition that the people were incompetent<br />

to make their own bargains. fI (43) Spooner noted<br />

t hat Art i c 1 e I, Sec t ion 1 0 0 f the Co n s tit uti 0 n s pee i ­<br />

fically stated that fino <strong>State</strong> shall impair the obligat<br />

ion 0 f con t rae t s • " This meant, he sa i d, t hat the Con ­<br />

st i tut ion specifically acknowledged the right to enter<br />

into contracts <strong>and</strong> hence, any law restricting the right<br />

of individuals to make contracts, including any law<br />

prohibiting private banking, was in clear violation of<br />

the Constitution.(44) But Spooner even went a step<br />

fur the r<strong>and</strong>el aimedt hat i t wa s log i ca I I Y imp 0 s sib I e<br />

for any government to have exclusive power in any area.<br />

The Pream blet0 the Co n s tit uti 0 n c I ear I yindieate s t hat<br />

the government was established by flthe People." Consequently,<br />

as Spooner argued in his The Unconstitutionality<br />

of the Laws of Congress Prohibiting Private<br />

Mails:<br />

In matters of government the people are the<br />

principals, <strong>and</strong> the government mere agents ..•<br />

Now it is perfectly clear that a principal, by<br />

simply authorizing an agent to carryon a particular<br />

business in his name, gives the agent<br />

no promise that he, (the principal,) will not<br />

also himself carryon business of the same<br />

kind. He plainly surrenders no right to carry<br />

on the same kind of business at pleasure. And<br />

the agent has no claim even to be consulted,<br />

as to whether his principal shall set up a<br />

rival establishment to the one that is entrusted<br />

to the agent. The whole authority of<br />

the agen tis I imi ted s imply to the management<br />

of the establ ishment confided to hirn.(45)<br />

191


No power granted to the government, 'even that of making<br />

war, he contended, could possibly be exclusive, for<br />

that would entail a logical impossibility, viz., that<br />

government (the agent) would dominate <strong>and</strong> control the<br />

people (the principals). In short, Spooner was of the<br />

op in i on tha t "the money monopo ly is one of the most<br />

g I a r i n g v i 0 I a t ion s 0 f men' s nat u r a I righ t s to rna ke<br />

their own contracts, <strong>and</strong> one of the most effective<br />

perhaps the most effective-- for enabling a few men to<br />

rob everybodyelse."(46)<br />

The philosophical anarchists expected great things<br />

from free banking. Once individuals were able to monet<br />

i ze any <strong>and</strong> all property, every individual would become<br />

his own banker <strong>and</strong> the "money monopoly" would collapse<br />

since the bankers would no longer be in a position<br />

to control the money supply. The supply of money<br />

would then, as Spooner phrased it, be subject to "an<br />

indef ini te increase." The interest rate, accordingly,<br />

would be reduced to the cost of issuing money, <strong>and</strong><br />

speculation would be eliminated altogether. The "natural"<br />

price, based on labor cost, would then be equal<br />

tothe" mar k e t" Price, bas e don sup ply <strong>and</strong> dema nd •<br />

Capital would become plentiful <strong>and</strong> could be obtained by<br />

any 0 newhod e sir e d it, <strong>and</strong> produe t ion, i n t urn, wo u 1d<br />

increase dramatically. And finally, the business cycle<br />

would be terminated since, with no "shortage" of money,<br />

all that was produced could be bought.<br />

The monetary views developed by Greene, Heywood<br />

<strong>and</strong> Spooner were des igned to provide a cirCUlating<br />

medium based on labor but without the limitations of<br />

Warren's labor exchange system, with notes signed by<br />

the issuer <strong>and</strong> redeemable only in the issuer's labor.<br />

They rema i ned a t the heart of .phi los 0 ph ica 1 a narchism<br />

in the nineteenth century. As late as October 18,<br />

1890, one finds Benjamin Tucker, in whom philosophical<br />

a n archis m rea c h e d its f ulIma t urat ion, wr i tingin his<br />

journal, Liberty, that<br />

It is true that I expect lending <strong>and</strong> borrowing<br />

to disappear, but not by any denial of<br />

the right to lend <strong>and</strong> borrow. On the contrary,<br />

I expect them to disappear by virtue of<br />

the affirmat ion <strong>and</strong> exercise of a right that<br />

is now denied, namely the right to use<br />

one's own credit, or to exchange it freely<br />

for anot her's, in such a way that one or the<br />

other of these credits may perform the function<br />

of a circulating medium, without the<br />

192


3. JOSHUA K. INGALLS AND THE OWNERSHIP OF LAND<br />

The later anarchist position regarding the nature<br />

of l<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> its ownership also constitutes an advance<br />

bey 0 n d the 0 rig ina 1 War r en i t e ideas. On e 0 f Wa r r en' s<br />

central principles was "cost, the limit of price."<br />

Ea chi n d i v i d ua I wa sentit led tothe produe t 0 f his own<br />

labor, no more, no less. This means, said Warren, that<br />

tt Nat urea c k now led g e s n 0 0 wn e r s hip 0 reon t r 0 1 i n rna n<br />

save as a result of exertion •.•. Sbe recognizes no<br />

claim but that of labor."(52) Thus, while "Every individual<br />

has the right to appropriate so much of the common<br />

natural wealth as is requisite to the supply of his<br />

wants,"(53) one could not justly acquire another's<br />

we a 1 thex c e p t b y g i v i n g an·e qua 1 am 0 un t 0 f 1abor i n<br />

ret urn. The 0 n 1 y "ren t" wh i c h the own e r cou 1d jus t 1Y<br />

colle c two u I d the ref 0 rebe for the rna i n tena nee 0 f the<br />

premises. In fact, argued Andrews, if the tenant left<br />

the prem i s e sin bet t e r s hape t han wh en he a r r i ved, the<br />

owner would actually owe "rent" to the tenant. But<br />

since under a sys t em of labor exchange there would be<br />

"no advantage in owning l<strong>and</strong> which one does not want<br />

for his present uses" it was not only believed that<br />

"all temptation to monopolize the soil" would be<br />

"ex·tinguished," but also that no great inequalities of<br />

wealth could even arise.(54) Hence, it is not too surprising<br />

that Warren did not devote much time to clarifying<br />

the nature of ownership. But with the emergence<br />

of industrialization, large corporations, <strong>and</strong> the business<br />

tycoon in the post-Civil War period, anarchists<br />

had to fa c e the prob 1em 0 f own e r s hip. Th e i r wr i tings<br />

constitute not so much a departure from the thought of<br />

War r e n a s the f u lIdeve I 0 pmen t 0 f the idea s t hat we r e<br />

expressed only more or less implicitly in his labor exc<br />

han g e s y s tern • The p ion e e r i nth i s area wa s J 0 shua<br />

Ingalls, whom Martin refers to as the William Greene of<br />

l<strong>and</strong> reform.<br />

Ingal Is premised his entire argument on the belief<br />

that "The whole produce of labor belongs to the Iabore<br />

r, <strong>and</strong> ish i s nat u raIrewar d . " Gr 0 un d- r en t wa s the r e ­<br />

fore unjust, since it was the acquisition of wealth<br />

without labor. It was exploitive because it deprived<br />

the worker of the full value of his product. Hence, he<br />

con c Iud ed, a bs en tee - own e r s hip wasacI ea r vi 0 I a t ion 0 f<br />

the labor theory of value.(55)<br />

Rent, he continued, was not an economic but a polit<br />

ical concept. Whereas David Ricardo had argued that<br />

it was the 'increase in populat ion that produced rent by


forcing the less productive l<strong>and</strong> int.o use, Ingalls conten<br />

d edthat the revers e wa s t rue: the ex i s tenceof r en t<br />

forced the use of less productive l<strong>and</strong>. While the need<br />

for l<strong>and</strong> increased with the increase in population,<br />

Ingalls believed that the title-holders to the l<strong>and</strong>,<br />

backed by the power of the government, were able to<br />

dem<strong>and</strong> payment for the mere right to use l<strong>and</strong> that<br />

w0 u I dot her w i seli e f a I 1ow • Th us r en t the a r g ued, wa s<br />

aresuI t 0 f go v e. r n men t a I pro tee t. i on of l<strong>and</strong> tit Ies<br />

beyond that of occupancy <strong>and</strong> use.<br />

If, then, l<strong>and</strong> titles were based on the principles<br />

of equity, viz., the exchange of labor for an equivallent<br />

amount of labor, ownership could not extend beyond<br />

actual occupancy <strong>and</strong> rent would be eliminated. Not<br />

only would implementation of the occupancy principle<br />

eliminate the problem of wealth concentration but<br />

I n g a I I s eve n bel i eve d t hat i t wo uIds0 decen t r a lize<br />

1<strong>and</strong> 0 wn e r s hip a s to rna k e Wa r r en' s Iabo r c he c k s Ystem<br />

practical. Ingalls proposed a gradual transition from<br />

legal "ownership" to actual "occupancy," where the curr<br />

e n tie g a lown e r s 0 f I<strong>and</strong> wo u I d ret a i nthe i r proper t y<br />

rig h t suntil the i r dea t hs, aft e r wh i c h proper t y righ t s<br />

would be determined by use or occupancy.(56)<br />

Ingalls' view that l<strong>and</strong> holdings should be limited<br />

b y 0 c c u pa n c y i san imp 0 r tan t ref i nerne n t 0 f Wa r r en's<br />

principle that labor-cost should be the limit of price.<br />

It is also significant in its impact on subsequent anarchist<br />

thought. "Occupation-<strong>and</strong>-use-tenure of l<strong>and</strong>,"<br />

says Martin, "a nearly-forgotten theory in non-radical<br />

circles, became firmly established in anarchist teaching<br />

from the time of J. K. Ingalls."(57)<br />

The only major nineteenth century philosophical<br />

a n archis t not a d her' i n g tot h e view t hat 1<strong>and</strong> own e r s<br />

should be 1 imi ted by occupancy was Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner.<br />

In 1853, Spooner published his The Law of Intellectual<br />

Property which was intended to demonstrate that individuals<br />

had, by natural law, perpetual property right<br />

ina 1 1 proper ty, tang i ble or in tangi ble. Star t i ng from<br />

his Lockean natural rights position of individual self<br />

own e r s hip <strong>and</strong>, byex ten s ion, 0 ne 's own e r s hip 0 f the<br />

fruits of his labor, Spooner maintained that:<br />

The . p r inc i pie 0 f proper t y is, t hat the own e r<br />

of a thing has absolute dominion over it,<br />

whether he have it in actual possession or<br />

not, <strong>and</strong> whether he himself wish to use it or<br />

not;· t hat noon e ha s a rig h t tota ke po ssession<br />

of it, or use it, without his consent ...<br />

196


There is, he continued,<br />

no middle ground between absolute communism,<br />

on the one h<strong>and</strong>, which holds that a man has a<br />

right to lay his h<strong>and</strong> on anything, which has<br />

no other man 1 s h<strong>and</strong>s upon it, no matter who<br />

may have been the producer; <strong>and</strong> the principle<br />

of individual dominion, as against all other<br />

men, over the products <strong>and</strong> acquisitions of<br />

his 0 wn 1abo r, wh e ther hereta Ln them i n his<br />

actual possession or not.(58)<br />

For S poone r, theref 0 r e, the 0 c c upan c y pr inc i pIe wa s not<br />

only a contradictory middle-of-the-road position between<br />

commun ism <strong>and</strong> individual sovereignty, but a viol<br />

a t ion 0 f the nat u r a I righ t s pr inc i pie 0 f s elf own e r ­<br />

s hip, a s well. Howe ve r, S po0 n e r s tood virt uall y a Ione<br />

on this issue. Benjamin Tucker was extremely critical.<br />

11 I call Spooner 1 s work on Intellectual Property positively<br />

foolish,1I he wrote<br />

because it is fundamentally foolish, -- that<br />

is to say, its discussion of the acquisition<br />

of pro per t y s tar t s wi t h a bas i c pr opos i t ion<br />

that must be looked upon by all consistent<br />

Anarchists as obvious nonsense. I quote this<br />

basic proposition. 'The natural wealth of<br />

the world belongs to those who first take<br />

possession of it • So much natural<br />

wealth, remaining unpossessed, as anyone can<br />

take possession of first, becomes absolutely<br />

his property.'(59)<br />

Later anarchists, like Tucker, followed Ingalls to<br />

the letter. Writing in 1890, Tucker said:<br />

[ L ] e t us sup p 0 sethat the Ana r ch i s t<br />

view that occupancy <strong>and</strong> use should condition<br />

<strong>and</strong> 1 im it l<strong>and</strong>holding becomes the prevai 1 ing<br />

view • E v ide n t I Y thenth e s e mun i c i pa lit i e s<br />

wi 11 proceed to formulate <strong>and</strong> enforce this<br />

view. Wha t the for mu I a wi libe noon e can<br />

foresee••. [W]e will say that they decide to<br />

protect no one in possession of more than ten<br />

acres, then particular l<strong>and</strong>s will be open to<br />

those there first to claim it.(60)<br />

197


4. BENJAMIN TUCKER, LYSANDER SPOONER AND THE<br />

PROVISION OF POLICE AND COURT SERVICES<br />

The development of philosophical anarchism into a<br />

complete system reached its fruition in the writings of<br />

Benjamin Tucker <strong>and</strong> Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner on the difficult<br />

problem of the protection of individual rights within a<br />

no-government system. Josiah Warren" sUbscrib"ing to<br />

the Owenite belief in environmental determinism, believed<br />

that crime was a product of an environment characterized<br />

by poverty <strong>and</strong> disorder. Since the implementation<br />

of his ideas, he believed, would produce a har-monious<br />

society characterized by an ever increasing<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ard of living, it followed that individuals would<br />

I ear n t 0 I i vet 0 get her h arm 0 n i ously, <strong>and</strong> c rime, <strong>and</strong><br />

therefore the need for government, would disappear.<br />

Warren's successors took a somewhat less sanguine view<br />

of human na t u r e. They agreed that a society based on<br />

"individual sovereignty" would end economic injustice<br />

<strong>and</strong> allow for a much greater degree of flexibility as<br />

well as a higher st<strong>and</strong>ard of living. While they felt<br />

these factors would eliminate most of the causes of<br />

cr ime, they doubted that crime would cease altogether.<br />

But 0 nee sue han a dmiss ion i s rna de, the que s t ion t hat<br />

mu s t be i mme d i ate I y fa c edis wo u I d not suehas0 c i e t y<br />

b e p I ace d a t the mer c y 0 f the r ema i n i ng c rim ina I e I e ­<br />

men t, whie h pres uma b I Y wo u I d not hesitate toengage i n<br />

violence whenever it suited its purpose?<br />

Tucker admitted that "Where crime exists, force<br />

mu.st exist to suppress it" <strong>and</strong> denied that anarchism<br />

was simply a "revival of non-resistance."(61) He defined<br />

anarchism in terms of the "sovereignty of the individual"<br />

<strong>and</strong> Herbert Spencer's "law of equal liberty,"<br />

<strong>and</strong> contended that the use of force was not necessarily<br />

incompatible with either pr"inciple. Force, he pointed<br />

out, could be either invasive or non-invasive. The<br />

former was defined as the initiation of the use of<br />

coercion <strong>and</strong> was incompatible with anarchism since it<br />

was a clear violation of the "sovereignty of the<br />

individual." The latter, however, was the defensive<br />

use 0 f co ere ion, i. e ., the mea n s by wh i c h the nona<br />

g g res s i ve i nd i v i d ua I wa s a blet 0 protee t hims elf from<br />

those who would initiate the use of coercion. The noni<br />

n vas i ve use 0 f for c e wa s per f ec t I Y compa t i blew i t h<br />

anarchism, he argued, since it not only did not violate<br />

t he p r inc i pie 0 fin d i v i d u a Iso verei gn t y but wa s, i n<br />

fact, the only means by which that principle could be<br />

upheld in the face of attempted violation. Since<br />

crime, by defInition, involved the invasion of the<br />

r i gh t s of others, Tucker <strong>and</strong> his colleagues argued that<br />

198


far fro m g ran ting c rim inalsi mm un i t y for the irerime s ,<br />

anarchism entailed the exact opposite: its complete<br />

suppression.<br />

Their own individualist assumptions, however, precluded<br />

reliance on government institutions as the vehicle<br />

for the protection of individual rights. The community,<br />

they contended, is merely the sum· of its parts<br />

<strong>and</strong> can have no more rights than that possessed by its<br />

individual members. This assumption .leads logically to<br />

the conclusion that the state is, by its very nature,<br />

an invasive <strong>and</strong> thus a criminal institution. As<br />

Tucker's close associate, Victor Yarros, summarized:<br />

Individuals, <strong>and</strong> individuals only, have<br />

rights. This proposition is the corner-stone<br />

of the anarchist doctrine, <strong>and</strong> those who accept<br />

it are bound to go the full length of<br />

anarchism. For if the community cannot<br />

rightfully compel a man to do or refrain from<br />

doing that which private <strong>and</strong> individual memb<br />

e r s thereof cannot 1e g i t i rna tel y for c e him to<br />

do or forego, then compulsory taxation <strong>and</strong><br />

compulsory cooperation for any purpose whatever<br />

are wrong in principle, <strong>and</strong> government<br />

is merely another name for aggression. It<br />

will not be pretended that one private individual<br />

has a right to tax another without his<br />

con sen t; how, then, doe s the rna j 0 r i t Y 0 f the<br />

members of a communi ty obtain the right to<br />

tax the minority without its consent?<br />

T h us, the phi los 0 phi c a I a narchis t s den i edthat i t wa s<br />

possible for any government, regardless of size or<br />

type, to protect individual liberty. Since they both<br />

entai led the initiation of the use of force, government<br />

<strong>and</strong> c rim e' weres e e n a s m0 reo r 1e s s s ynon ym 0 us. I n<br />

fact, Yarros maintains that crime "involves not the<br />

abolition of government, but the widest possible<br />

extension of it."(62)<br />

Even granting that anarchism is consistent with<br />

the non - i n vas i v e use 0 f for c e, wo u I d not any soc i e t y<br />

lacking a central institution with a monopoly on the<br />

"legitimate" use of force, viz., a government, be<br />

characterized by the indiscriminate use of force <strong>and</strong><br />

thus result in a state of chaos <strong>and</strong> insecurity? Tucker<br />

tho ugh t not. T u eke r<strong>and</strong> his f 0 I lowe r s we r e, 1ike the<br />

nineteenth century classical liberals, great believers<br />

i n f r e e com pet i t ion <strong>and</strong> the rna r ke t pro c e s s . The rna r -<br />

199


the moral duty, of all other children, <strong>and</strong><br />

all other persons, to assist the injured party<br />

in defending his rights, <strong>and</strong> redressing<br />

his wr ongs. These are fundamental pr inciples<br />

of natural rights which govern the most imp<br />

0 r tan t t ran sac t ion s 0 f rna n wit h rna n • Yet<br />

children learn them earlier than they learn<br />

t hat t h r e e <strong>and</strong> t h r e ear e six, or' five <strong>and</strong><br />

five are ten. Their childish plays, even,<br />

c 0 u 1 d not be car r i e don wit h0 uta cons tan t<br />

regard to them; <strong>and</strong> itis equally impossible<br />

for persons of any age to live together in<br />

peace on any other conditions.(70) .<br />

"If justice be not a natural principle," he continued,<br />

"then there is no such thing as injustice; <strong>and</strong> all the<br />

crimes of which the world has been the scene, have been<br />

no crimes at all; but only simple events, like the<br />

fall ing of the rain ••." But if, on the other h<strong>and</strong>,<br />

justice was a natural principle, then "it is necessarily<br />

an immutable one; <strong>and</strong> can no more be changed -- by<br />

any power i n fer i 0 r tothat wh i c h esta b lished i t - - t han<br />

can the law of gravitation, the laws of light, the<br />

principles of mathematics, or any other natural law or<br />

principle whatever."(7l)<br />

Co n seq uen t 1y, all huma n 1e g i s 1a t i on , so I on g as i t<br />

was in violation of natural law, was morally null <strong>and</strong><br />

void <strong>and</strong> was legally nothing more than "an absurdity, a<br />

unsurpation, <strong>and</strong> a crime." If every man had a natural<br />

right to the fruit of his labor then, Spooner believed,<br />

he had a natural right to the fruit of his labor; <strong>and</strong><br />

i twa s jus t a s mu c h rob b e r y for any rna n, 0 r g r 0 up 0 f<br />

men, even if they call themselves "government" <strong>and</strong><br />

the irac t i v i tie s "t a x a t ion ," tota k e a I lor pa r t 0 f<br />

another's property, without the latter's consent, as if<br />

i t weret a ken by a common highwayman. S im i 1a r 1y, if a<br />

man was only under obligation to perform duties to<br />

which he freely consented, then he was under obligation<br />

only to perform duties to which he freely consented;<br />

<strong>and</strong> no man or group of men, even if they called themselves<br />

"government," could impose upon him any additional<br />

obligations. This meant, as he pointed out in<br />

No Treason, Number One, all "governments, if they can<br />

rightfully exist at all, can exist only by consent,"<br />

i • e ., "t h e i n d i v i d uale 0 n sen t 0 f eve r y rna n . . . ( 7 2 )<br />

In No Treason, Number Six, Spooner further argued<br />

that since no group of men, however numerous, was able<br />

to bind .another group of men, however small, then in<br />

like manner, no generation of men could bind a succeedi<br />

n g g e n era t ion . Conseq uen t 1y, the Co n s tit uti 0 nco u 1d<br />

204


social expediency.<br />

After reading Stirner, Tucker declared that<br />

Anarchism of the 'natural right' type is out<br />

of date. The Anarchism of today affirms the<br />

right of society to coerce the individual <strong>and</strong><br />

of the individual to coerce society so far as<br />

either has the requisite power .•• practical<br />

i n d i v i d u a Iso v ere i g n t y - -. t h.atis, the<br />

g rea t est am 0 un t 0 f lib e r t y compat i blewi t h<br />

equality of liberty -- is the law of social<br />

I i fe, the 0 n lye0 n d i t ion up 0 n wh ich h uma n<br />

be i ngs can 1 i ve in harmony. When the truth<br />

is ascertained <strong>and</strong> acted upon, we shall have<br />

individual sovereignty in reality-- not as a<br />

sacred natural right vindicated, but as a<br />

social expedient agreed upon••• (79)<br />

Tucker's endorsement of egoism produced a split in<br />

the movement. Natural rights theorists such as Henry<br />

Appleton, M. E. Lazarus <strong>and</strong> John Kelly (Spooner died in<br />

1887, pr ior to Tucker's rejection of natural rights)<br />

s eve red the ire0 nne c t ion wit h Libe r t y, wh i leeg 0 i s t s<br />

1 ike J. L. Wa 1 k e r, <strong>and</strong> J. B. Rob i nson came to the defenseof<br />

Tucker. The split never completely healed <strong>and</strong><br />

probably contributed at least somewhat to the ultimate<br />

decline of philosophical anarchism.<br />

Nevertheless, it should be noted that just one<br />

month after his initial rejection of nat·ural law,<br />

Tucker reaffirmed his attachment to Spooner's "common<br />

law jury": "under Anarchism all rules <strong>and</strong> laws will be<br />

little more than suggestions for the guidance of juri<br />

e s , • • <strong>and</strong> a 1 I dis put e s, wh e t he r abo u t l<strong>and</strong> or anyt<br />

h i ngel s e, will b e submit ted t 0 j uri e s wh i c h wi I 1<br />

judge not only the facts, but the justice of the law,<br />

its applicabiliity to the given circumstances, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

penalty or damage to be inflicted because of its infraction<br />

."(80) Thus, both the egoist as well as the<br />

natural rights strains of individualist anarchism advocated<br />

the same institutional framework: competitive defense<br />

companies to provide protection <strong>and</strong> the trial by<br />

j u r y, wit h dec i s ion s bas e don comm 0 n law, t 0 set tie<br />

disputes. Their real disagreement was philosophical:<br />

whether common law was based on natural rights principles<br />

or social expediency.<br />

207


5 • TUCKER AND HIS JOURNAL, "L I BERTY'" : PH I LOSOPH I CAL<br />

ANARCHISM MATURED<br />

Phi los 0 phi c a I a n arc his m r e c e i v e d its rna t ures t<br />

expression in the writings of Benjamin Tucker. While<br />

Tucker did not produce a systematic exposition of his<br />

ideas, his philosophy can be constructed from his<br />

writings in his journal, Liberty, which spanned a<br />

period of nearly thirty years, from 1881 to 1908.<br />

For Warren <strong>and</strong> Andrews, the principle of "cost the<br />

I imi t of pr ice" was more a prescription for a harmonious<br />

society than a description of actual conduct.<br />

The i r rei ian ceonthe I aborexc hange s ystem meant t hat<br />

the scope of the market <strong>and</strong> therefore of competition<br />

was strictly limited. Hence, they believed that competit<br />

ion was 0 n 1y pa r t i a 1 I y a b 1e to ins urethe 0 per a t ion<br />

of the cost principle. Instead, they relied heavily on<br />

moral exhortat ion <strong>and</strong>· enlightened self-interest, "We<br />

poi n t 0 u t c e r t a i n p r inc i piesin the na t ur e ·0f t h i n gs<br />

which related to the order of human society," commented<br />

Andrews, "in conforming to which mankind will find<br />

their affairs harmonically adjusted, <strong>and</strong> departing from<br />

wh i c h the y w i I I run i n t 0 con f us ion • " ( 81 ) 0 ncernan r e ­<br />

cognized these "scientific" principles, he would find<br />

it in his own interest to follow them.<br />

But in the h<strong>and</strong>s of Warren's successors, "cost the<br />

I imi t of pr ice" was gradually extended into the realm<br />

of description, as well. Through Greene the labor<br />

ex c han g e s y s t em was rep 1aced by a c i r cuI a ting me d i urn<br />

based on the monetization of property, in an effort to<br />

provide a much fuller scope for the role of the market.<br />

And b y the time 0 f Tuc ke r, i t wa s f e 1t t hat the imp e r ­<br />

sonal forces of the market could direct all production<br />

by means of supply <strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> that competit<br />

ion would insure that profit, interest, <strong>and</strong> rent would<br />

be, i f not eliminated, atieas t reducedt0 ami n i mum •<br />

The existence of interest, rent <strong>and</strong> profit, argued<br />

Tucker, was the direct result of "the denial of libert<br />

y, t he sup pres s i on 0 r res t ric t i on 0 f com pet i t i on [ by ]<br />

the 1ega I c rea t ion 0 f m0 no pol i e s . It ( 82) I tis wo r t h<br />

following his argument in some detail. There were<br />

four, <strong>and</strong> only four, monopolies: The l<strong>and</strong> monopoly,<br />

the banking monopoly, the tariff monopoly, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

patent <strong>and</strong> copyright monopoly. And all four were, he<br />

said, the direct result of government privilege. Patents,<br />

copyrights, <strong>and</strong> tariffs restricted or eliminated<br />

competifon in the areas of their application, thereby<br />

208


producing "monopol istic profit" for the beneficiaries<br />

oft h e s e leg a I p r i viI e ge s; r en t wa s the res uItof the<br />

legal protection of l<strong>and</strong> titles not based on occupancy,<br />

"thereby compelling the non-owning users to pay tribute<br />

to the non-using owners as a condition of admission to<br />

the compet i t i v e mar k e t "; <strong>and</strong> i n t eres t res u I ted from<br />

denying the right of each individual to issue his own<br />

notes, i.e., by decreeing that only gold <strong>and</strong> silver<br />

were "legal tender," thereby compelling all non-holders<br />

of go I dan d s i I ve r to pa y t rib ute. ta the ho I der s of<br />

these metals for the privilege of conducting transactions.(83)<br />

Once these legal monopolies were abolished, free<br />

money, free l<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> free trade would prevail. And<br />

under the force of the reSUlting competition, "interest,<br />

profit,<strong>and</strong> rent on buildings will almost entirely<br />

disappear; ground-rents will no longer flow into a few<br />

h<strong>and</strong>s; <strong>and</strong> practically the only inequality remaining<br />

will be the slight disparity of production due to<br />

"s u per i 0 r i t Y 0 f s 0 i I <strong>and</strong> ski 1 1 • n ( 84 ) Un dera s y s t em 0 f<br />

free competition, insisted Tucker, the trusts, which<br />

"instead of growing out of competition, as is so genera<br />

I I Y sup p 0 sed, ha ve been rna de pos sibleon I y by the a b ­<br />

sence of competition. only, in short, by those<br />

arb i t r a r y lim ita t ions of compet i t ion wh i ch we find in<br />

those law-created privileges <strong>and</strong> monopolies of which I<br />

have just spoken,"(85) would be crippled. Further, in<br />

a society governed by free competition, prices would be<br />

determined by their labor-costs, <strong>and</strong> the wage system<br />

would no longer be a vehicle for exploitation. Under<br />

the influence of free competition, he said,· "it will<br />

make no difference whether men work for themsleves, are<br />

employed or employ others. In any case they can get<br />

nothing but that wage for their labor which free competition<br />

determines. n (86) Thus, according to TUCker,<br />

free compet i tion would eliminate exploitation by elimina<br />

tin g a I I profit, r en t<strong>and</strong>in t erest. I t wo u I dinsur<br />

e, i·not her .w0 r ds, t hat cos t Wo u I d bethelimit 0 f<br />

price. It was felt that in such a society everyone<br />

would receive his due <strong>and</strong> the antagonistic struggle<br />

between capital <strong>and</strong> labor would be replaced by harmonious<br />

cooperat ion. Since wealth would increase dramatically<br />

<strong>and</strong> economic justice would prevail, crime would<br />

be significantly reduced. Whatever crime remained<br />

could be h<strong>and</strong>led by competitive defense agencies offeri<br />

n g theirse r viceson the f r e e rna r k e t, <strong>and</strong> the t ria I by<br />

jury, whose decis ions would be guided by the common<br />

law.<br />

209


6. CONCLUSION: THE DECLINE OF PHILOSOPHICAL ANARCHISM<br />

Phi losophical anarchism never did attract a large<br />

following,(89) <strong>and</strong> after the mid-1890's the movement<br />

began to decline. Between 1892 <strong>and</strong> 1897 Liberty<br />

changed from a weekly to a bi-weekly publication, after<br />

wh i ch it appeared only irregularly. Phi losophical anarchism<br />

all but ceased to exist in 1908 when, after the<br />

destruction of his book shop by fire, Tucker ceased<br />

publication of Liberty altogether •. (90) For the next<br />

twenty years, the only anarchism that remained in any<br />

organized fashion in the United <strong>State</strong>s was the anarchocommunism<br />

of Emma Goldman'S journal Mother Earth.<br />

The reasons for the decline of philosophical anarchism<br />

are several. First, as Eunice Schuster points<br />

out, since its proponents were neither wage nor class<br />

con sci 0 us, i t wasspurn e d by bot h the cap ita lis t s, because<br />

of "its dem<strong>and</strong>s to secure the just distribution<br />

of wealth," <strong>and</strong> by labor, which "had had enough of what<br />

it thought was competition <strong>and</strong> individualism."(91) Second,<br />

the i r bel ief that the solut ion to the trust problem<br />

<strong>and</strong> the concentration of wealth lay in less government<br />

<strong>and</strong> freer competition, rather than in more government<br />

<strong>and</strong> the regUlation of business, appeared hopeless­<br />

I y n a i v e <strong>and</strong>, a s C ha r I e s Madis 0 n sa i d, "fa i led t 0 i mpress<br />

anyone but themselves."(92) Third, as Victor<br />

Ya r ro s no ted, a n arc his m ' s cry for the eli mina t ion of<br />

g 0 v ern men twa s bee om i nginerea sing I Y i r rei e van t sinc e<br />

" the wholet re ndin po 1 i tics <strong>and</strong> e con om i c s sinc e the<br />

end of the last century had been away from individualism<br />

<strong>and</strong> 1a iss e z - f air e - ism. The· s tat e, 0 b v i 0 us I y, wa s<br />

not dying of inanition or making room for voluntary<br />

ins tit uti 0 n s ," <strong>and</strong> "eve r y body, insh0 r t, wa s I 00king to<br />

the state for aid <strong>and</strong> support."(93) And finally, philosophical.<br />

anarchism continued to adhere to the labor<br />

theory of value, apparently oblivious to the marginalist<br />

revolution in economics occurring in the 1870'S.<br />

Yet, des pit e its s h 0 r t com i n gs, wh i c h we r e nowh ere<br />

more evident that in its economics, philosophical anarchism<br />

must be acknOWledged as the first, <strong>and</strong> at that<br />

tim e the 0 n I y, bra n d 0 fanarchism topr 0 po un d a complete<br />

system, both a critique of government <strong>and</strong> a positive<br />

alternative not founded on a previous transformation<br />

of human nature. And in its depiction of the<br />

institutional framework of an anarchist society, in<br />

partiCUlar its views regarding the provision of police<br />

<strong>and</strong> judicial services, nineteenth century philosophical<br />

anarchism bears a marked similarity to its more sophis-<br />

211


t icated cousin, twentieth century individualist<br />

anarchism.<br />

212


FOOTNOTES<br />

( 1 ) F ran z 0 p pen h e i mer, The S tat e ( New Yo r k: F r e e<br />

L i feE d i t ion s, 1975), p. x x xi; a 1s 0 see pp. 96-1 01 ;<br />

Emil Kauder, "The Intellectural <strong>and</strong> Political Roots of<br />

t he 0 1 de r A u s t r i an Schoo I ," Z e i t sc h r i f t fur<br />

Nationalokonomie XVII (1958). pp. 420-21; also see<br />

<strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>, The Historical Setting of the<br />

Austr ian School of Economics (New Rochelle: Arlington<br />

H0 use, 19 69 ), Pp. 29 - 34 •<br />

(2)See, for example, Yale Brozen, "Is Government<br />

the Source of Monopoly?," The Intercollegiate Review<br />

(Winter, 1968-1969), pp. 67-68; <strong>and</strong> Adam Smith, The<br />

Wealth of Nations (New Rochelle: Arlington House,<br />

n.d.), especially Vol. II, pg. 72: fl ••• it is the interest<br />

of the merchants <strong>and</strong> manufactures of every country<br />

t 0 see uret 0 thems e I ve s the m0 n 0 pol Y 0 f the home<br />

mar k e t. Hene e, i n Great Br ita in, <strong>and</strong> i n mo s tother European<br />

countries, the extraordinary duties upon almost<br />

a 11 goods imported by al ien merchants. Hence the high<br />

d uti e s<strong>and</strong> proh i bit i onsup0 n a I I thos e for e ign rna n u f aet<br />

u res whie h e a n e 0 me i n toe 0 mpet i t ion wit h 0 ur own.<br />

Hence too the extraordinary restraints upon the import<br />

a t ion 0 f a I m0 s t a I Iso r t s 0 f good s from thosec0 un ­<br />

tries with which the balance of trade is supposed to be<br />

disadvantageous."<br />

(3)Eunice Schuster, Native American Anarchism<br />

( New Yo r k: AL\1S Pres s, 19 7 0 ), D • 1 3 .<br />

(4)Murray Rothbard, "-Individualist Anarchism in<br />

the United <strong>State</strong>s: Origins," Libertarian Analysis<br />

(Winter 1970), p. 14.<br />

(S)Schuster, p. 42; also see Corinne Jacker, The<br />

B I a e k F I agofAn archis m (N e w Y0 r k: Cha r I e sSeribne r<br />

<strong>and</strong> Sons, 1968), pp. 25-26.<br />

(6 )Schus ter, p. 41.<br />

(7)Jaeker, p. 10. David Deleon, in his The<br />

American as Anarchist (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press,<br />

1978), argues that the individual ism of indigenous<br />

American anarchism is rooted in three factors: religion,<br />

the great open frontier, <strong>and</strong> capitalism. Protestantism<br />

certainly did individualize religion. But<br />

since it would have the same impact on both sides of<br />

the A t 1ant i c, I don T t see how i t ca n be a fa c tor explaining<br />

the individualism in America as distinct<br />

from the collectivism in Europe. Moreover, it should<br />

not be for got ten t hat man y 0 f tho s e wh 0 a r r i ve d at<br />

their anarchism via their religious individualism did<br />

not become individual ist anarchists at all, but<br />

anarcho-communists. Leo Tolstoy in Russia <strong>and</strong> John<br />

213


Hum p h r e y N0 yes i nAmerica are two s·uc hex a. mpies • Fin ­<br />

a 11 y, wh i 1 e many rei igious sects came to Amer ica seeki<br />

n g "r eli g i 0 u s f r e e d 0 m ,n wh a t the y me ant by t his wa s<br />

not freedom for the individual worshiper, but freedom<br />

for the sec t a s a wh 0 Ie, co upIed wit h rig i d con formit y<br />

b Y the mem b e r s 0 f the sec t • The Pur itansat Ma s sach usetts<br />

Bay are an outst<strong>and</strong>ing example. They wanted<br />

" rei i g i 0 u s f r e e d om" topraetice inthe i r . own wa y • But<br />

theyes tab lis h e d a the0 c r a c y d om ina ted by are 1 i g i 0 us<br />

aristocracy. The primary functions of the state were<br />

to compel church attendance, collect taxes for the suppor<br />

t of the church <strong>and</strong> to preserve rei igious orthodoxy.<br />

I t was in pursuit of the latter end that such religious<br />

dissenters as Roger Williams <strong>and</strong> Anne Hutchinson were<br />

e x pel led. T hus, the impact 0 f rei i g ion 0 nthe emerge n c e<br />

of American individualism is difficult to gauge. Certainly<br />

it is not a one way street. The other difference<br />

between Deleon's interpretation <strong>and</strong> mine is his<br />

treatment of the open frontier <strong>and</strong> capitalism as two<br />

dis tin c t f act 0 r s • But itse em s tome t hat the ex i sten<br />

ceo f the 0 pen fro n tie r wa s I a r gel y res ponsib I e for<br />

the emergence of capitalism. As noted in the text, in<br />

n ear 1 y everye 0 Ion y a con c e r t ed e f for t wa s rna d e to<br />

transplant the European feudal structure <strong>and</strong> these<br />

attempts failed because of the presence of the open<br />

frontier.<br />

(8)10 Schuster, p. 35.<br />

(9 )On Anne Hutch inson, the early Quakers <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Antinomian Doctrine <strong>and</strong> its relation to anarchism see<br />

Schuster, pp. 13-39; Rothbard pp. 14-28; <strong>and</strong> Deleon,<br />

pp. 14-23.<br />

(10 )For a good presentation of the principles of<br />

Transcendental ism <strong>and</strong> a summary of the views of two<br />

leading exponents, Emerson <strong>and</strong> Thoreau, see A. J.<br />

Bei tzinger, A History of American Political Thought<br />

( New Y 0 r k: Do d d , Mead<strong>and</strong> Co., 19 7 2 ), Pp. 341 -47. AIso<br />

see Alpheus Mason, "Romantic Individualism," Free<br />

Go v ernmentin the Ma kin g, e d: A• T. Ma son ( New Yo r k :<br />

Oxford University Press, 1965), pp. 474-79. On the<br />

reI i g i 0 usb a sis 0 f rna n y 0 f the r ad i c a Ire I i g i 0 usana r ­<br />

chi s t comm u nit i e s 0 f the n i net e en t h c e n t u r y, see Lew i s<br />

Perry's excellent "Versions of Anarchism in the Antislavery<br />

Movement," American Quarterly (Winter 1968),<br />

pp. 768-82. Also see Schuster, pp. 410-86. For a description<br />

of John Humphrey Noyes' Oneida Community<br />

see Stow Persons, "Christian Communitarianism in<br />

Am e ric a ,It Soc i ali sma n d Am e rican L i fe, V0 I. 1, e d s . :<br />

Dona ld Drew Egbert <strong>and</strong> Stow Persons (Princeton:<br />

Princeton UnIversity Press, 1952), pp. 127-51. Also of<br />

interest' is Morris Bishop, "The Great Oneida Love-in,"<br />

214


American Heritage (February 1969), pp. 14-17. For a<br />

statement of the principles of Adin Ballou, the founder<br />

of the Hopedale Community, see his Christian Non­<br />

Resistance (New York: Da Capo Press, 1970). For a<br />

commentary on the Hopedale experiment, as well as many<br />

other anarchist <strong>and</strong> social ist communities in early<br />

n i net e e nth c en t u r yAm e rica, see J 0 hn Hump h r e y Noyes,<br />

History of American Social isms (New York: Hillary<br />

House Pub., 1961), especially pp. 119-32.<br />

(11)Adin Ballou, "Remarks at. tbe First Annual<br />

M e e tin g 0 f ·t heN 0 n - Res i s tan c e Soc i e t y, B 0 s ton ,<br />

Massachusetts, September 25, 1839," Patterns of<br />

Anarchy, eds.: L. I. Kr immerman <strong>and</strong> Lewis Perry (New<br />

Yo r k : Do ubi e day <strong>and</strong> Co., 19 6 6 ), PP • 14 6- 47 •<br />

(12)ln Schuster, P. 116.<br />

( 1 3 ) J 0 s i a h War r en, Eq u itab I e Comme r ce (N ew Yo r k :<br />

Bur t Frankl in, 19 5 2 ), P• 58 • For apr e sentat ion 0 f the<br />

d eve lopmen t 0 fin d i v i d uali s tic a narchism t hat i n rna ny<br />

ways parallels that taken here see Lawrence Moss, "Privat<br />

e Pro per t y Anarchism: An Am e rica n Va riant, n Fur ther<br />

Explorat ions in the Theory of Anarchism, ed.: Gordon<br />

Tu·llock (Blackburg, Va.: University Publications,<br />

1974), p. 1-31.<br />

(14)Stephen P. Andrews, The Science of <strong>Society</strong><br />

(Weston, Mass.: M <strong>and</strong> S Press, 1970), p. 13. For an<br />

ex c ell en t, s u c c inc t, s tat erne n t a f And r ews' views see<br />

Bowman Hall "The Economi c Theories of Stephen Pearl<br />

Andrews: Neglected Utopian Writer," The South African<br />

Journal of Economics (March 1975). Hall's conclusion<br />

is that Andrews provided a "lucid <strong>and</strong> concise statement<br />

of the ideas originally but chaotically proposed by<br />

"Josiah Warren" <strong>and</strong> that "his philosophy can be said to<br />

carry the Lockean ideas found in the Declaration of<br />

Independence <strong>and</strong> the ideas found in the The Wealth of<br />

Nations to their logical extreme." On both counts<br />

Hall is surely correct.<br />

(15)Warren, P. 57.<br />

(16)Andrews, p. 63.<br />

(17)Ibid., p. 63. Note the striking similarity<br />

between the thought of Warren <strong>and</strong> Andrews <strong>and</strong> the ideas<br />

being propounded independently in France by P. J.<br />

Pro u d h 0 n . Pro u d h 0 n bel i eve d t hat "L i be r t y wa s the<br />

Mother, not the Daughter, of Order."<br />

(18)Ibid., p. 64.<br />

(19)Warren, p. 61. Warren admitted that there<br />

might be a few cases where individualism was impossible.<br />

In such cases he allowed for a "Deliberative<br />

Council" which would be composed of community leaders<br />

or exper ts. The Counci 1 would be called into session<br />

to dISCUSS a particular problem <strong>and</strong> dissolve itself<br />

215


immediately following its decision.' Further, the members<br />

were to be paid only after they rendered their<br />

services. See Schuster, p. 102.<br />

( 20 ) And r e ws, p. 53; a Iso see Wa r r en, p. 41. Bo t h<br />

Warren <strong>and</strong> Andrews merely said that the only just price<br />

was that based upon cost. They acknowledged that the<br />

p r inc i pie of II i nd i v i d ua I sovereignty" left i t up to the<br />

discretion of the individual to respect or reject this<br />

moral cost principle.<br />

(21)Warren, pp. 43-48; also see Boman Hall, "The<br />

Economic Ideas of Josiah War r-eh· , First American<br />

A n arc his t ," His tor y 0 f Pol i ticalEconomy, 6, (19 7 4 ) ,<br />

p. 99.<br />

(22)Warren, p. 85.<br />

(23)See James Martin, Men Against the <strong>State</strong><br />

(Colorado Springs: Ralph Myles PUblishing Co., 1970),<br />

p. 27. Whether such "modifications" as repugnance <strong>and</strong><br />

intensity can be reconciled with the labor theory of<br />

value is indeed doubtful.<br />

(24)Warren, p. 76; also see Schuster, p. 105-06.<br />

(25)Andrews, pp. 96-98, <strong>and</strong> Warren, pp. 65-67.<br />

(26)Warren, p. 49.<br />

(27)Ibid., p. 66.<br />

(28) Ibid., p. 49. Harold Barclay has argued<br />

that Warren was, at least in his later years, only<br />

"peripherally anarchistic" <strong>and</strong> in fact advocated a<br />

"I imi ted government much in the tradition of Thomas<br />

Jefferson. tl See his "Josiah Warren: The Incomplete<br />

A n arc his t ," An arc h y (Ma r c h 1968), p p. 90 - 9 6 • The<br />

argument is interesting but unconvincing in that<br />

Barclay's case rests on the false assumption that anarchi<br />

sma n d the use 0 f for cear e incompat i b 1e • Fur the r ,<br />

whether Warren was or was not an anarchist is really<br />

irrelevant for our purpose, for it cannot be doubted<br />

that his concept of "individual sovereignty" was the<br />

foundat ion for what his successors developed into the<br />

American doctrine of "philosophical anarchism."<br />

(29 )For a good explanat ion of this process see<br />

Hall, p. 96.<br />

(30)Warren, p. 47.<br />

(31)Ibid., p. 80.<br />

(32)Andrews, p. 69.<br />

(33)Hall, p. 106.<br />

(34)Andrews, P. 70.<br />

(35)Warren, p. 68; <strong>and</strong> see Andrews, p. 138, <strong>and</strong><br />

Hall, ltJosiah Warren," p. 197.<br />

(36)Andrews, p. 62.<br />

(37)Ibid., p. 44.<br />

( 38 ) Via r tin, p. xii.<br />

(39)ln Ibid., p. 128.<br />

216


( 4 0 ) I nib i d . ,... p. 1 1 2 • He yw00dar g uedthat lega I<br />

tender laws were "class currency."<br />

(41)ln ibid., p. 130.<br />

(42)Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner, "Constitutinnl Law, Relative<br />

t 0 C red it, Cur r e n c y <strong>and</strong> Bn nkin g ," The Co lIec ted Wo r k s<br />

o fLy san d e r S p 0 0 n e r, Vo. V ( We s ton ,Mas s .: M<strong>and</strong> S<br />

Pres s, 19 71 ), P• 24.<br />

(43)Ibid., p. 27.<br />

(44)See ibid. Also see Carl Watner, "The Works<br />

of Lys<strong>and</strong>e r Spooner," address before .the ed i tor s of the<br />

Liberty Book,n.d., pp. 2-3.<br />

(45)Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner, "The Unconstitutionality of<br />

the Laws of Congress Prohibiting Pri vateMail s , fiThe<br />

Collected Works of Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner Vol. I (Weston,<br />

Mass: M <strong>and</strong>S Press, 1971), p. 7.<br />

(46)Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner, "Letter to Grover<br />

Clevel<strong>and</strong>," The Collected Works of Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner,<br />

Vol. I (Weston, Mass: M <strong>and</strong> S Press, 1971), p. 42.<br />

(47)Benjamin Tucker, "An Unwarranted Question,"<br />

Ins tea d 0 f aBo 0 k (N e w Yo r k: A r no Pres s<strong>and</strong> The New<br />

York Times, 1972), p. 208.<br />

(48}Greene's description of the operations of the<br />

mutual bank can be found in his "The Mutual Bank," in<br />

American Radical Thought, ed.: H. J. Silverman<br />

(Lexington, Mass.: D. C. Heath, 197.0), pp. 138-41.<br />

A 1 s 0 see Mar tin, p p. 1 3 1 - 32 • On e can ea s i I Y see the<br />

simi lar i ties between Proudhon's mutual bank <strong>and</strong> that<br />

espoused by Greene. The Proudhonian influence on<br />

Greene is clearly documented in Wiliam Reichert,<br />

Partisans of <strong>Freedom</strong> (BoWling Green: Bowling Green<br />

<strong>State</strong> University, Popular Press, 1976), pp. 100-16.<br />

For a good summary of Proudhon's banking ideas <strong>and</strong> a<br />

critique of mutual banking see Herbert Osgood,<br />

"Scientific Anarchism," Political Science Quarterly<br />

(Ma r c h 1889 ), Pp. 15- 18, 34- 36 •<br />

( 49 )Ma r tin, p • 1 7 6 •<br />

( 50 ) I bid., p p. 2 1 2 -13; a 1so see Mur ra y Ro t hba r d ,<br />

11 The S po 0 n e r. - T u c k e r Doc t r i n e: An Econom i s t 's View, 11<br />

Egalitarianism As A Revolt Against Nature, <strong>and</strong> Other<br />

Essays (Washington, D.C.: Libertarian Press, 1974), p.<br />

133; <strong>and</strong> Osgood, pp. 34-36.<br />

(51)ln Martin, p. 138.<br />

(52)ln Schuster, p. 105.<br />

(53)Andrews, p. 7.<br />

(54)Ibid., p. 145.<br />

(55)Ibid.<br />

( 56 )Ma r tin, pp. 144- 48 .<br />

(57)Ibid., p. 153.<br />

(58) Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner, "The Law of Intellectual<br />

PropertY,TI Collected Works of Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner, Vol.<br />

217


III (Weston, Mass.: M <strong>and</strong> S Press, 1971), pp. 27-8,<br />

80-9. (59) I n Car I Wa tner, "Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner: From<br />

Const·itutional Lawyer to Individualist-Anarchist,"<br />

(Address delivered at the Third Libertarian Scholars<br />

Conference, October 5, 1975), p. 13. For an excellent<br />

<strong>and</strong> in-depth analysis of the Spooner-Tucker debate on<br />

this issue see Carl Watner's two part article "A<br />

Question of Property: two opinions," The d<strong>and</strong>elion<br />

(Spring <strong>and</strong> Summer, 1977), pp. 4-21; 4-12,<br />

respectively.<br />

( 6 0 ) T u eke r, "P r 0 per t y Un de r Ana r chi sm," Ins tead<br />

of a Book, p. 311. On Ingall's influence on later<br />

anarchists also see Moss, op.cit., pp. 10-11.<br />

( 61 ) T u eke r, "w her e We S ta nd ," Ins t ead of a Book,<br />

p. 52. (62)Victor Yarros, "Individualist or Philosophical<br />

Anarchism," The New Encyclopedia of Social Reform,<br />

eds.: W. D. P. Bliss <strong>and</strong> R. M. Binder (1908), p. 42.<br />

( 6 3 ) T u eke r, " Con t raetor 0 r gani s m, What' s That t 0<br />

Us? tt, Ins tead 0 f a Bo 0 k t P• 33.<br />

(64)Tucker, "Competitive Protection," Instead of<br />

a Book, p. 327.<br />

(65)Gustave de Molinari, The PrOduction of<br />

Security (New York: Center for Libertarian Studies,<br />

1977), pp.6-9.<br />

(66)Ibid., p. 8.<br />

(67)ln Carl Watner, "Les 'Economistes'<br />

Libertaires," Reason (January 1977), p. 26.<br />

(68)Ibid. This article provides a good<br />

discussion of the entire French controversy over this<br />

matter. For more on the early nineteenth century<br />

F r e n c h r a d i c a lin d i v i d ua lis t ssee Ma r k We i nbur g, "The<br />

Soc i a I A n a I y sis 0 f T h r e e Ear 1 y 1 9 t h Ce n t u r y F r en c h<br />

Liberals: Say, Comte, <strong>and</strong> Dunoyer," The Journal of<br />

Libertarian StUdies (Winter 1978), pp. 45-63.<br />

(69)Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner, "Natural Law, or the Science<br />

of Justice," Collected Works of Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner Vol.<br />

I (Weston, Mass.: M <strong>and</strong> S Press, 1971), p. 6. Also<br />

relevant for Spooner's natural law position is his<br />

Vices are Not Crimes: A Vindication of Moral Liberty<br />

(Baltimore, 1977). This pamphlet was published<br />

a non y m0 u sly i n 1 8 7 5. Sin c e its aut h 0 r s hip wa s not<br />

discovered until recently, it was not included in his<br />

Collected Works.<br />

(70)Spooner, "Natural Law," pp. 9-11.<br />

(71)lbid., pp. 11-12.<br />

(72 )Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner, "No Treason, Number One,"<br />

The Collected Works of Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner (Weston,<br />

Ma s s .: M<strong>and</strong> S Pre s s, 19 7 1 ), p • 6.<br />

218


(73)Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner, "No Treason, Number Six,"<br />

The Collected Works of Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner Vol.<br />

(Weston, Mass.: M<strong>and</strong> S Press, 1971), pp. 1-59.<br />

( 7 4 ) F red Mille r, " L Ysan dera n d Lim i ted Go vern ­<br />

ment," Reason (May, 1976) pp. 19-21, asserts that<br />

Spooner's argument is actually consistent only with<br />

1 imi ted government, <strong>and</strong> not anarchism. To some extent,<br />

this is a matter of semantics. If we define.government<br />

so as to make it compatible with no initiated force,<br />

then Spooner's philosophy is consistent with limited<br />

government. But then so are the philosophies of all<br />

other anarchists.<br />

(75)Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner, "An Essay on the Trial by<br />

Jury," The Collected Works of Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner, Vol.<br />

I I ( We s ton, Ma s s .: M<strong>and</strong> S Pres s, 19 7 1 ), P • 6.<br />

(76)Ibid. For a sneering "analysis" of<br />

Spooner's ideas see A. John Alex<strong>and</strong>er, "The Ideas of<br />

Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner," The New Engl<strong>and</strong> Quarterly (June<br />

1950), pp. 200-17. For a more sympathetic treatment of<br />

Spooner see such works as CarlWatner, "Lys<strong>and</strong>er<br />

Spooner, Libertarian Pioneer," Reason (March, 1973),<br />

pp. 20-23; Carl Watner, "Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner: From<br />

Constitutional Lawyer to Individualist Anarchist," Ope<br />

cit.; Martin, pp. 167-201; <strong>and</strong> Reichert, pp. 117-40.<br />

Also of interest is Charles Shively's "BIography" of<br />

Spooner in The Collected Works of Lys<strong>and</strong>er Spooner,<br />

V0 I. I ( We s t on, Ma s s .: M<strong>and</strong> S Pre s s, 19 7 1 ), Pp. 15 - 62 .<br />

( 7 7 ) Ma x S t i r n e r, The Ego <strong>and</strong> His Own ( New Yo r k :<br />

Dover PUblishing, 1973), p. 5.<br />

(78)Ibid., p. 179.<br />

( 79 ) T u c k e r, "I n d i v i d u a ISo v ere i gn t y Our Goa I , "<br />

Ins tea d 0 f aBo 0 k, P • 1 32 • Ric ha r d His k e s has rna d e a<br />

very strong case that "to the extent that Tucker<br />

believes in equal liberty he is no egoist." See his<br />

Community <strong>and</strong> <strong>Freedom</strong>: The Political Theory of Cooperative<br />

Individualism (Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation:<br />

Indiana University, 1979). See especially, p. 128: "To<br />

advocat'e egoism or the view that the 'only source of<br />

reasons for action lies in the interests of the<br />

agents,' precludes one from making dem<strong>and</strong>s or claims on<br />

others on any other basis than that of the power or<br />

·brute force one has to back up the claims. As a pacifist,<br />

Tucker would shrink at such a prospect; as an<br />

anarchist he must reject it, for of all types of political<br />

discontents anarchists are without doubt the most<br />

'resentfUl' of the political world in which they live."<br />

Further, Hlskes notes, Tucker's concern for "the law of<br />

equal liberty" actually smuggles in natural law principles<br />

(pp. 129-30).<br />

(80)Tucker, "A CrIticism That Does Not Apply,fl<br />

219


CHAPTER VII<br />

The Politico-Economic Perspective<br />

of Individualist Anarchism<br />

The i nd i v i dual ist anarchist paradign is a synthesis<br />

0 f phi los 0 phi c a I a narchism wit h mo der n e conom i c s •<br />

The ph i losophical anarchist framework of competing police<br />

agencies sell ing their services on the free market<br />

i sad 0 pte d • But the phi los 0 phi ca I ana r ch i s t s, s ubscr<br />

i bing to the labor theory of value, bel ieved that<br />

free competition would eliminate profit, rent <strong>and</strong> interest<br />

by reducing price to cost. This belief in the<br />

labor theory of value is replaeed by the subjective<br />

value-marginal utility approach of modern economics.<br />

The individualist anarchists do not believe that free<br />

competition would eliminate profit. Rather, it is the<br />

phenomenon of profit <strong>and</strong> loss as they see it, that performs<br />

the essential social function of directing economic<br />

activity into the satisfaction of consumer dem<strong>and</strong>.<br />

By blending the institutional framework of philosophical<br />

anarchism with the marginal utility approach of<br />

modern economics, the individualist anarchist believes<br />

t ha t he has developed the out line for a workable<br />

government less society.<br />

This chapter deals with a series of diverse topics<br />

that wi 11 clar i fy the organizational principles upon<br />

which individualist anarchism is based. It is only<br />

after this general framework has been articulated that<br />

the specifics of the individualist anarchist framework<br />

can be examined.<br />

1. SOCIAL COORDINATION<br />

All societ ies must have some means for coordinating<br />

the act ions of the individual members. The larger<br />

<strong>and</strong> m0 r e compie x the soc i e t y the morediff i cuI t<strong>and</strong><br />

crucial this problem becomes. How the individualist<br />

a n arc his t soc i e t y w0 u 1d a pproa c h t his prob I em ca n be<br />

seen by contrasting the operations of the collective<br />

anarchist society with that of individualist anarchism.<br />

Bot h t Ypes 0 fan arc his mad v 0 cat e e con om i c f r e edom.<br />

Yet, it is clear that they mean widely different things<br />

by this. The collectivist anarchists believe that<br />

economic freedom entails the abolition of the entire<br />

market paraphernalia of exchange, private property,<br />

wages, profit <strong>and</strong> loss, while the indIvidualist anar-<br />

221


chist advocates the sanctity of private property <strong>and</strong><br />

the entire market system.<br />

For analytical purposes collectivist anarchism can<br />

be divided into two broad types: anarcho-syndicalism or<br />

fun c t ion a 1 collec t i vism• <strong>and</strong> a narch 0 - comm un ism 0 r ge 0 ­<br />

graphical collectivism. Under anarcho-syndicalism society<br />

would be organized on the basis of functions.<br />

Each industry would be owned <strong>and</strong> operated by the worke<br />

r sin t hat pa r ticu 1a r i nd us try. The mine r s wo u 1down<br />

<strong>and</strong> 0 per ate the co a lind us try; the t r uc ke r s wo u I down<br />

<strong>and</strong> make all of the decisions within the trucking ind<br />

us try. etc. Pre suma b 1y. the r e wo u I d be on e supr asyndicate<br />

to integrate the operations of the independent<br />

syndicates with each other.(l) Anarcho-communism.<br />

on the other h<strong>and</strong>. is organized on the basis of geography.<br />

"The revolution," says Kropotkin, "must strive<br />

toenablee v e r y c omm un j t y t 0 sus t a init s elf. t 0 be come<br />

mat e ria I 1yin d e pen den t • " ( 2 ) T husea c h c omm unit y 0 r<br />

commune is to be large enough to be completely selfsupporting.<br />

Kropotkin, for example, refers to the<br />

communities as consisting of "a few millions of inhabitants."(3)<br />

They would be primarily agricultural, but<br />

industry would also exist. Modern technology, he argues,<br />

would make agricultural production so plentiful<br />

that" our h y pot h e t i cal i nha bitant s would be led ne c e s ­<br />

s a r i 1 Y t 0 em p loy the i r lei sur e i n rna n u f act uri ng, art i s ­<br />

tic, scientific, <strong>and</strong> other pursuits."(4)<br />

Regardless of which type of collectivist anarchism<br />

is advocated, all money, wages, exchange <strong>and</strong> prices<br />

would be abolished. "There will be no buying <strong>and</strong> selling,"<br />

says Berkman. "Exchange will be free." Each<br />

group of producers or each syndicate will deposit their<br />

produce at the community warehouses <strong>and</strong> be given in return<br />

whatever they need. Need rather than profit will<br />

d e t e r min e what i s prod u ced, <strong>and</strong> c omm 0 n sensewi I I tel I<br />

the members of the community what is needed <strong>and</strong> how it<br />

should be produced. "As much coal will be mined as<br />

will be necessary to satisfy the need. Similarly, will<br />

as much food be raised as the country needs. It will<br />

be the requirements of the community <strong>and</strong> the supply<br />

obtaining which will determine the amounts it is to<br />

receive. This applies to coal <strong>and</strong> food as to all other<br />

needs of the people."(S)<br />

Inc 0 n t r a s t towhat may be ca lIed the rna n ua lor<br />

conscious coordination endemic to anarcho-collectivism,<br />

the individualist anarchist opts for what he believes<br />

to be the automatic or spontaneous coordina-<br />

222


t ion a f for de d by the rna r ke t s ystem. In fa c t, the individualist<br />

anarchist is very critical of the principle<br />

of conscious coordination for two reasons: for the<br />

political reason that the principle itself entails the<br />

rei n t rod u c t ion 0 f the s tat e; <strong>and</strong> for the e con om i c<br />

rea son t hat therei s no a I t erna t i vet 0 the rna r k e tin<br />

any soc let y abovet h e mo s t s imp 1 e <strong>and</strong> econom i caII y<br />

backward.<br />

There are three problems of coordination that must<br />

be solved in any socio-economic system: [1] the problem<br />

of priortities, i.e., what goods <strong>and</strong> services should<br />

be produe e d; [2] t he pro b I em of ef fie i en c y, i. e. ,<br />

what c om bina t ion 0 f res 0 ur c esus edin the prod uc t ion 0 f<br />

a commodity will (a) not impede the production of goods<br />

des i red more intensely by the consumers, <strong>and</strong> (b) leave<br />

the largest bundle of resources left over for the product<br />

ion of other goods <strong>and</strong> services; <strong>and</strong> [3] the problem<br />

of distribution, i.e., how to compensate each<br />

participant in the productive process.(6)<br />

Both the individualist anarchist critique of the<br />

principle of conscious dIrection <strong>and</strong> the view of the<br />

market process as a method of spontaneous coordination<br />

can b e h i g h I i g h ted by i n d i cat i ng how the y bel i eve t hat<br />

the market system approaches <strong>and</strong> is able to solve these<br />

three problems.<br />

a. Priorities.<br />

The individualist anarchists argue that since consumers<br />

only buy what they intend to use, one can make a<br />

profIt only by producing what others desire. Hence,<br />

there can be no distinction between production for use<br />

<strong>and</strong> pro d u c t ion for profit. Wit h I n a rna r ke t s ystem<br />

priorities are therefore set by the consumers' buying<br />

<strong>and</strong> abs t en t i on from buying. Entrepreneurs, anxious to<br />

maximize their profits, will tend to produce those<br />

goods with the greatest discrepancy between total<br />

rev e n u e <strong>and</strong> tot a I cos t • I tis inth i s wa y t hat the<br />

unhampered price system is able to disseminate the<br />

needed informat ion to market participants. One need<br />

only be concerned with the prices that are relevant to<br />

him. If consumer dem<strong>and</strong> for any good increases or its<br />

supply decreases, its price would rise, thereby encouraging<br />

Its increased production. Conversely, if consumer<br />

dem<strong>and</strong> decreased or the supply increased, the price<br />

would fall thereby discouraging production. Thus the<br />

i n d i v i d uall s tanarchis t s a r gue t hat the rna r ke t pro C e s s<br />

works in such a way as to produce precisely those goods<br />

that consumers wish to buy.<br />

223


A common criticism of this type of reasoning is<br />

that there are many examples where the market cannot be<br />

said to reflect the priorities of the consumers. It is<br />

assumed, for example, that bread is more important than<br />

diamonds while it is noted that the price of diamonds<br />

is much greater than that of bread. The error in this<br />

1 i ne of reason i ng is tha t individuals are never confronted<br />

with a choice between diamonds in the abstract<br />

<strong>and</strong> bread in the abstract. Instead,. they choose between<br />

individual units of bread <strong>and</strong> diamonds. Since<br />

under normal conditions that quantity of bread greatly<br />

exceeds that of diamonds, the satisfaction or dissatisfaction<br />

caused by the addition or loss of any particu­<br />

1a run itof bread , i.e., its rna r gina 1 uti 1 i t Y , i s reI a ­<br />

tively low compared with that of any unit of diamonds.<br />

Were, by some quirk of fate, the quantity of bread<br />

great ly reduced or that of diamonds significantly increased,<br />

the marginal utility of the units of bread <strong>and</strong><br />

diamonds would be altered causing the price of bread to<br />

rise <strong>and</strong> that of diamonds to fall. It can therefore be<br />

seen, a r g ue the i nd i v i d ua listanarchis t s, t hat the rna r ­<br />

ket does in fact reflect the priorities of the consumers<br />

<strong>and</strong> does so without the need for any conscious direction<br />

<strong>and</strong> control. In fact, any such control would<br />

only impede consumer satisfaction for, as the economist<br />

I s rae 1 K i r z nern0 t e s, " any non - rna r ke t 0 bs t a c I e s p I aced<br />

in the way of the pricing process thus necessarily<br />

interfere with the priority system that the consumers<br />

have set up."(7)<br />

I t should be noted at this juncture that this view<br />

of price formation indicates a significant difference<br />

between the modern individualist anarchists <strong>and</strong> their<br />

nineteenth century cous ins, the philosophical anarchists.<br />

The labor theory of value, so dear to men like<br />

Tucker, has been replaced by the modern principle of<br />

sub j e c t i v e val ue, <strong>and</strong> its coroll a r y, rna r gina I uti lit Y•<br />

Prices for the individualist anarchist are to be determined<br />

not by the quantity of labor involved in product<br />

ion but b Y wh a t the rna r ke t wi 1 I bea r, i. e., by supply<br />

<strong>and</strong> dem<strong>and</strong>.<br />

b. Efficiency.<br />

For the i nd i v i d uali s tanarchis t the prob 1em 0 f the<br />

efficient allocation of resources is to be h<strong>and</strong>led in<br />

the Same way that the problem of priorities is to be<br />

h<strong>and</strong>led: the price system. To produce their goods the<br />

entrepreneurs must bid for the needed resources. They,<br />

therefore, st<strong>and</strong> in the same relation to the sellers of<br />

224


esources as the consumers do to the sellers of final<br />

go od s. Thus, pr ices for the var i ous factor s of product<br />

i on tend to reflect the dem<strong>and</strong> for them by the entrepreneurs.<br />

Since what the entrepreneur is able to bid<br />

is limited by his expected yield on the final sale of<br />

his product, the libertarians believe that the factors<br />

of production are channeled into production of the<br />

goods most in dem<strong>and</strong> by the consumers. Those who best<br />

serve the consumers earn the greatest profits <strong>and</strong>,<br />

hence, are able to offer the highest bids for the resources<br />

they need. If returns are not high enough to<br />

cover the cost of a particUlar operation, this means<br />

that there is, in the eyes of the consumers, a more<br />

important use for the factors of production elsewhere.<br />

The market, therefore, allocates resources to their<br />

m0 s t pro due t i ve poi n t reI a t i vet 0 the prior i t y s ystem<br />

that the consumers have established.<br />

This can be demonstrated by the following. Assume<br />

t hat the rna r k etis in eq u iIi br i urn. Al so as s ume t ha t a<br />

new technological breakthrough has enabled the product<br />

i on of a new commod i ty that is highly valued by the<br />

consumers. The production of the commodity, however,<br />

requi res the use of factor A. Those entrepreneurs who<br />

perceive this new profit opportunity will begin to bid<br />

for the fa c tor. T his inc rea sed competit ion for the<br />

available supply of A will cause its price to rise,<br />

forcing some of the users of A to curtail their purchases.<br />

But who wi II be the ones forced to curtail<br />

the i r pur c has e s ? C I ear 1y, i t wi I I beth0 seemp loye r s<br />

of A who are receiving the least remuneration for their<br />

product from the consumers, i.e., those who are employi<br />

n g A init s I e a s t produe t i ve poi n t • Inth i s wa y, the<br />

use 0 f A i s c han n e 1 e d f r om use s t hat the cons urn e r s<br />

value less highly into uses that they value more highly.<br />

But fur ther, the rise in the price <strong>and</strong> therefore<br />

the prof it margins of A will encourage other entrepreneurs,<br />

also anxious to make profits, to exp<strong>and</strong> the<br />

supply of A.<br />

In other words, the individualist anarchists believethat<br />

the price fluc t ua t ion s 0 f the rna r k e t proc e s s<br />

automatically coordinate the actions of all participants<br />

in the system by transmitting the relevant know­<br />

1 e d g e pre cis ely tot h 0 s e wh 0 r equi ret hat pa r ticu 1a r<br />

information to guide their actions. For example, informa<br />

t i on about rubber is commun i ca ted to tire manufacturers,<br />

while information about steel is communicated<br />

to automobile manufacturers, etc. As F. A. Hayek<br />

states, "The marvel is that Without an order being<br />

225


issued, without more than a h<strong>and</strong>ful of people knowing<br />

the cause, tens of thous<strong>and</strong>s of people whose identity<br />

cou 1 d not be as cer ta i ned by months of invest igat ion,<br />

are made to••• move in the right direction."(B)<br />

c. Distribution.<br />

Since under the free market those eager to earn<br />

profits can do so only by producing better than their<br />

competitors what the consumers desire to buy, the individualist<br />

anarchists contend that there can be no distinction<br />

between production <strong>and</strong> distribution. The more<br />

sa tis factor i ly one serves the consumers, the more profits<br />

he will earn. "The only means to acquire wealth<br />

<strong>and</strong> to preserve it in a market economy not adulterated<br />

by government-made restriction," says <strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>,<br />

"is to serve the consumers in the best <strong>and</strong> cheapest<br />

way."(9)<br />

This means that wealth is not dispersed on the<br />

basis of personal moral merit but purely according to<br />

one's a b iIi t y top r 0 v ide 0 the r s wit h wh a t the y wa n t •<br />

While this may be considered unjust from some higher<br />

point of view, the libertarians regard It as one of the<br />

market's greatest merits. The dem<strong>and</strong> for a "just" distribution<br />

of wealth, argues Hayek, implies that wealth<br />

be distributed according to moral merit. But this<br />

mea n s t hat s om e per son 0 r s om e g r 0 up mus t be compIe tel y<br />

cognizant of all the motivations that prompted any individual<br />

to engage in any particular action <strong>and</strong> then<br />

allocate rewards accordingly. But since "we cannot<br />

know or isolate all the circumstances which determine<br />

mer it, tf wit h 0 u t the compIetee1 i mina t ion 0 fin d i v i d ua 1<br />

privacy, the allocation of wealth according to "merit"<br />

is incompatible with a free society.(lO)<br />

The dispersion of wealth in a market society, libertarians<br />

argue, is in itself neither just nor unjust.<br />

It is functional from the point of view of facilitating<br />

the satisfaction of all market participants; it is also<br />

an integral aspect of a free society.<br />

d. <strong>State</strong>, Economy <strong>and</strong> Conscious Coordination.<br />

Since the market process spontaneously coordinates<br />

the act ion s 0 f a II me r ke t pe r tic i pe n t s tIt canoperat e<br />

wit h the u t m0 s t dec e n t r ali z a t ion 0 f know 1e d ge. S uc h<br />

ope rat ion permit s eve r yon e t 0 de vis e <strong>and</strong> pur sue his ow n<br />

p I a n s, run n i n g the gam u t from pur ely s elf ish to a 1 t r uist<br />

IC. It makes no difference what ends any individual<br />

226


may c h 00 s e; the fa c t r ema ins t hat the mo resa tis fa c tori<br />

ly .one produces what the others desire, the more money<br />

he will earn <strong>and</strong> hence the better able he will be to<br />

pursue his own goals, whatever they may be. But, in<br />

the absence of the price system the coordination of<br />

individual actions cannot be spontaneously generated.<br />

Rather, it requires conscious coordination <strong>and</strong> control.<br />

T his, howe v e r, c rea t esad i I amma for collec t i vis t<br />

a n arc his m • Sin ceo u t put s are rna t e ria I Iyin t e r depen ­<br />

den t, not on I y mus t product ion quotas be set for each<br />

i n d u s try insuc h a wa y as to coo r dinate the 0 u t put s 0 f<br />

all industr ies wi th one another, but all resources,<br />

including labor, must be allocated so as to enable each<br />

industry to attain its particular production quota. If<br />

i tis dec ide d by the C en t ralP1ann i n g Boa r d t hat the<br />

expansion of production in branch A would be desirable,<br />

res 0 u r c e s mu s t bet ran s fer red to i t from some 0 the r<br />

branch or branches. On the market this would be done<br />

by means of the pr ice system. If there is a need for<br />

expansion in one area, prices for the respective factor<br />

s, inc Iud i n g 1abor, wo u 1d r i s e in 0 r de r t a a t t r act<br />

them into that area. But in the absence of the price<br />

system the transfer requires conscious direction. Ind<br />

i v i d u a Ism u s t betran s fer red from bra n c h B, wh i chi s<br />

considered economically less desirable to the more<br />

economically desirable branch A. A crucial problem<br />

a r i s e s i f we ask what wi I I bet h e pol icy 0 f the n c omm un<br />

i tyn if the individuals who must be transferred balk?<br />

There are only two alternatives: [1] coerce them, or<br />

[2] allow them to go their own way. If the former is<br />

adopted, then clearly the state has not been abolished,<br />

for coercion is being initiated against individuals who<br />

themselves have not coerced anyone. But if the second<br />

alternative is adopted, the production quota of branch<br />

A wi II not be met. This, in turn, means that the industries<br />

dependent upon the output of A will, likewise,<br />

be una b let 0 me e t the i r pro d u c t ion quo t as, etc., in<br />

ever widening circles.<br />

Since plan attainment requires that resources be<br />

.allocated in the correct proportions, any spontaneous<br />

act ion wi II prevent the anticipated outputs from being<br />

attained. Plan fulfillment is therefore contingent<br />

u p 0 n e i the r [1] eve r yon e vol u n tar i 1 Y f 0 I 1ow i n g the<br />

directives of the planning authority, or [2] investing<br />

the CPB with an apparatus of compulsion <strong>and</strong> coercion.<br />

Kropotkin envisions the anarchist commune as consisting<br />

of several million people. But in such a society voluntary<br />

acquiesence is highly improbable. As Hayek<br />

227


poi n t sout tit i s not en 0 ugh to ha ve a g r e em e nton pIa n ­<br />

ning in the abstract; there must be 100 percent agreemen<br />

t on every aspect of the plan - pr i or it i es, resource<br />

all 0 cat ion, <strong>and</strong> dis t ributi 0 n - 0 reo ere i on mus t be<br />

utilized.(ll) Since it is doubtful that the several<br />

mil I ion p e 0 pIe com p 0 sing the c omm un e will a t a I I time s<br />

adhere,to exactly the same scale of values, plan fulfillment<br />

in a collective anarchist society of the size<br />

envisioned by Kropotkin would dem<strong>and</strong>" a uniformity of<br />

action that is probably impossible to attain without<br />

the use of an agency possessing a monopoly on the use<br />

of compulsion <strong>and</strong> control, viz., the state.<br />

However, some have pointed out that the successful<br />

opera t i on of a market no less than a non-market economy<br />

r e qui res the em pI 0 ym en t 0 f res 0 ur c esin cor r e c t propor<br />

t ions. They conclude that the respective processes<br />

o f a I I 0 cat ion rna keli ttl e d ifferen c e . The Ind i v i d ua I ­<br />

i s tanarc his t 0 b j e c t s tot his con c I us ion. To pa r aph<br />

r a s e Hayek, the d if ference iss imi lar to tha t between<br />

erecting street signs <strong>and</strong> permitting each individual to<br />

chart his own course, on the one h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> telling the<br />

people which road they must take, on the other.(12)<br />

The pr ice system, it is argued, does not comm<strong>and</strong> anyone<br />

t 0 do any t h i n g • Eve r yon e i s f r e e to devis e his own<br />

plans <strong>and</strong> to follow or not to follow the market signals.<br />

"It would be . accurate to state," claims<br />

Rot h bard, "that inthe f r e e rna r ke t therei s s 0 vere i g n t y<br />

of the individual: the Individual is sovereign over<br />

his own person <strong>and</strong> actions <strong>and</strong> his own property. This<br />

may be termed individual self-sovereignty. To earn a<br />

monetary return, the individual producer must satisfy<br />

con sum e r d em<strong>and</strong>, but the ext e n t t 0 wh i c h he pur sues<br />

o the r non m0 net a r y fa c torsis en t ire I y a rna t t e r 0 f his<br />

own free cholce."(13) In the absence of the price systern<br />

i n d i v i d u a I sea n not be per mit ted the f r e e d om to<br />

choose their own goals, occupations, etc., for it is<br />

unl ikely that free choice will produce an allocation of<br />

labor in exactly the proportions required for plan<br />

f u I f ill men t. The 0 n I y wa y to ins ureth e cor r eetaI I 0cat<br />

ion of labor is for the CPB to transfer laborers<br />

wher eve r nee d e dan d top u n ish d e v i a t ion s from the<br />

orders. ThUS, the indivIdualist anarchist contends<br />

that collectivist anarchism is contradictory: a collectivist<br />

society of the size envisioned by Kropotkin<br />

presupposes the existence of a state.(14)<br />

The rei s yet an 0 the r prob 1em . Sin c e the r e wo u 1d<br />

ben 0 buy i n g 0 r s ell i n g, the r e wo u 1 d ben 0 mar k e t .<br />

T his pIa cest h e CP Bin a d I 1 emma . I nor de r t 0 de VIS e<br />

228


its plans, the CPB would require information about the<br />

p re fe r e n c e s 0 f "s 0 c i e t y • " T he prob 1em i s t hat s u c h<br />

information is neither static, centralized, nor independent<br />

of the preferences of the individuals who comprIse<br />

the "society." The information needed by the CPB<br />

i sin for rna t ion abo u t the needs<strong>and</strong> des ire s 0 fin d i v i d ualso<br />

By its very nature such information is radically<br />

deeentralized: it exists only in the minds of each<br />

<strong>and</strong> every individual in society. Such information is<br />

dynamic, changing as often as individuals alter their<br />

preferences. I t is also sUbjective. An individual's<br />

preferences can be known, even to himself, only through<br />

his act s 0 f c h 0 0 sing . On e rna y c I aim topreferA to B,<br />

but u n til <strong>and</strong> u n I e s she act uall y rna kesth e c hoi c e, he<br />

can never be certain.<br />

We I ive in an uncertain <strong>and</strong> ever-changing world.<br />

Information is scarce <strong>and</strong> costly. The problem of ignorance,<br />

of incomplete knowledge, is perhaps the key<br />

social <strong>and</strong> economic problem. But, argue libertarians,<br />

i tis jus t t his p r ob 1em t hat the co I lee t i vis t i gn 0 res<br />

by posit i n g the eX i s ten ceof a CPB wh i c h e i the r po s ­<br />

sesses, or is capable of obtainIng at little or no<br />

cost, all of the information needed for the construction<br />

of the economic plan.<br />

The virtue of the market process, libertarians are<br />

fond of pointing out, "IS the economy of knowledge with<br />

which it operates, or how little the individual<br />

particIpants need to know in order to take the right<br />

action."(15) The price system acts as a sensoring<br />

dev i ce wh i ch not only moni tors the ongoing changes in<br />

consumer priorities <strong>and</strong> other economic data, but<br />

rewards those who adjust to these changes while punishing<br />

those who do not.<br />

The economi c problem facing any society organized<br />

on pure collectivist, i.e., non-market, principles, is<br />

that if there is no market, the CPB would have no information<br />

<strong>and</strong> thus no economic basis on which to construct<br />

its plans. True, high speed computers could be<br />

used to collect data, but the decentralized, dynamic<br />

<strong>and</strong> subjective nature of the information required would<br />

render such data practically worthless. From an econom<br />

1 cpo i n t 0 f view, the dec i s ion s 0 f the CPB wo u 1d<br />

therefore be totally arbitrary. The resulting inefficiencies<br />

<strong>and</strong> distortions would entail capital decumulation<br />

WhICh, in turn, would mean progressive impoverlshrnent.(16)<br />

229


T h us, for two reasons, the e conom i erea son 0 f the<br />

absence of economic calculation in a socialist economy,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the pol i tical reason of the inevitable reintroduct<br />

ion 0 f the s tat e, the i nd i v i d ua listanarchis t rna i n ­<br />

tains that even a moderately sized collectivist anarchIst<br />

society is simply not possible. The only possible<br />

alternative would be to establish communes so small<br />

as to permit every individual to have both personal<br />

contact with every other individual <strong>and</strong> complete knowled<br />

g e 0 f eve r y f ace t 0 f the c omm un e • I nth i s wa y the<br />

community would be small enough to permit every individual<br />

to participate in every decision. The problem,<br />

however, is that such a society would have to be so<br />

small as to all but entirely eliminate the division of<br />

labor. But without a division of labor, no capital<br />

machinery could be utilized. While such a society<br />

might funct ion as a collectivist anarchist community,<br />

It would have to be almost solely agricultural using<br />

primitive instruments <strong>and</strong> sUbsisting in grinding<br />

poverty.(17)<br />

Ins h 0 r t, the i n d i v i d u a lis tan archis t be lieve s<br />

that a state is the sine qua non of a large scale<br />

collectivist society <strong>and</strong> that while a small anarchist<br />

commune might be possible, it would be most<br />

unattractive.<br />

2. LAISSEZ FAIRE, POWER AND FREEDOM<br />

a. Power Defined.<br />

Libertarians argue that a libertarian society<br />

w0 u I d beeh a rae t e r i zed by the a bsenceof powe r rei ations.<br />

But the libertarian definition of power <strong>and</strong><br />

freedom solely in terms of the presence or absence of<br />

violent activities, <strong>and</strong> the threat of such activities,<br />

has been criticized for disposing of the question of<br />

power relations by means of a semantic sleight-of-h<strong>and</strong>.<br />

Warren J. Samuels' critique of Rothbardian anarchism IS<br />

a good example of this line of thought.<br />

While anarchism would be a "system without a<br />

state," Samuels says, it would not be a system without<br />

power relationships, for "power, coercion <strong>and</strong> externalit<br />

ies are ubiquitous." They exist in all social<br />

sys terns. "The anarchist ideal, contemplated In terms<br />

of strict or absolute autonomy, is impossible."(lS)<br />

T h US, on e ca n l! sol veT! the prob I em 0 f powe r ina soc i e t y<br />

only by arbitrarily defining it in terms of certain<br />

types of coercion but not others. It is only through<br />

230


such "selective perception of mutual coercion," Samuels<br />

maintains, "that the anarchist ideal is sensible -- <strong>and</strong><br />

that selectivity begs the critical issues."(19)<br />

Rot h bar d's de fin i t ion 0 f power <strong>and</strong> f r e e d om in<br />

t e r ms 0 f p h Ysic a I v i ole nee com e sin for es p e cia 1 1Y<br />

c a u s tic c r i tic ism • " Con C e n t rat ion up 0 n ph Ysica I v i 0lence<br />

<strong>and</strong> obedience is an undue narrowing of the focus<br />

upon the full range of mutual coercion," he charges.<br />

Rothbard's "nonaggression axiom" is "misleading <strong>and</strong><br />

s e lee t i ve wit h reg a r d to' invas ion s ' • " He" can on I y<br />

pretend to abolish invasions by selectively admitting<br />

them, i.e., (he) abolished only certain invasions <strong>and</strong><br />

coercion." And what invasions would Rothbard's axiom<br />

abol ish? Since his conception of voluntarism <strong>and</strong> freedom<br />

are "specified only in terms of market exchange,"<br />

the y are "i n compIetean d s e I e c t i ve • " T hus"Ro t h bard's<br />

system" says Samuels, "would permit the operation of<br />

mu t u a I c 0 e r c ion i nthe rna r ke t, but he doe s not see i t<br />

as pejoratively <strong>and</strong> analytically coercion. In other<br />

words, he would abolish only the coercion he is willing<br />

to acknowledge."(20) Given his arbitrarily narrow view<br />

of power, Samuels continues, Rothbard cannot see -- or<br />

a tIe a s two n 't ad mit - - t hat the rna r ke t s y stem isits<br />

elf co ere i ve <strong>and</strong> t hat "i t g i v e s e f f e c t to wh ate ve r<br />

structure of private power operates through it." Thus,<br />

the "s tat e I e s s n e s s If 0 faRo t hba r d ian soc i e t y is a me r e<br />

"pretense"; it IS a "play with words" that "only functions<br />

to mislead." Consequently, not only would there<br />

be the functional equivalent of a state but it would be<br />

a state "skewed in favor of a propertied elite."<br />

Rothbard's "anarchism" "is not anarchism but a cleverly<br />

designed <strong>and</strong> worded surrogate for elitist or aristocratic<br />

con s e r vat ism. " I t wo u I d res u I tin a "p1 utoeraey"<br />

in the truest sense of the word, <strong>and</strong> "it cannot claim<br />

attent ion as a work of serious scholarship." In brief,<br />

"there is more to coercion, to voluntarism, <strong>and</strong> to<br />

freedom than Rothbard's system admits," <strong>and</strong> it is only<br />

by his "spur i ous" <strong>and</strong>, Samuel s strongly impl ies conscious<br />

"sleight-of-h<strong>and</strong> of narrowly contemplating ext<br />

ern a lit i e s<strong>and</strong>invas ion s" t hat he i s a blet 0 sol vethe<br />

spector of power in his society.(21)<br />

This is a stinging critiCIsm that, despite its<br />

truculent <strong>and</strong> polemical tone, does raise an important<br />

question: is the Rothbardian -- <strong>and</strong> more generally the<br />

lIbertarian -- resolution of the power problem simply a<br />

product of the (conscious?) abuse of the language; of a<br />

semantic sleight-of-h<strong>and</strong>?<br />

231


Wh i let her e is, a dm itt e d I y, ve r y lit tIe a g r e em e n t<br />

e i the r i nor din a r y I a n g u age 0 reve n am 0 ngpolit i cal<br />

scientists regarding the meaning of the term "power,"<br />

what little consensus there is follows, I believe, the<br />

path taken by such poltical scientists as Robert Dahl,<br />

Harold Lasswell <strong>and</strong> Morton Kaplan. Since there is<br />

lit tIe doubt that theirs is a respected approach to the<br />

question of power, it will, perhaps, be worthwhile to<br />

examine the libertarian definition in terms of the<br />

Dahl-Lasswell-Kaplan approach.(22)<br />

What is interesting about their analysis is the<br />

distinction they make between power <strong>and</strong> influence. For<br />

them, influence is a generic term that includes an entire<br />

family of more specific concepts such as power,<br />

authority, coercion, persuasion, force, etc. Power, on<br />

the other h<strong>and</strong>, says Dahl, is "defined as a special<br />

case of influence involving severe losses for noncomp<br />

I ian c e • " ( 23 ) S imil a r I y, La s s we I I <strong>and</strong> Ka p Iann0 t e t hat<br />

"it is the threat of sanctions that differentiates<br />

power from influence in general. Power is a special<br />

case of the exercise of influence: it is the process<br />

of affecting policies of others with the help of<br />

(actual or threatened) severe deprivations for nonconformity<br />

with the policies intended."(24)<br />

A problem with the Samuels' critique is immediatelyapparent.<br />

For Samuels, power is ubiquitous, but<br />

on I y bee a use h e (i mpi i cit I y) de fin esit ass y non ym 0 us<br />

with influence. But if the Dahl-Lawwell-Kaplan approach<br />

is followed power is clearly not ubiquitous. It<br />

is only one specific type -- that involving severe deprivations<br />

or losses -- of the much more inclusive concept<br />

of influence. Rothbard never denied that influence<br />

may be ubiquitous, but power certainly is not. If<br />

there is any abuse of language it lies with Samuels,<br />

not Rothbard.<br />

Even if one follows this approach, the question is<br />

far fro m be i n g res 0 I v e d . For is the r e, 0 r canthere<br />

be, market influence strong enough to constitute severe<br />

deprivation, i.e., can there be "economic power?"<br />

The rearet w 0 s tan dar d wa y s 0 f proc e e ding : t hat<br />

o f c I ass i fie a t ion <strong>and</strong> t hat 0 f compar i son . The met hod<br />

or per hap s morea c curate 1y, teeh n i que - - 0 f c I ass j ­<br />

fication establishes two or more mutually exclusive <strong>and</strong><br />

exhaustive categories or classes <strong>and</strong> then assigns the<br />

phenomena to one or the other of the classes. The<br />

comparative technique proceeds by establishing a con-<br />

232


lence if they did not comply. However, if (a) the<br />

employees agree to ban together <strong>and</strong> present a united<br />

fro n t tothe i r em ploye r, <strong>and</strong> i f (b) the em p loyerag r e e s<br />

that he will not hire anyone who does not belong to the<br />

union, a closed shop will have been voluntarily agreed<br />

upon. Coercion, i.e., the initiation of the use of<br />

violence, in this ease was entirely absent. True, if<br />

a n em p loy e e wa n t s to wo r k for t hat pa r tic u I a r em p loye r<br />

he must join the union. But this is not coercion, for<br />

as the I tal ian legal theorist Bruno Leoni has commented,<br />

"You do not 'constrain' someone if you merely refrain<br />

from doing on his behalf something you have not<br />

agr eed to do. ft (32) The only thing the members of the<br />

union did was to agree among themselves not to work for<br />

the employer unless he agreed to hire only union memb<br />

e r s<strong>and</strong> the em ploye r, i n ret urn, a g r eedt 0 the dema nd .<br />

It makes no more sense, the individualist anarchist bel<br />

ieves, to say that non-union members are being coerced<br />

in this situation than to say that one is coercing<br />

Gimbels by buying a tie from :'r1acys. But if the employer<br />

were told by the union that unless he agreed to<br />

their conditions his factory would be burned, or by the<br />

government that he would be fined or imprisoned, the<br />

closed shop agreement would be coercive in this ease,<br />

since it was obtained via the threat of violence. The<br />

sam e w0 u I d bet rue i f the em ploye r h ired s t r ike - brea k ­<br />

e r s toe r u s h the un ion 0 r i f Ma c y s h ired agen t s t 0 use<br />

violence against Gimbels' shoppers.<br />

The siutuation IS identical for acts of private<br />

dis c rim ina t ion. I n a lib e r tar ian wo rId a I I proper t y<br />

wo u I d b e p r i vat ely own ed<strong>and</strong>anyind i v i d u a 1 wo u 1d ha ve<br />

the right to use his property in any non-violent way he<br />

desired. "It might be charged that all this will allow<br />

freedom 'to discriminate' in housing or the use of<br />

streets," acknowledges Rothbard. And "there is no<br />

quest ion about that." "Fundamental to the libertarian<br />

creed is every man's right to choose who shall enter or<br />

use his own property, provided of course that the other<br />

person is willing."(33) Clearly, if private discrimina<br />

t i on is simply the right of an owner to determine who<br />

shall use his property it is, according to the libertarian<br />

definition of the term, "non-coercive." It is a<br />

method of exercising voluntary influence over another.<br />

What would be coerCIve, however, would be an order by<br />

an uninvited third party which included the threat of<br />

physical sanction for noncompliance of either discriminatory<br />

or nondiscriminatory behavior on the part of any<br />

individual. As with a closed or open shop, neither<br />

discriminatory nor nondiscriminatory behavior is in<br />

237


itself coerCive, but either may be depending on how<br />

they are undertaken.<br />

While voluntary private discrimination would be<br />

permitted, it should be noted that individualist anarchi<br />

s t s bel i eve t hat the rna r ke t wo u I d ten d tom i n i mi z e<br />

such behavior by placing the cost squarely on the<br />

shoulders of the property owner involved. Suppose,<br />

says Rothbard, that a l<strong>and</strong>lord of an apartment building<br />

is a great admirer of six-foot Swedish­<br />

Americans. <strong>and</strong> decides to rent his apartments<br />

only to fami 1 ies of such a group. In the<br />

f r e e soc i e t y i t wo u 1d be full yin his rig h t<br />

to do so. bu t he wo u 1del ear 1y s u f fer a I a r g e<br />

monetary loss 8S 8 result. For this means<br />

that he would have to turn away tenant after<br />

tenant in an endless quest for very tall<br />

Swedish-Americans. While this may be considered<br />

an extreme example, the effect is exactly<br />

the same, though differing in degree, for<br />

any sort of personal discrimination in the<br />

marketplace. If, for example, the l<strong>and</strong>lord<br />

dislikes redheads <strong>and</strong> determines not to rent<br />

his apartments to them, he will suffer<br />

losses, al though not as severely as in the<br />

first example.(34)<br />

This argument is not altogether convincing, for the<br />

market is ethically neutral <strong>and</strong> will, as a general<br />

r u Ie. ref I e c t the val ue s dom ina ntin the c omm un i t Y. I t<br />

i s c e r t a i n 1yeo nee i v a b 1 e t hat ina c omm un i t Y wh ere<br />

ant i - b 1a c k. ant i - s em i tic 0 ran t i - redh e a d fee lin g isextremely<br />

high. the "costs" of doing business with a member<br />

of such an anathematized group would also be very<br />

high. In" fact, a businessman who is not himself prejudiced<br />

may find tha t his employees refuse to work wi th<br />

blacks or Jews, or that his customers refuse to buy<br />

from him if he employs such "undes"irables." In such<br />

cases the market would actually intensify discrimination<br />

by imposing a heavy cost for not discriminating.<br />

Still, it is likely that the overall effect of<br />

the market is to reduce rather than intensify the incidence<br />

of discrimination. For, as Milton Friedman has<br />

poi n ted 0 u t, nth e pur c has e r 0 f b rea d do e s not know<br />

wh€ther it was made from wheat grown by a white man or<br />

a Neg r 0, b Y a C h r i s t ian 0 r 8 J ew . " I tis precisely<br />

this "impersonality of the market,l1 he notes, that<br />

It s epa rat e sec 0 nom i cae t i v i t i € S from po lit 1 ca I views 'I ,<br />

238


thereby protecting indIviduals from "being discriminated<br />

against in their economic activities for reasons<br />

that are irrelevant to their productivity -- whether<br />

these are associated with their views or color."(35)<br />

A related confusion is the role of leaders in an<br />

anarchist society. One view seems to be that anarchism<br />

impl i es the absence of leaders. This is only partially<br />

true. Individualist anarchists reject political<br />

leaders, not because they are leaders but because their<br />

f·unction is to exercise the use of coercion over<br />

others. They not only have no objection to leaders who<br />

have the voluntary assent of their followers, they recognize<br />

that such leaders are necessary. Their position<br />

is that<br />

Because of the uneven distribution of abiliti<br />

es, el i tes wi II tend to emerge from the<br />

ranks of the better qualified through a natural<br />

process of emerging hierarchy in all<br />

are a s 0 f hum a n act i v i t y. • • The f r e e rna r ke t<br />

society, then, is a society of evolving<br />

(ascending <strong>and</strong> descending) elites, or, as<br />

Vi I fredo Pareto put it, a 'ci rcula"tion of<br />

el i tes.' Since change is the fundamental<br />

c h a r act e r i s tic 0 f the f r e e rna r ke t soc i e t y ,<br />

the emergence of elites <strong>and</strong> their continuing<br />

circulation is both natural <strong>and</strong> desirable for<br />

it promotes optimization of both economic efficiency<br />

<strong>and</strong> social harmony.(36)<br />

I tis f eItthat the I e a d e r s<strong>and</strong> dec i s ion rna ke r sin<br />

a la i ssez fa i re society would be able to retain their<br />

pos i t ions only by continued service to their followers.<br />

The moment a leader ceased such service the rank-<strong>and</strong>file<br />

would take their support elsewhere <strong>and</strong> that partie<br />

u I a r I e a d e r wo u 1d los e his posit ion. Wh i leitis r ecog<br />

n i zed t hat a I a iss e z fa ire s y stem, as in fa c tany<br />

soc i a I s ystern, r e qui res dec i s ion rna ke r s, the a narchis t s<br />

bel i eve t hat i tis 0 n 1 y the rna r k e t, wit hit s constraint<br />

of serving the consumers, that prevents the<br />

leaders from using their leadership positions for purposes<br />

of exploitation.<br />

c. <strong>Freedom</strong> Defined.<br />

<strong>Freedom</strong>, as defined by the libertarians, is simply<br />

the absence of interpersonal violence, i.e., the use of<br />

initIated force or violence, or its threat, against the<br />

person or property of another. In this sense it is not<br />

239


only "negative" but, as Hayek points out, it "refers<br />

solely to a relation of men to·other men, <strong>and</strong> the inf<br />

r i n gementon itis coe r c ion by 0 the r me n • " ( 37 ) De fin ­<br />

ing freedom in this fashion means that in a libertarian<br />

society everyone would have an equal amount of freedom,<br />

i.e., the right to engage in any non-violent activity<br />

they desired. But it is important to realize that this<br />

does not mean that everyone would have an equal abil i ty<br />

to use that freedom. While the poor would have the<br />

same amount of freedom as the wealthy, the range of opt<br />

ions is undoubtedly more 1 iroi ted for the poor than the<br />

wealthy. Unlike the wealthy, the prospect of an ocean<br />

cruise on the Car ibbean or a vacation on the French<br />

R i v i era w0 u I d not be wi t h i n the ran g e of effect i ve<br />

choice for most poor. The cognition that the ability<br />

to use one's freedom is partly a function of one's economic<br />

position is probably what Harold Laski meant by<br />

his remark that "liberty in a laissez faire society is<br />

attainable only by those who have the wealth or<br />

opportunity to attainit."(38)<br />

Not only Harold Laski, but "progressives" such as<br />

J. R. Commons <strong>and</strong> John Dewey <strong>and</strong> "idealists" such as T.<br />

H. Green also define freedom as the "effective power<br />

t 0 do s p e c i f i c t h ings ," thereby viewing itin t e r mS 0 f<br />

the number of options open to a person. Libertarians,<br />

however, maintain a strict distinction between the absence<br />

of coercion <strong>and</strong> the power or ability to engage<br />

ins p e c i f i c t hi ngs, <strong>and</strong> res e r vethe t e r m "f r e e dom" for<br />

the former. While acknowledging that the range of opt<br />

ions open to an individual is an important question,<br />

it is, argues Hayek, not synonymous with freedom:<br />

the roc k eli mb e ron a d iff i cuI·t pit c h wh 0<br />

seeson Iyone wa y ou t to s a ve his I i f e i sunques<br />

t i onably free, though we would hardly say<br />

he has any choice. Also most people will<br />

st i II have enough feel ing for the original<br />

use of the word "free" to see that if the<br />

same cl imber were to fall into a crevasse <strong>and</strong><br />

were unable to get out of it, he could only<br />

fig u rat i vel Y be called "un f r e e ,n <strong>and</strong> t hat t 0<br />

speak of him as being "deprived of liberty"<br />

or of being "held captive" is to use these<br />

t e r msin a sensed ifferen t from t hat in wh i c h<br />

they apply in social relations.(39)<br />

Since in a libertarian society no one would have the<br />

right to initiate violence, such a society would, aee<br />

0 r din g t 0 Ro t hbar d , be "t 0 tally f r e e . " That is, si nc e<br />

240


feel ings of one individual with another. Is the degree<br />

of pa in tha t Jack Benny regards as ·severe of the same<br />

intensity as that which Helen Keller, or the Marquis de<br />

Sade, or Joe Smith regard as severe? And even if it<br />

is, how can we ever tell? In short, the application of<br />

the comparative technique to the concepts of power <strong>and</strong><br />

influence robs these terms of any empirical import.<br />

What of the classification teehnique? This<br />

approach, as we have seen, does not compare things<br />

according to "more/less" but establishes criteria to<br />

construct mutually exclusive <strong>and</strong> exhaustive categories<br />

<strong>and</strong> thenap p lie s the c r i t e ria t 0 ass i gnthe phe n omena<br />

either to one or the other of the categories. This is<br />

the approach adopted by Rothbard. While it tends to be<br />

I e s s dis c rim ina ting t han the compar a t i vete c hn i que, i t<br />

does possess the inestimable value in this case of giving<br />

the concept of power what the comparative technique<br />

could not: empirical import.<br />

Rothbard doesn't deny the ubiquity of influence.<br />

But rather than trying to determine the degree of<br />

Influence one person exercises over another, he looks<br />

to the meaDS one uses to obtain influence. Those<br />

attempts to influence others by violent means, defined<br />

in Lockean-fashion as physical force, or its threat,<br />

against the person or property of another, is termed<br />

power. All nonviolent, or what may be termed persuasive,<br />

methods of influencing others are designated as<br />

voluntary. What of "economic power"? Since the only<br />

"economic power" anyone can exercise is the ability to<br />

refuse to agree to an exchange, <strong>and</strong> since this is nonviolent<br />

according to Rothbard's definition, it is not<br />

con sidere d power a t a I I . Thus, the rna r ke t, ace0 r ding<br />

to this definition, is a system of social coordination<br />

in which power is completely absent.(28)<br />

Two caveats should be borne in mind. First,<br />

Rothbard looks at the means to influence rather than<br />

the degree of influence actually exercised. His taxonomy<br />

says nothing about the effectiveness of any particular<br />

influence-attempt in any particular situation.<br />

It is certainly consistent with his taxonomy for nonviolent<br />

methods of influence to be more effective in a<br />

particular case or with a particular individual than<br />

violent methods. To use Jack Benny again, it is conceivable<br />

that the use of "economic sanctions" such as<br />

the ref usa I to make an exchange prof itable to Jack<br />

would be a more effective method of influencing his<br />

behavior than to threaten him with bodily harm.<br />

234


Second, SInce one can define a concept in any way<br />

one desires, it is technically meaningless to speak of<br />

the "correctness" of a definition. But to be underst<strong>and</strong>able<br />

a definition must bear some congruence with<br />

the way the term is commonly used. It would be ridiculous<br />

to define power in terms of, say, the length of<br />

one's shoe laces. But within this limit the ambiguity<br />

surrounding the term provides one with fairly wide discretion<br />

to st.ipulate a particular definition. Rothbard's<br />

definition of power in terms of physical violen<br />

c e c e r t a i n I y f a I I s wit h i ntheli mit S 0 f commo n<br />

usa g e • For, a s Da h I not e s aftera c knowledging the<br />

ambiguity of the term, "probably among all people"<br />

physical violence such as "exile, imprisonment <strong>and</strong><br />

death would be considered as severe punishment."(29)<br />

Da hId 0 e s not lim i t power tot heseac t s as Ro t hbar d<br />

does. But his statement, if correct, does indicate<br />

that the acts that Rothbard denotes as violent are the<br />

ones that everyone can agree as being powerful. One<br />

can disagree with this definition of power <strong>and</strong>, given<br />

the s tip u I a t i ve asp e c t 0 f de fin i t ion s, i t wo u I d be<br />

poi n tIesst 0 a r g u e t hat Ro t h ba r d's de fin i t ion is the<br />

"only correct" one. But it certainly must be admitted<br />

to be a correct <strong>and</strong> plausible use of the term.(30) It<br />

is therefore highly unfair to argue, as does Samuels,<br />

that Rothbard's definition of power is an abuse of<br />

language <strong>and</strong> a (consciously) misleading semantic<br />

sleight-of-h<strong>and</strong>. On the contrary, H. E. Frech, who is<br />

otherwise critical of Rothbard, applauds him for "excellently<br />

sharpening the language," precisely in the<br />

ambiguous area of power relationships.(31)<br />

We are now ina pos i t ion to fIe s h ou t the r ema ining<br />

elements of what may be termed the Rothbardian influence<br />

taxonomy. While power has been defined as the<br />

use of violence, we have not distinguished between its<br />

legitimate <strong>and</strong> illegitimate uses. Yet Rothbard does<br />

draw such a distinction. For him, as for Tucker <strong>and</strong><br />

the philosophical anarchists, the initiated use of<br />

power is illegitimate, while its defensive use is<br />

legitimate. This fits perfectly with the Dahl-<br />

.L 8 ssw e I I - K a p I 8 nap pro a c h, wh i c h a Iso rna kesthis distinction<br />

between the legitimate <strong>and</strong> IllegItimate uses<br />

of power. Power that "is said to be legitimate," -however<br />

that term may be defined -- notes Dahl, is<br />

"generally called authority," while that which is saId<br />

to be illegitimate is referred to as "coercion."<br />

The Rothbardlan influence taxonomy can now be<br />

summarIzed as follows:<br />

235


freedom is automatically restricted by any coercive<br />

act, t heg0 v ernmen t a I t ran s fer 0 f s eve r a I rn i I I ion dollars<br />

from a mi II ionaire to a group of indigents would<br />

res t ric t f r e e d om eventh 0 ugh i t mig htinereasethe 0 ptions<br />

open to the indigents without perceptibly limiti<br />

n g the 0 p t ion s 0 f the mill ionair e • Itis en t ire I y<br />

p 0 s sib Ie, the ref 0 r e, t hat f r e e d om co u 1d be res t ricted<br />

at the same time that the number of alternatives open<br />

to particUlar individuals or groups might increase.<br />

This raises the question of how important such<br />

freedom actually is. The welfare state could not exist<br />

in the absence of the state. What would happen to the<br />

poor in such a society? It is to this issue we now<br />

turn.<br />

3. THE PLIGHT OF THE POOR<br />

a. Government <strong>and</strong> the Poor.<br />

Libertarians of all persuasions are confident that<br />

the substantial reduction or even the total elimination<br />

of government, including the dismantling of the government<br />

poverty programs, would actually benefit the poor.<br />

Recall that in Chapter III it was noted that government<br />

transfers wealth according to influence, not need.<br />

Since the poor tend to lack the three things necessary<br />

to influence government -- time, money <strong>and</strong> expertise -government<br />

policies actually transfer wealth away from<br />

the lower <strong>and</strong> to the middle <strong>and</strong> upper income groups.<br />

This is done in any number of ways of which subsidies,<br />

lieens i n g res t ric t ions<strong>and</strong> tar iff s are 0 n 1y the rno s t<br />

obvious. It has been estimated, for example, that government<br />

regulatory boards actually cost consumers about<br />

$ 1 3 0 b i I I ion e a c h yea r • ( 40 ) The po 0 rcan I e a s t a f for d<br />

high pr ices. They are therefore the ones most hurt by<br />

these agencies.<br />

If the foregoing is correct, if the poor are the<br />

victims of governmental redistribution of wealth, it<br />

follows that they would benefit from its termination .<br />

.Hence, if government were abolished or substantially<br />

reduced, with taxes correspondingly eliminated or drastically<br />

cut, libertarians believe that the position of<br />

the poor would improve.<br />

Not only do libertarians argue that government policies<br />

harm the poor, they also maintain that the free<br />

market works to their benefit. In order to underst<strong>and</strong><br />

this argument a few preliminary observations are necessa<br />

r y.<br />

241


a I' ," Cha r I es Murray has noted, "are di fferent at di fferent<br />

economi c levels."(42) But the dilemma created<br />

by the recogni t ion of this fact, i.e., are people poor<br />

because they live in the present or do they live in the<br />

present because they are poor, is only apparent. There<br />

is no doubt some truth to both, although it is seldom,<br />

if ever, the case that they have no choice. Nevertheless,<br />

why people adopt the lifestyle they do is<br />

one que s t ion; the con seq u e nees t hat res u 1 t r r om t hat<br />

choice is quite another. And there can be little doubt<br />

that "living in the present" impedes, if not precludes,<br />

economic advance.<br />

Wh i 1erea d i I Y a c k now led ging t hat therear e rna n y<br />

rea s· 0 nsf 0 r po v e r t y, i tis, says Ba n fie I d, f 0 un d disproportionately<br />

among those exhibiting the values of<br />

the T1 lower c I ass men t a lit Y• " This po i ntis sign i f i ­<br />

cant, believes the libertarian, because it has an important<br />

bearing both on determining the number of those<br />

who are actually poor <strong>and</strong> on the ability of government,<br />

eve n ass urn i n g the bes t 0 fIn t en t ions, to dea I wit h the<br />

problem. It is to these two issues that we now turn.<br />

c. Poverty Statistics.<br />

Approximately 12 percent of the popUlation of the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s have, according to offical statistics,<br />

incomes below the poverty line. The libertarian believes<br />

that these statistiCS exaggerate the amount of<br />

actual poverty. First, wealth is partially a function<br />

of age. The wealthy, says Thomas Sowell, "are likely<br />

to be elderly individuals who have finally paid off<br />

the i r m0 r t gag e s, <strong>and</strong> wh 0 rna y we I I ha ve been amo n g the<br />

statistical 'poor' when they were younger." Similarly,<br />

the median age of blacks is nearly a decade less than<br />

the median age of whites. When such factors as age <strong>and</strong><br />

education are controlled, the income differences bet<br />

we e n b 1a c ksan d whit e s dis a ppear. This mean s , says<br />

Sowell, that "the poor" do not really constitute a socioeconomic<br />

class "in the usual sense of people stratified<br />

in a certain way across their lifetimes." Rather,<br />

those who are statistically poor are often simply those<br />

in a temporary, <strong>and</strong> quite normal, part of their economic<br />

life cycle.(43)<br />

A second reason statistics inflate the incidence<br />

of actual poverty is that living in the present the<br />

lower class individual has an affinity for risk, action<br />

<strong>and</strong> 1 mp u I s e be h a v i 0 r. G i ven t his a f fin i t y, rna ny wh 0<br />

are class if J ed as poor have high risk <strong>and</strong>/or seasonal<br />

243


jobs. Therefore, "their incomes rise <strong>and</strong> fall with<br />

changing employment conditions."(44) The result is<br />

that the tur.nover rate among those with incomes below<br />

the p 0 v e r t y lin e i s abo u ton e - t h i r d per yea r • °T his<br />

means that if poverty were based on a two or three,<br />

instead of a one, year period the actual number of poor<br />

would be significantly less.<br />

Fin a I I y, sincetaxes are pa i don 0 incom e s, therei s<br />

a built-in tendency for income to be underreported.<br />

This means that basing poverty statistics on reported<br />

incomes inflates the statistics. In testimony before<br />

the House Hear ings on the Economic Opportunity Act of<br />

1964, Margaret Reid disclosed that those reporting incomes<br />

under $1,000 per year were actually spending an<br />

average of approximately $2,500 per year.(45) Reinforcing<br />

this is the fact. that such high-risk, actionoriented<br />

occupations as gambling, loan sharking, prost<br />

i tut ion <strong>and</strong> the like attract a disproportionate share<br />

of "lower class" individuals. Since these activities<br />

are illegal, this income cannot be reported. Although<br />

the amount of Income from unreported transactions is<br />

difficult to gauge, a 1978 estimate placed it at about<br />

$700 billion.(46) Regardless of what one thinks of<br />

such activities, it is clear, says the libertarian,<br />

that if this income could be taken into consideration<br />

"a considerable percentage of the 'poor'<br />

cities would turn out to be well-off."(47)<br />

in large<br />

Wh i Ie acknowl edg i ng that there are those who are<br />

legi t imately poor, the I ibertarian believes that the<br />

official figure of about 12 percent is inflated.<br />

d. Poverty Programs.<br />

The concept of the "culture of poverty" also indicates<br />

just how limited is the ability of the government<br />

to help the poor, even assuming the best of circumstances.<br />

Cons ider the government policy regarding educat<br />

ion. One of the reasons for compulsory, "free" grade<br />

<strong>and</strong> high school education, <strong>and</strong> zero or minimal tuition,<br />

taxpayer supported, state universities, was to make education<br />

accessible to children of poor famIlies. This,<br />

it was reasoned. would break the "cycle of poverty" by<br />

providing such children with the skills needed to enter<br />

high paying occupations. What happened, libertarians<br />

argue, was instructive. The payoffs from education lay<br />

several years in the future. Consequently, while mid-<br />

244


dIe <strong>and</strong> upper class individuals began attending staterllnuniversities<br />

in droves, the poor were not particu­<br />

I a r I y a t t rae ted, eve n when i t wa s "f r e e • " Ins tea d ,<br />

the yen t ere d the w0 r k - for c e, us u a I I Y get ting lowskilled,<br />

low paying jobs <strong>and</strong> began paying taxes, some<br />

of which went to provide low-cost, subsidized, education<br />

for middle <strong>and</strong> upper class chi ldren at state<br />

universities.(48)<br />

A not her g 0 v ernmen t pro g ram wa s "j 0 bs t r a i n i ng , "<br />

wh i ch began wi t h much fanfare in the "War on Poverty"<br />

programs of the 1960's. This too proved a failure <strong>and</strong><br />

for the samerea son : 1 ike e d ucat ion, the pa yo f f s from<br />

t ra in i ng programs lay months, maybe years, in the future.<br />

In fact, the entire program was based on a contradiction.<br />

A program designed to train the poor for<br />

good jobs could not succeed for the same reason that<br />

the poor do not have good jobs in the first place:<br />

both good jobs <strong>and</strong> successful training are futureoriented;<br />

the poor live in the present.(49)<br />

The minimum wage is yet another example. Many<br />

lIbertarians feel that this is the most pernicious of<br />

a 1 I " an t i - p 0 v e r t y" leg i s I a t ion • Wages are de t e r mi ned<br />

by the marginal productivity of labor. And since the<br />

poor as a rule do not have the skills that would enable<br />

them to become hIghly productive members of the labor<br />

force the only jobs open to them are low-paying ones.<br />

This is most unfortunate but good intentions are not<br />

e n 0 ugh • Sin cern i n i mum wage leg i s I a t ion doe s not, <strong>and</strong><br />

can not, increaset he rna r gina I prod uc t 1 V i t Y 0 f the poor<br />

its only effect is to eliminate their jobs. If an ind<br />

i v i d u a 1 w0 r k e r 's rna r gina 1 val ue . toth e fir m i s $ 3 • 00<br />

per h 0 ur, ani ncr e as e i nthe min i mum wa g e from $ 2 .90 to<br />

$3.10 per hour means that the worker will lose his job.<br />

T h us, the 0 n e s m0 s t h u r t by min i murn wa gel aws are the<br />

least productive members of society, i.e., the<br />

poor.(SO) If the foregoing is correct, then the ability<br />

of government to eliminate poverty is most limited,<br />

indeed.<br />

Once the cui tural basis of poverty is recognized,<br />

the government appears to have but two options: [1] to<br />

insure everyone a minimum income <strong>and</strong>/or [2] to somehow<br />

change the t ime- frame of the poor from a present to a<br />

future orientation. The problem with the former is<br />

that if the minimum is set high enough to eliminate<br />

poverty it would also be hIgh enough to have a disincent<br />

ive effect on those whose incomes are only slightly<br />

above the mInimum. If some of this group quit not only<br />

245


Put differently, government poverty programs enc<br />

0 u rag e, p e. r hap sun.w itt i n g 1 y, the adop t ion 0 f wh a t<br />

Banfield termed the "lower class mental ity." The<br />

result is that these programs actually increased the<br />

number of poor.<br />

e. The Market <strong>and</strong> the Poor.<br />

Granted that government programs have failed, the<br />

quest ion is, given the "culture of poverty," would pure<br />

laissez faire prove any more effective? Libertarians<br />

believe that it would.<br />

As noted earlier in Section 1 of this chapter, the<br />

libertarian maintains that the unhampered market tends<br />

to employ every factor of production at its most value<br />

productive point. Since it is the poor who can least<br />

afford the squ<strong>and</strong>ering of scarce resources, it is they,<br />

says the libertarian, who most benefit by the market<br />

process. What of the objection that although this is<br />

very well for the "able-bodied poor," most who are poor<br />

today have I ittle education <strong>and</strong>/or physical h<strong>and</strong>icaps?<br />

Such unskilled workers do not benefit from the market<br />

process since their productivity tends to be so low<br />

that they cannot even find jobs. Libertarians respond<br />

that such individuals cannot find jobs not because of<br />

their low productivity but because minimum wage laws<br />

establish wages in excess of their productivity.<br />

For example, in the 1950's <strong>and</strong> early 1960's most<br />

e I e vat 0 r s we reoperated rna n ua I I Y <strong>and</strong> rna n y res tauran t s<br />

had their dishes washed by h<strong>and</strong>. These jobs were<br />

usually filled by the unskilled: the young, uneducated<br />

<strong>and</strong> the h<strong>and</strong>icapped. They did not pay much, but that is<br />

jus t the poi n t. As the min i mum wag e wa s r a isedt 0<br />

$.75, then to $1.00 <strong>and</strong> then to $1.25 per hour, the<br />

bui lding owners discovered that it now was economical<br />

to automate their elevators, thereby eliminating these<br />

jobs. The same was true with dishwashers. As the minimum<br />

wage was ra i sed, they were replaced by automated<br />

dishwashing machinery.(52)<br />

The root of the problem, therefore, is not the low<br />

productivitiy of the unskilled worker. It is the fact<br />

that, being prevented by the minimum wage from offering<br />

a compensating difference for his low productivity, his<br />

labor, under this condition, is overpriced <strong>and</strong> he is<br />

therefore unemployed.<br />

But, i teo u ] d b e 0 b j e C ted, wit h 0 u t the min i mum<br />

247


wage the unskilled might find jobs. They would pay so<br />

little however that such workers would still have to<br />

rely on government for assistance. The libertarian<br />

response is two-fold. First, most of the lowest paying<br />

jobs are not had by the breadwinner but by other family<br />

members desiring to supplement the family income. And,<br />

second, wage rates do not depend on the individual<br />

w0 r k e r 's phYsica I prod uc t i v i t Y but on the rna r gina I produet<br />

i vi ty of labor. Barbers <strong>and</strong> butlers perform their<br />

services today in much the same way they did two hund<br />

red yea r s a go. Yet, says economi s t <strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>von</strong> Mi ses,<br />

the wagera t e sea r ned by s uc h "wo r ke r s are today muc h<br />

higher than they were in the past. They are higher bee<br />

a use the y are de t e r mine d by the rna r gina I prod uc t i v i t Y<br />

of labor. The employer of a butler withholds this man<br />

from employment in a factory <strong>and</strong> must therefore pay the<br />

equivalent of the increase in outputwhich the additiona<br />

I emp I oymen t of one man in a factory would br ing<br />

about."(53)<br />

This means that while the unskilled worker would<br />

s e I d om be c om ewe a I thy his wa ge rat e wo u I d ten d to be<br />

h i g her t han c omm 0 n 1 y tho ugh t, pro v ide d the r e we r e<br />

alternative means of employment open to him. What is<br />

needed are more jobs available for the unskilled. But<br />

the effect of such regulations as the minimum wage <strong>and</strong><br />

licensing restrictions is to eliminiate just those<br />

job s • Rep e a I 0 f s uchi e g i s I a t ion wo u I d beex pe c ted t 0<br />

pro v ide a d e qua t e, but not I u c rat i v e, wa ge s for the<br />

unskilled.<br />

In br i ef, the movement from government to the market<br />

would reduce poverty in two ways. First, the disman<br />

t 1 i n g 0 f the weI farestate wo uIde1 iminate the i ncentiveto<br />

fail which is inherent in government poverty<br />

programs. Second I y, the low-paying jobs generated by<br />

the repe a 1 0 f the min i mum wa g e wo u 1d s e r vet 0 enco urage<br />

such valuable job skills as hard work, cooperation with<br />

others, punctuality, etc., which are valuable steppingstones<br />

to better, higher-paying jobs.<br />

The mar k e t pro c e s s, libe r tar ian s say, wo u I d a 1s 0<br />

help the poor in their capacity as consumers. Consider,<br />

for example, the "ghetto merchant." Since prices<br />

in the ghetto average about 10 percent more than prIces<br />

for goods in other neighborhoods, the ghetto merchant<br />

is often excoriated for exploiting the poor. But the<br />

key question is why is the ghetto merchant able to<br />

charge, <strong>and</strong> receive, such prices; why don't such prIces<br />

attract additional competitors? The answer is that<br />

248


f. Care for the Truly Poor.<br />

There is one final question to be dealt with.<br />

What would happen to those few who were in fact incapacitated<br />

<strong>and</strong> could not take care of themselves? Regardless<br />

of the socioeconomic system, such people can be<br />

provided for only out of "surplus production." The<br />

complete el iminat ion of government intervention would<br />

h a vetwoe f f e c t s: [1] i t wo u 1del i minate the pove r t y<br />

unnecessarily created by such government policies as<br />

minimum wages <strong>and</strong> I icensing restrictions; <strong>and</strong> [2] it<br />

would increase output <strong>and</strong> thus "surplus production."<br />

There is, of course, no guarantee that this "surplus"<br />

w0 u 1 d got 0 the tr u I y need y • Yet, i n 19 78 Arne rican s<br />

donated nearly $40 billion to charity.(55) If one assumest<br />

hat u n dera pur e I a iss e z fa ire e con omy the r e<br />

wo u Ids till be abo u t 8 or 10mi II i on poor, th i s wou 1d<br />

prorate out to $5,000 for every poor individual in the<br />

country or $20,000 for every poor family of four. And,<br />

given an even more productive economy coupled with the<br />

s i g n i f i can t I Y lowe r t a xes res u I ting from the disrna n t I ­<br />

ing of the weI fare state, it is conceivable that this<br />

sum would be even greater under pure laissez faire.<br />

In short, the libertarian believes that there is<br />

every reason to believe that the poor would fare better<br />

under the market than under the government.<br />

4. MONOPOL I ES AND THE FREE MARKET<br />

Libertarians believe that the substitution of a<br />

completely laissez faire economic system for the political<br />

system of government intervent ion would el iminate<br />

the pr ob I em of power. But in the absence of a governmentally<br />

imposed anti-trust policy, would not voluntary<br />

cartelization or "cut-throat" competition result in the<br />

emergence of a few giant corporations able to use their<br />

monopol ist ic positions to exploit consumers?(56) Libertarians<br />

answer in the negative.<br />

Assuming a free market, the first question is how<br />

one attained a monopoly position in the first place?<br />

Since profit can only be earned by supplying consumers<br />

wit h wha t they wan t bet ter than anyone el se, the "monopolist"<br />

IS seen as actually increasing their satisfact<br />

i on beyond the abi Ii ty of any other producer. Otherwise,<br />

he would never have obtained his position. This<br />

situation is unchanged even after he has become a<br />

"monopolIst," for an attempt to restrict production <strong>and</strong><br />

raise prices would only serve to attract competitors<br />

250


endeavoring to gain access to the lucrative profits,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the exp<strong>and</strong>ed supply would force the price back<br />

down. But if a monopolist is confronted by new competitors,<br />

why can't he either reduce his prices again in<br />

order to drive the newcomers out of business, or buy up<br />

his rivals' plants? As for the former, even if a<br />

smaller firm is driven into bankruptcy, its physical<br />

plant remains intact <strong>and</strong> may therefore be bought by new<br />

compet i tors at extremely low prices. This means that<br />

these new compet i tors would then be in a position to<br />

s eve reI y damage the w0 u 1 d - be mo nopol i s t<strong>and</strong> ke e p the<br />

price low for a considerable time. Moreover, a policy<br />

o f bUy i n g 0 uta I I compet itorsis seen as i nor dinate 1y<br />

expens ive. A small efficient firm could dem<strong>and</strong> a high<br />

price for its plant as the price for selling its<br />

ass e t s. But if the monopol is t would then try to recoup<br />

his losses after such a purchase by raising prices, he<br />

would only encourage the entrace of new competitors,<br />

thus necess i tat ing the "buying out" process allover<br />

again.<br />

The foregoing means that, provided they are voluntary,<br />

successful mergers, price-fixing agreements or<br />

cartelizations do not harm the consumer. On the contrary,<br />

like all voluntary transactions, they help to<br />

find the most value-productive point for the allocation<br />

of resources. Therefore, they help to increase the satisfaction<br />

of all members of society. Assume, for example,<br />

that firms A, B<strong>and</strong> C find that by merging they<br />

can increase their profits byrest ricting prod uc t ion .<br />

The "restriction" means that some factors of production<br />

w i I I now b e c om e i dIe • But solongas therea r e no i n ­<br />

stitutional, i.e., governmental, impediments to their<br />

use, resources cannot long remain idle. Their employment<br />

in other areas wi 11 exp<strong>and</strong> production in those<br />

areas. If so, production has not been restricted at<br />

all. What occurred was a shifting of factors from one<br />

area to another. But the merger would take place only<br />

if the participants believed that it would increase<br />

their profits. Since the market correlates profits <strong>and</strong><br />

consumer satisfaction, the merger will, provided the<br />

.expectat ions of the participants are correct, actually<br />

increase consumer satisfaction. That is, while physical<br />

output will have remained about the same, the value<br />

of that output, from the st<strong>and</strong>point of the consumers,<br />

has been augmented.<br />

Libertarians further argue that the larger the<br />

firm in relation to the market, the more limited it is<br />

i nit s a b iIi t y toe a 1cuI ate <strong>and</strong> the ref 0 ret he mo r e<br />

251


susceptIble it is to losses that would preclude further<br />

expansion. Since monopolies <strong>and</strong> cartels eliminate the<br />

market in the area of their operations, they would have<br />

no economic signals to guide them in allocating their<br />

resources or making investment decisions. Since this<br />

means that their decisions would be economically arbitrary<br />

they would suffer severe losses <strong>and</strong>, in the absence<br />

of governmental protection, collapse. There is,<br />

in other words, no economic difference between a monopoly<br />

<strong>and</strong> a socialist economy <strong>and</strong> both would collapse<br />

for the samereas 0 n : the a bsenceofee 0 nom i c ca 1cui a ­<br />

tion.(57)<br />

Consequently, the libertarian believes that the<br />

size of the firm is limited by the limits of calcula<br />

b iii t y <strong>and</strong> den i esthat the rna r ke t ena b Iesany fir m,<br />

regardless of size, to exploit the consumer or victimize<br />

society. The popular fear of the "tyranny of<br />

we a I t h" u n d e r the f r e e rna r ketis theref 0 rese en asan<br />

illusion.(58)<br />

5. GOVERNMENT AND UTILITY<br />

There is one significant ramification of the libertarian<br />

monopoly theory. Government itself is a<br />

m0 n 0 pol Y• Hen ce, .therei s no wa y for i t rat iona I 1Y to<br />

a I I 0 cat e "i t s" res 0 ur c e s • I t rna y, for examp Ie, c I aim<br />

tha t taxes must be raised because there is a "shortage"<br />

o froads, pol ice, tea c her s, etc. Howe ver, a r g uesthe<br />

anarchist, it actually has no idea whether there really<br />

is a s hor tage of these th i ngs, too many of them or jus t<br />

enough, since ther e is no market test for these goods<br />

<strong>and</strong> services <strong>and</strong> therefore no way for the consumers to<br />

evaluate their utility. Dem<strong>and</strong>s may be made on the polit<br />

i c a I s y stem, but t his inn0 wa y sol ve s the prob I em •<br />

Pol i tic s res p 0 n d s t 0 i n flue nee <strong>and</strong>, a s rna ny ha ve a r ­<br />

gued, the influence any group is able to exert is near­<br />

I y the rever s e 0fit s s i z e . As Ma ncur 0 Ison has po i n t ­<br />

ed out, an individual in a large group "cannot make a<br />

noticeable contribution to the group, <strong>and</strong> since no one<br />

i nth e gr 0 up wi I 1 rea c t i f he rna ke s no con t ributi 0 n, he<br />

has no incentive to contribute."(S9) A smaller group,<br />

of course, is easier to organize. And, further, not<br />

only are individuals in a smaller group able to see the<br />

impact 0 f the i r con t r i bu t ion, butit is a Iso ea s i e r to<br />

exert social pressure on the members to insure that<br />

each individual continues to do his part. Hence, the<br />

smaller, better organized groups are usually able to<br />

exert greater pressure on the political system. The<br />

result is that, even If the political leaders honestly<br />

252


desire to represent the views of the community, the<br />

signals conveyed to the politcal leaders will almost<br />

invariable depart from the actual state of dem<strong>and</strong> by<br />

the commun i ty. Thus, despite the dem<strong>and</strong>s made on the<br />

political system, government is ipso faeto an isl<strong>and</strong><br />

of calculational chaos, <strong>and</strong> it is therefore impossible<br />

for it to operate efficiently.(60) This, in turn, means<br />

that even if people desire such things as education,<br />

roads, <strong>and</strong> police protection, it would"be more advantageous<br />

for them to purchase these on the market.<br />

The very fact that the government uses its monopolyon<br />

the use of force to outlaw competition with itself<br />

demonstrates this point, they argue. For if it<br />

actually provided its customers, i.e., the taxpayers,<br />

wit h the best pos siblede fen s e s e r vicesther e wo u I d be<br />

no need for it to ban competitors.(61)<br />

6. THE BUSINESS CYCLE AND DEPRESSION<br />

Another problem that must be dealt with is the<br />

business cycle <strong>and</strong>, its corollary, depression. Aren't<br />

government contra-cyclical policies needed to moderate<br />

the tendency of the market to gyrate wildly between<br />

boom <strong>and</strong> bust,· between inflation <strong>and</strong> depression?<br />

There are many different explanations of the business<br />

cycle. Most of these -- such as the Keynesian<br />

over- investment argument, Schumpeter's "cluster" of entrepreneurial<br />

error thesis, <strong>and</strong> the "acceleration principle,"<br />

associated with the names of the American econom<br />

i s t, J. M. C I ark <strong>and</strong> the Eng 1 ish e conom i s t, R. F 0<br />

Harrod(62) -- see the cause of the cycle in some aspect<br />

of the market process <strong>and</strong> generally see the solution in<br />

some form of government activity. One explanation that<br />

reverses the causal flow <strong>and</strong> sees the cause of the<br />

bus iness cycle in government manipulation of the economy<br />

<strong>and</strong> "Its solution in a completely unhampered, or<br />

laissez faire, economy is the "Austrian," or monetary,<br />

theory of the trade cycle. While this explanation can<br />

cIa i m 0 n I yam i nor i t Y f 0 I I ow i n g am 0 n g e con om i s t s , ( 63 )<br />

it is hardly surprising that the overwhelming majority<br />

of individualist anarchists subscribe to the "Austrian"<br />

explanation. At some risk of over-simplification, the<br />

Austrian theory is presented below.<br />

The problem that must be explained by any theory<br />

of the business cycle is why do entrepreneurs, who only<br />

obtain their positions by being better forecasters than<br />

others, suddenly, collectively <strong>and</strong> so grieviously mis-<br />

253


per c e i vet h e act u 8 1 e conom i cstate 0 f a f fa irs? Sin c e<br />

the Austrians contend that the unhampered market is alwayshea<br />

dj ng for equi 1 i b I' i urn, the I' e i s not h i nginher en t<br />

in the market process to account for this sudden cluster<br />

of errors, <strong>and</strong> thus for the cycle. Individual entrepreneurs<br />

may well make isolated errors, but the<br />

sudden emergence of mass entrepreneurial error must<br />

have some general cause. Since the only thing that ties<br />

the va rio u s rnark e t s tog e the I' i s rno ne y, the Au s t ria n s<br />

argue that the trade cycle can only be explained by a<br />

monetary theory.(64)<br />

The rate of interest is the crucial factor in the<br />

Austr ian theory. The interest rate serves to allocate<br />

resources between the consumer <strong>and</strong> capital goods industr<br />

ies so that the entire structure of production is in<br />

congruence wi th the. "social rate of time preference,"<br />

i. e., the general dem<strong>and</strong> for consumpt ion goods immediately<br />

-- consumer goods dem<strong>and</strong> -- relative to the dem<strong>and</strong><br />

for consumption goods in the future -- capital<br />

goods dem<strong>and</strong>. Interest, in other words, is the payment<br />

for the use of one's savings for a particular length of<br />

time; <strong>and</strong> the rate of interest is simply that price<br />

that will insure that at any particular time all that<br />

iss a v e d will be i n ve s ted, i. e ., t hat the dema nd for<br />

sa vi ngs wi 11 equal the supply of savings. The point at<br />

which equilibrium is reached is referred to as the<br />

"natural rate of interest."<br />

The problem is that an increase in the supply of<br />

money, <strong>and</strong> it should be noted not of actual savings,<br />

wi 11 upset this equil ibrium. If banks suddenly obtained<br />

additional money they would be unable to loan it out<br />

at the prevailing rate of interest <strong>and</strong> would conseque<br />

n t 1Y be for cedt 0 lower the i r rat e • In t his wa y<br />

the ma I' k e t I' ate 0 fin tel'est dev i ates from the nat ur a 1<br />

rate. At this lower market rate of interest some ventures<br />

that were once too costly now appear profitable.<br />

Since interest is the payment for time <strong>and</strong> since<br />

there is more production time involved in the capital<br />

goods industries than in the consumer goods industries,<br />

the change in the rate of interest has its biggest impact<br />

on the former. In other words, since the costs of<br />

production in the capital goods industries declines<br />

wit h the dec 1 i n e i ntherateofin t ere s t, pI' 0 fit rna rgins<br />

are correspondingly increased. Spurred by these<br />

profIts, entrepreneurs will exp<strong>and</strong> production of capital<br />

goods. Factor pI' ices then begin to rise as producers<br />

of these goods begin to bid factors away from<br />

producers of consumer goods.<br />

254


ere d t t e x pan s ton ereate s rna linvestrn e n t s t hat wi lIsur ­<br />

face as soon as the policy ceases. If the government<br />

des i res to avoid the depressionary effects inherent in<br />

the re-adjustment process, it will have to try to<br />

shore-up the malinvestments by continuing the influx of<br />

new money. But, as Hayek points out, "inflation acts<br />

as a stimulus to business only insofar as it is unforeseen."(66)<br />

If the prices are rising at, say, five percen<br />

t per year, people will soon come to expect future<br />

price rises of five percent <strong>and</strong> ma"ke adjustments in<br />

ant i c i pat ion 0 f tho s e inc rea s e s • Conseq ue n t 1y, for<br />

the policy of credit expansion to be successful it must<br />

be more than expected. Iff i ve percent is expected<br />

the government must exp<strong>and</strong> the money supply by, say,<br />

seven percent. But then seven percent will come to be<br />

expected, forcing the government to exp<strong>and</strong> the money<br />

supply by, say ten percent .. Clearly, if the policy of<br />

credit expansion is not terminated it will lead to what<br />

the Austrians refer to as the "crack-up boom," i.e.,<br />

the point where the "prices at which people would be<br />

prepared to part with 'real goods' discount to such an<br />

extent the expected progress in the fall of purchasing<br />

power that nobody has sufficIent cash at h<strong>and</strong> to pay<br />

for them." But once this point is reached "The monetary<br />

system breaks down; all transactions in the money<br />

co nee r ned c e a s e; a pan i c ma k esits purchas i ng power<br />

van i sh al together. People return ei ther to barter or<br />

to the use of another kind of money."(67) This point<br />

was reached at several tImes in the past including 1781<br />

colonial America, 1796 France, 1920 Russia, <strong>and</strong> 1923<br />

Germany.<br />

The Austrians believe that their theory was borne<br />

out by the depression of the 1930's. Between July 1921<br />

<strong>and</strong> July 1929, they note, the supply of money in the<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s increased from $45.3 billion to $73.3<br />

b ill ion, 0 ran inc rea s e if 61.8 per cen t . Meanwh i Ie,<br />

product i on of such durable goods as iron <strong>and</strong> steel increased<br />

by 160 percent <strong>and</strong> production of non-durable<br />

goo d s r 0 s e b y 6 0 per c e n t. Conseq ue n t I y, the genera 1<br />

pr ice level rose only slightly. What is of importance<br />

for the Austrians, however, is not the aggregate<br />

pr ice level but the changes in the prices between the<br />

consumer <strong>and</strong> capital goods industries. Credit expans<br />

ion, say the Austr ians, forced the interest rate below<br />

what it would have been on the unhampered market. ThIS<br />

caused the bulk of the new money to enter the capital<br />

goods market, forcing prIces in those industries to<br />

rise. Since the existing consumption/savings proportions<br />

were pulled out of balance wIth the social rate<br />

256


of tIme preference, the collapse came once the credit<br />

ex pan s ion was h a I ted • T h us, the rna 1ad jus t men t s surfaced<br />

the moment the Federal Reserve terminated its<br />

easy money policies in mid-1929, <strong>and</strong> the depression<br />

ensued.(68)<br />

What are the policy implications of the Austrian<br />

theory? According to the proponents of contra-cyclical<br />

policies, government is supposed to stablilize the economy<br />

by reducing taxes <strong>and</strong> increasing expenditures in<br />

times of economic downturns in order to increase aggregate<br />

spending <strong>and</strong> thus st imulate the economy. Conversely,<br />

in times of economic boom, the government is<br />

to increase taxes <strong>and</strong> reduce expenditures in order to<br />

k e e p the e con 0 my from "0ve r hea ting • " I nth i s wa y, i t<br />

is argued, the economy can be stabilized <strong>and</strong> permanent<br />

prosperity <strong>and</strong> full employment maintained.(69)<br />

The Austrians contend that such a policy will only<br />

rna k e rna t ter s worse. I f the depress ion is the necessary<br />

process of adjust ing to the malinvestments caused by<br />

the preceding boom, <strong>and</strong> since the boom was a direct result<br />

of government credit expansion, renewed expansion<br />

can only postpone the inevitable <strong>and</strong> the process induce<br />

fur the r mal i n v est men t s wh i c h wilIon 1y rna ke the r e ­<br />

adjustment process, which must ultimately come, even<br />

more severe. Once again, the Great Depression illustrates<br />

this point. The deficit financing of the Hoover<br />

<strong>and</strong> Roosevelt Administrations, as well as other policies<br />

of public works, subsidies, price supports, minimum<br />

wages, etc., argue the Austrians, obstructed the<br />

adjustment process <strong>and</strong> hence needlessly prolonged the<br />

depression.<br />

The Austrian prescription is both simple <strong>and</strong> quite<br />

congenial to the individualist anarchist. The governmen<br />

t s h 0 u Idstop i n f I a ting i mm e d i ate 1y <strong>and</strong> then rem0 ve<br />

all forms of intervention. This will permit the admittedly<br />

painful adjustment process to be completed in the<br />

shortest time. After that, the government should stay<br />

completely out of the economy <strong>and</strong> refrain from any type<br />

o fer e d i t man i p u I a t ion. 1fthis isaccom pI ished, the<br />

Au s t ria n s bel i eve t hat e con om i c pr os per i t y wou I d be<br />

assured <strong>and</strong> economic development would proceed at a<br />

fairly even, gradual pace.<br />

7. GOVERNMENT AND TAXATION<br />

It is generally assumed that to survive all governments<br />

must tax, <strong>and</strong> IndiVIdualist anarchists have<br />

257


accused the minarchists of inconsistency by championing<br />

the individual's natural right to property on the one<br />

h<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> arguing for a government, regardless of how<br />

restricted, on the other. It is charged that government<br />

must tax <strong>and</strong> that taxation violates the individual's<br />

property right. Recently, however, minarchists<br />

suehas Ay n Ra nd, J 0 hn H0 s pers<strong>and</strong> Ro be r t No z i c k, ha ve<br />

responded to this criticism by proposing a government<br />

fin a nee d not bye 0 e r c i vet a x a t ion but by vo I un tar y<br />

contributions.<br />

One ve r s ion i s the g i f t me thod 0 f finan c i ngadv0cated<br />

by Ayn R<strong>and</strong>. R<strong>and</strong> believes that the wealthy<br />

s t rat a, i. e ., thos e wh 0 wo u I d havethe mo s t to los e i f<br />

there were no protection against anti-social individuals,<br />

would voluntarily pay for government protection.<br />

Since police protection is assumed to be a collective<br />

good, "those on the lowest economic levels••• would<br />

be virtually exempt [from payment] -- though they would<br />

st i II enjoy the benefits of legal protection, such as<br />

that afforded by the armed forces, by the police <strong>and</strong> by<br />

the courts dealing with criminal offenses."(70) Provided<br />

government were small enough, the costs would be<br />

only a small burden to the wealthy contributors. One<br />

of the mer its of the system, as R<strong>and</strong> sees it, is precisely<br />

that it would serve to keep government from exp<strong>and</strong>ing<br />

beyond its only proper function of defending<br />

individual rights. The individualist anarchists are<br />

c r i tic a I 0 f t his pro p 0 s a I on two coun t s • Fir s t, "i t<br />

con t i nues that disjunction between payment <strong>and</strong> receipt<br />

of service which constitutes one of the great defects<br />

of a taxing system." This, of course, tends to perpetuate<br />

the calculational problems endemic in any government<br />

operation. Second, the fact that everyone will<br />

continue to receive services regardless of whether or<br />

not he contributes will tend to discourage contributions.<br />

Since company A will receive protection regardless<br />

of its contributions, it will be able to obtain an<br />

edge on its competitors by ceasing its contributions<br />

<strong>and</strong> lowering its prices to attract more customers.<br />

This, anarchists hold, will force other companies to do<br />

the same, <strong>and</strong> the voluntary contributions would soon<br />

corne to a halt.(71)<br />

A second alternative, that of "voluntary taxation,"<br />

was originally advocated by such men as Herbert<br />

Spencer <strong>and</strong> Auberon Herbert <strong>and</strong> more recently by John<br />

Hospers <strong>and</strong> Robert Nozick. - Under this system one agency<br />

would be invested with 8 monopoly on the use of<br />

force. No one, however, would be compelled to purchase<br />

258


Its serVIces. Instead, the agency would charge a price<br />

for its services <strong>and</strong> each member of the community could<br />

then either purchase protection at that price or go<br />

without protection. "If you want police protection,"<br />

says Hospers, "you will have to pay a fee to obtain it,<br />

but 0 f co u r s e you are f r e e not to wa ntit 0 r pa y for<br />

it, in which case you will not have the protection even<br />

if you need it."(72) While this does have the merit of<br />

eliminatIng the "payment-benefit disjunction," the ind<br />

i v i d uali s tanarchis t rna i n t a ins t hat the propon e n t s 0 f<br />

voluntary taxation are inconsistent. tlIf the government<br />

elected to outlaw all competing defense agencies,"<br />

notes Rothbard,<br />

it would no longer function as the voluntary<br />

society sought by its proponents. It would<br />

not for c epa ym en t 0 f t a xes, but i t wo u 1d say<br />

to the citizens: "You are free to accept <strong>and</strong><br />

pay for our protection or to abstain; but you<br />

are not free to purchase defense from a<br />

com pet i n gag e n c y • nThlsi s not a f r e e rna r ­<br />

ket; this is a compUlsory monopoly, once<br />

again a grant of monopoly privilege by the<br />

Sta te to it sel f. Such a monopoly would be<br />

far less efficient than a freely competitive<br />

system; hence, its costs would be higher, its<br />

service poorer. It would clearly not be<br />

neutral to the market.(73)<br />

One fInal alternative is the "voting" or "poll"<br />

tax. Voters would be charged a fee. But voting would<br />

be voluntary so this would not be a tax. Whether a<br />

"poll tax" would be able to generate revenues<br />

s u f fie i e n t t 0 rna i n t a ina go vernmentis do ub t f u I • Even<br />

when voting is free barely fifty percent of those<br />

eligible consider voting important enough to do so. It<br />

seems likely that if a fee were charged even that<br />

percentage would drop considerably. But as the number<br />

of vot er s dec I i ned, the government would only be able<br />

to support itself by increasing the burden on the<br />

remaining voters, thereby discouraging voting even<br />

more.(74) The result would be that either the<br />

government would collapse or it would have to raise the<br />

poll tax to such heights as to disenfranchise the poor,<br />

leaving government policy to be determIned almost<br />

exclUSIvely by the wealthy. Thus, the individualist<br />

anarchist is highly skeptical of any proposal for the<br />

fInancing of government by means of voluntary<br />

contributions.<br />

259


The ·individualist anarchist appears to have the<br />

bet t e r 0 f the iss ue • Fir s t, v 0 ting i s a h i gh 1Y rna r gina<br />

I act for the vas t rna j 0 r i t Y 0 f cit i zens, so itse em s<br />

doubtful that government could be financed by the "poll<br />

tax." Second, the gift method would create an incentive<br />

to evade payment. Whether this would create an<br />

insuperable problem is an empirical question. Its prop<br />

0 n e n t s, s u c has Ra nd, bel i eve t hat solongas govern ­<br />

ment was 1 imited to the provision of defense <strong>and</strong> court<br />

services its cost would be so small that little or no<br />

competitive edge could be obtained by not contributing.<br />

Moreover, such a society is seen as being so prosperous<br />

that the payments, small to begin with, would become<br />

increasingly less burdensome as the st<strong>and</strong>ard of living<br />

rose. Whether these factors would alone make the gift<br />

proposal feasible cannot be answered by recourse to<br />

the 0 r y a Ion e. Th i r d, sincern0 stind i v i d ua I s pr e sen ted<br />

with a choice between no protection <strong>and</strong> paying a stipulated<br />

fee would be likely to pay the fee, the "voluntary<br />

taxat ion" method would be the most likely to succeed.<br />

But the individualist anarchist is correct in<br />

pointing out that to the extent that their proponents<br />

conceive of these proposals as establishing a purely<br />

voluntary society they fail, for all are contingent<br />

u p 0 nth e e xis tenceo f a sin g I e agen c y rna i n t a i n i ng a<br />

rnonopolyof the use of force within a given geographical<br />

area. Thus, the concept of "voluntary government<br />

fin a n c i n g " i samy t h : tothe ex ten t t hat i t wo u 1d be<br />

successful, it would not really be voluntary; to the<br />

extent that it would be voluntary it would not be<br />

successful.<br />

8 • DEM


of participants, whenever government acts, one particular<br />

policy must be chosen for the entire society <strong>and</strong><br />

then imposed on those who disagree with the choice.<br />

In contrast, argues the anarchist, when the choice<br />

ish<strong>and</strong> led 0 nthe rna r ketc0 ere ion i s a bsent<strong>and</strong> a wid e<br />

variety of alternatives is present, permitting not just<br />

the majority but a multitude of minorities to get their<br />

way as well. The distinction between democracy <strong>and</strong> the<br />

market can be illustrated by the following example.<br />

Assume that three individuals, Larry, Curly <strong>and</strong><br />

Moe, are trying to determine the "correct" amount of<br />

life insurance coverage. After examining the benefits<br />

of the coverage <strong>and</strong> comparing them to the costs, each<br />

individual would arrive at an amount of coverage which,<br />

all things considered, would maximize his utility.<br />

It is likely that the optimum, or equilibrium level,<br />

w0 u I d d iff e r for e a chi n d i v i d ua I • Sin c e La r r y has a<br />

large family <strong>and</strong> a risky occupation, being a window<br />

washer on a skyscrapper, he desires considerable coverage.<br />

Moe, on the other h<strong>and</strong>, is single <strong>and</strong> has terminalea<br />

nee r. G i v e n his rna r ita1sta t usan d the e x orb i ­<br />

tant premiums, he desires only a minimum amount. Curly<br />

is an accountant with a small family. He desires an<br />

intermediate amount. Their optimal insurance levels<br />

are depicted in Fig. 1. The solid sloping lines simply<br />

indicate that one's utilitv declines as one moves awav<br />

from one's optimum. - -<br />

Utility U<br />

Curly Larry<br />

low------------------> high<br />

Figure 1: Optimum Coverage Levels<br />

If insurance were supplied on the market, Larry<br />

would purchase more than Curly <strong>and</strong> Curly more than Moe.<br />

E 8 C h w0 U 1 d 8 d jus t his pur c has e s s 0 a s t 0 rna x i rn i z e his<br />

ut iIi tv. But if the issue were decided democratical lv,<br />

only Curly would obtain his optImum. If a c<strong>and</strong>idate<br />

took a position at or near Moe's optimum he would be<br />

defeated by a c<strong>and</strong>idate taking a position at or near<br />

261


wr itt en, " The consis ten c y 0 f rna r ketchoi c e i sachie ve d<br />

Wittlout the overruling of minority values as would be<br />

in the case if ordinary political voting were made consistent.<br />

Therefore, in a very real sense, market decisions<br />

are comparable to political decisions only when<br />

unanimity is present."(76)<br />

The inefficiency of democracy relative to the market<br />

is widely acknOWledged even by democrats. The obvious<br />

question is why not dispense with democracy <strong>and</strong><br />

rely entirely on the market? The usual response is that<br />

in many cases those affected by an exchange are not the<br />

sam e a s thoset ran sac tin g the ex chan g e • Co 1 I e c t i ve<br />

goods are goods whose benefits cannot be restricted to<br />

the transacting parties, but ttspillover," gratis as it<br />

wer,e, onto third parties. Since individuals will reap<br />

the benefits of the collective good regardless of<br />

whether they pay the costs, there is no incentive to<br />

pay. But if everyone thinks this way, no one will pay.<br />

Thus, if payments were voluntary, the collective good<br />

would not be provided at all, or at only a suboptimal<br />

level. Coercion, i.e., government, is required to<br />

overcome the "free rider" problem.<br />

The real choice, according to the democrat, is<br />

not between permitting each individual to purchase his<br />

optimal qua n tit Y 0 fag00d 0 r s e r vice ,<strong>and</strong>imposing 0 n<br />

the e n t ire soc i e t y a pa r ticu 1a r qua ntit Y t hat i s nonopt<br />

imal for all but the median voter. Rather, it is a<br />

choice between providing a good, albeit at a nonoptimal<br />

level for most, <strong>and</strong> not providing it at all. Since<br />

everyone is assumed to desire at least some quantity of<br />

the good, a nonoptimal supply is better than none at<br />

all.(77)<br />

In response, the anarchist argues that the number<br />

of collective goods is exaggerated <strong>and</strong> that nearly all<br />

goo d sea n be b r 0 ken down i n t 0 rna r gina I un its <strong>and</strong> sol d<br />

onth e mar k e t. And for tho s e goods t hat ar e act ua I I Y<br />

collective, effective noncoercive means can be found<br />

for their provision.<br />

With this in mind we can now examine the specifics<br />

of the anarachists paradigm.<br />

263


FOOTNOTES<br />

(l)See Rudolph Rocker, "Anarchism <strong>and</strong> Anarcho­<br />

Syndicalism," appendix to Paul Eltzbacher, Anarchism<br />

(New York: Chip's, n.d.), pp. 227-72; <strong>and</strong> George<br />

Woodcock, "Syndicalism, the Industrial Expression of<br />

Anarchism," Patterns of Anarchy. eds. L. I.<br />

Krimmerman <strong>and</strong> L. Perry (New York: Anchor, 1966), pp.<br />

38-42. Also see Mulford Sibley, Political Ideas <strong>and</strong><br />

Ideologies (New York: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1970), pp. 547­<br />

48; <strong>and</strong> Get D. H. Cole, Social Theory (London: 1920),<br />

especially pp. 128-43.<br />

(2)Peter Kropotkin, "Fields, FactorieS <strong>and</strong> Workshops,"<br />

The Essent ial Kropotkio. eds. E. Caporya <strong>and</strong><br />

K. Thomp kin s ( New Yo r k : L i verigh t, 19 7 S), pp. 27 0 - 7 2 ;<br />

<strong>and</strong> Alex<strong>and</strong>er Berkman, The ABC of Anarchism (London:<br />

F r e e d om Pre s s, 1973), p. 76.<br />

(3)Kropotkin, p. 282.<br />

(4)Ibid., p. 272.<br />

(S)Berkman, pp. 68-69. Such statements as these<br />

by Berkman <strong>and</strong> Kropotkin abound in the literature. They<br />

c I ear I yindieate ami sun d e r s t<strong>and</strong>ing 0 f how e con om i c<br />

systems -- all economic systems -- function. The purpose<br />

of an economic system is to produce <strong>and</strong> distribute<br />

goo d san d s e r vice s • But, a s Thoma s S owe 11 po i n t S ou t ,<br />

"what is crucial for underst<strong>and</strong>ing the way it functions<br />

is that it is a system for rationing goods <strong>and</strong> services<br />

that are inadequate to supply all that people want."<br />

This is true for all economic systems, including communism.<br />

Because goods were so abundant that rationing<br />

was not necessary, "the Garden of Eden was not an economic<br />

system." Writers such as Berkman <strong>and</strong> Kropotkin<br />

seem to assume that scarcity is not a fact of nature<br />

but a product of the capitalist economic system. Scarci<br />

ty will disappear when the economic system is changed<br />

to socialism. Witness Berkman's comment that under socialism<br />

"as much food will be raised as the country<br />

needs." But, as Sowell notes, "because economic systems<br />

are essentially systems of rationing, any successfu<br />

1 funct ion ing economic system would have unmet needs<br />

everywhere. The alternative would be to completely<br />

satisfy all of some category of needs -- the most urgent,<br />

the moderately important, <strong>and</strong> the trivially marginal<br />

thereby leaving still more unsatisfied (<strong>and</strong><br />

far more urgent) needs unmet elsewhere in the economy<br />

The mundane fact of insufficiencv must be insisted<br />

upon <strong>and</strong> reiterated because so many discussions of 'unmet<br />

needs' proceed as if 'better' policies, practices,<br />

ora t tit u des wo u Id's 0 1ve' the prob I em a t han d wit h 0 u t<br />

264


creat ing deficIencies elsewhere. Typical of thIs attit<br />

u d e i s the commen t t hat 'I f weean send a rna n tot he<br />

moon, why can't we --' followed by whatever project the<br />

speaker favors. The fact that we sent a man to the<br />

moon is par t of the reason why many other things could<br />

not be done." Thomas Sowell, Knowledge <strong>and</strong> Decisions<br />

(New York: Basic Books, 1980), pp. 45-46.<br />

( 6 ) I s rae I K i r z n e r, Ma r k e t The 0 r y <strong>and</strong> the Pr ice<br />

System (Princeton: D. Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>, 1963).<br />

( 7 ) I bid., p. 39.<br />

(8)F. A. Hayek, Individualism <strong>and</strong> Economic Order<br />

(Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1972,), pp. 86-87.<br />

( 9 ) L u dwig <strong>von</strong> Mis e s, Soc i ali sm (London: J. Cap e ,<br />

1969), p. 535.<br />

(lO)F. A. Hayek, "What is 'Social'? What Does It<br />

Mea n ? ,n StudiesIn Phi los 0 phy, Pol i tics<strong>and</strong>Ec0 nom i c s<br />

(New York: Simon <strong>and</strong> Schuster, 1969), p. 244. Also see<br />

E. C. Pasour, "On Economic Justice," Modern Age<br />

(Summer 1981), pp. 290-99.<br />

(11) F.A. Hayek, The Road to Ser fdom (Chicago:<br />

University of Chicago Press, 1967), pp. 61-64.<br />

(12)Ibid., p. 74.<br />

(13)Murray Rothbard, Man, Economy, <strong>and</strong> <strong>State</strong><br />

(Los An gel e s : Nash, 19 7 0 ), pp. 5 60 - 61 •<br />

(14)Murray Rothbard, "Anarcho-Communism," Egalitarianism<br />

as a Revolt Against Nature, <strong>and</strong> other essays<br />

(Washington, D. C.: Libertarian Review Press, 1974),<br />

pp. 121-24.<br />

(15)The pioneering work on this topic was F. A.<br />

Hayek's "The Use of Knowledge in <strong>Society</strong>." See his<br />

Individualism <strong>and</strong> Economic Order, pp.77-91. Also<br />

see Thomas Sowell's brilliant <strong>and</strong> in-depth study,<br />

Knowledge <strong>and</strong> Decisions, op cit. Also valuable is E.<br />

C. Pasour, "Economic Efficiency: Touchstone or Mirage,"<br />

The Intercollegiate Review (Fall/Winter 1981), pp.<br />

33-44.<br />

(16)The classic work on the subject of economic<br />

calculation was done by <strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>. See his<br />

Human Action (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1966), pp.<br />

200-31 <strong>and</strong> 689-715; <strong>and</strong> his Socialism. Also see F.<br />

A. Hayek, ed., Collectivist Economic Planning<br />

(Clifton, New Jersey: Augustus M. Kelley, 1975), <strong>and</strong><br />

Don Lavoie, National Economic Planning: What is<br />

Left? ( Cam b rid g e : Ba I I I nge r, 19 85 ). Os car La n g e a 1legedly<br />

"refuted ll <strong>Mises</strong> on this point. But see Paul<br />

Craig Roberts, "Oskar Lange's Theory of Socialist Planning,"<br />

Journal of Politicsl Economy (May 1971), pp.<br />

562-77. Also of great interest is the entire Winter<br />

1982 issue of The Journal of Libertarian Studies<br />

WhICh is devoted to Ilan economic critique of soclal-<br />

265


ism." For a simple presentation of the argument, see<br />

my" Mar x, Mis e san d Soc i a lism,." The F r e ema n (0 c t 0 be r<br />

1974), pp. 605-11.<br />

( 1 7 ) See Mu r ray Rot h bar d, F r e e d om , I n equalitY,<br />

Primitivism <strong>and</strong> the Division of Labor (Menlo Park,<br />

Cal.: <strong>Institute</strong> for Humane Studies, 1971).<br />

(18)Warren J. Samuels, "Anarchism <strong>and</strong> the Theory<br />

of Power," Further Explorations in the Theory of Anarchy,<br />

ed. Gordon Tullock (Blacksburg, Vir.: University<br />

Publications, 1974), p. 40.<br />

(19)Ibid., p. 48.<br />

(20)Ibid., p. 51.<br />

(21)Ibid., pp. 49-56.<br />

(22)See especially, Robert Dahl, Modern Political<br />

Analysis (Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice­<br />

Hall, 1970), pp. 14-34; Robert Dahl, "Power," International<br />

Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (New<br />

York: Macmillan, 1968), vol. 12, pp. 405-15; Harold<br />

Lasswell <strong>and</strong> Abraham Kaplan, Power <strong>and</strong> <strong>Society</strong> (New<br />

Haven: Yale University Press, 1950).<br />

(23)Dahl, Modern Political Analysis, p. 32.<br />

(24)Laswell <strong>and</strong> Kaplan, pp. 74-76.<br />

(25)See Arthur Kalleburg, "The Logic of Comparison:<br />

A Methodological Note on the Comparative Study of<br />

Political Systems," World Politics (October 1966),<br />

p p. 6 9 - 8 2. AsKa II enbur g rna kescI ear, the two t e c hn i ­<br />

quesare not inherently mutually exclusive but may at<br />

times be complementary.<br />

(26)Dahl, Modern Political Analysis, p. 32.<br />

(27)Not everyone, however, regards the lack of<br />

"operationalizability" as a liability. See, for example,<br />

Giovanni Sartori, "Concept Misinformation in Comparative<br />

Politics," The American Political Science<br />

Review (December 1970), pp. 1033-53, <strong>and</strong> especially p.<br />

1045: "Now, we are surely required to reduce ambiguity<br />

by cutting down the range of meanings of concepts. But<br />

the operational criterion of reducing ambiguity entails<br />

drastic losses in conceptual richness <strong>and</strong> in explanatory<br />

power. Take, for instance, the suggestion that<br />

r social class r should be dismissed <strong>and</strong> replaced by a<br />

set of operational statements relating to income, occupation,<br />

education level, etc. If the suggestion were<br />

adopted wholesale, the loss of conceptual substance<br />

would be not only considerable, but unjustified. The<br />

same appl ies, to cite another example, to 'power.' To<br />

be concerned with the measurement of power does not imply<br />

that the meaning of the concept should be reduced<br />

to what can be measured about power -- the latter view<br />

would make human behavior in whatever collective sphere<br />

almost inexpl icable." Two things are worthy of note<br />

266


here. First, the use of imprecise concepts may well be<br />

w 0 r t h w h i Ie, evennee ded, .. a t t.h e I eve I 0 f res ear c h • But<br />

this can hardly be the case at the level of applicat<br />

ion, i. e ., as use d by dec i s ion rna ke r s • And i tis the<br />

level of appl i cat ion that Rothbard is concerned with.<br />

Second, even at the research level, "conceptual richness"<br />

may well prove to be merely a euphemism for "conceptual<br />

confusion."<br />

(28)See, for example, Rothbard, Power <strong>and</strong> Market<br />

(Menlo Park, Cal.: <strong>Institute</strong> for Humane Studies, 1970),<br />

pp. 168-73 <strong>and</strong> 194-96. Milton Shapiro has aptly noted<br />

t hat abe t t e r tit I e for t his boo k w 0 u I d h a ve bee n<br />

Power or Market. See hi s "Power OR Market: government<br />

<strong>and</strong> the economy: a review," Libertarian Analysis<br />

( V0 I. 1, Nurn b e r 4), Pp. 2 2 - 29 •<br />

(29)Dahl, Modern Political Analysis, pp. 32-33.<br />

(30)For other definitions of power see Dahl's<br />

" Power • " A Iso see J 0 h n C ham p 1 in, e d •• Power ( New<br />

York: Lieber, 1971); Peter Bachrach <strong>and</strong> Morton Baratz.<br />

"Two Faces of Power," The American Political Science<br />

Rev i ew (D e c e mb e r 1 9 6 1 ), PP • 9 47 - 52; <strong>and</strong> the i r n Dec i ­<br />

sions <strong>and</strong> Nondecisions: An Analytical Framework," The<br />

American Political Science Review (September 1963),<br />

pp. 632-42; <strong>and</strong> Harry Eckstein. "Authority Patterns,"<br />

Compar a t i v e Pol i tic s : Not e s 8 n d Read i n g S teds. Ra y<br />

Macridis <strong>and</strong> Bernard Brown (Homewood, Ill.: Dorsey,<br />

1977), pp. 271-99, to ci te just a few.<br />

(31)H. E. Frech III, "The Public Choice Theory of<br />

Murray N. Rothbard, A Modern American Anarchist,"<br />

Public Choice (Vol. 14, 1973). pp. 149-50.<br />

(32)Bruno Leoni, <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> the Law (Los<br />

Angel es: Nash, 1971), p. 55.<br />

(33)Murray Rothbard, For A New Liberty (New<br />

York: Macmillan, 1973), pp. 208-09.<br />

(34)Ibid., p. 209.<br />

(35)Milton Friedman, Capitalism <strong>and</strong> <strong>Freedom</strong><br />

(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1969), pp. 21<br />

<strong>and</strong> 109.<br />

( 3 6 ) Wa 1 t erG r i n d er<strong>and</strong> J 0 hn Hage I I I I, "Towa r d a<br />

Theory of <strong>State</strong> CapItalism: Ultimate Decision-Making<br />

<strong>and</strong> Class Structure,: The Journal of Libertarian<br />

Studie s (W i n t e r 1 9 7 7 ), P • 67. A1S 0 see Ro t hbar d, For<br />

A New Liberty, p. 53.<br />

(37)F. A. Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty<br />

(Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1971), p. 12.<br />

(38)Harold Laski t "Liberty," Encyclopedia of the<br />

Soc i 8 I Sci e nee s V 0 I. 9. ( New Yo r k : Ma cm i I I an, 19 4 6 ) ,<br />

p. 443.<br />

(39 )Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty. pp.<br />

12-23.<br />

267


(40) See, for example, '''The Regulators,' They Cost<br />

You $130 Billion a Year," U.5. News <strong>and</strong> World Report<br />

(June,30, 1975), pp. 24-28.<br />

(41)Edward Banfield, The Unheavenly City<br />

Rev i sit e d (B 0 s ton : Lit tie, Brown <strong>and</strong> Co., 19 7 4 ), PP .<br />

57-61.<br />

(42)Charles Murray, Losing Ground, American<br />

5 0 cia I Pol icy. 1 9 5 0- 19 80 (N ew Yo r k : Basic, 19 8 4 ), p.<br />

155.<br />

(43)Sowell, pp. 257-58 <strong>and</strong> 344.<br />

(44)Daniel Patrick Moynihan, "Poverty in Cities,"<br />

The Metropolitan Engima. (New York: Anchor, 1970)<br />

ed., James Q. Wilson, p. 369.<br />

( 45 ) I n Banfie I d, P • 129.<br />

( 46 ) Pas 0 ur, " Econ om i c Jus tice ," p. 29 1 •<br />

(47)Banfield, pp.128-29.<br />

(48)See, for example, George Stigler, "Director's<br />

Law of Public Income Distribution," Journal of Law <strong>and</strong><br />

Economics (April 1970), pp. 1-10. The same holds true<br />

for programs like social security. First, since the<br />

tax is regressive, the poor pay a higher percentage of<br />

their earnings in social security taxes. Second, since<br />

the poor usually do not go to college, they tend to ent<br />

e r the w0 r k for ceea r lie r than middle <strong>and</strong> upper income<br />

individuals. They therefore begin paying social security<br />

taxes much earlier. And finally, statistics show<br />

that the poor have a shorter life expectancy than other<br />

economi c groups. The result is that the poor tend to<br />

pay the most into social security <strong>and</strong> receive the<br />

fewest benefits.<br />

(49 )See, for example, Reo Chr istenson, Challenge<br />

<strong>and</strong> Decis ion (New York: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1976), pp.<br />

79-86. Especially see p. 80: "about one-fourth of the<br />

(Job Corps) recruits stayed less than a month. Less<br />

than half stayed for six months, though strongly<br />

encouraged to stay for nine months."<br />

( 5 0 ) Wa 1 t e r Wi I I i am s , Yo u t h<strong>and</strong> Min0 r i t y Un employment<br />

(Stanford: Hoover Institution Press, 1978).<br />

(51)Murray, p. 9.<br />

(52)See Yale Brazen, "Wage Rates, Minimum Wage<br />

Laws, <strong>and</strong> Unemployment," The Libertarian Alternative<br />

( Chi c ago : N e Iso n - Hal I, 1 9 7 4) ed ., T i b 0 r Ma c han, pp •<br />

380-99; <strong>and</strong> Wal ter Block, Defending the Undefendable<br />

( New Yo r k : FIee t Pres s, 19 7 6 ), pp. 2 32- 3 3 •<br />

( 5 3 ) L u d wig <strong>von</strong> Mis e s, The Ant i - Ca pitali s t<br />

Mentality (New York: Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>, 1956), pp.88-89.<br />

(54)See Block, pp.154-70.<br />

(55)Pasour, "Economic Justice," p. 297.<br />

(56)See, for example, L. T. Sargent's TlNozick <strong>and</strong><br />

the Libertarian Tradition," Paper presented at the Mid-<br />

268


west Political Science Convention, Chicago, April 26 to<br />

\1ay 1, 1976 ... Sar.gent's assertion that "the most thoroughly<br />

unexplained assumptIons" of libertarians "are<br />

those that state that capitalism will produce sufficient<br />

goods <strong>and</strong> will remain a reasonably open system,<br />

<strong>and</strong> that "capitalism is simply placed with God, Motherhood,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the Flag <strong>and</strong> not examined," (p. 6) is completely<br />

inexplicable to me. Sargent gives no evidence<br />

to support this charge, <strong>and</strong> libertarians in general are<br />

more often criticized for spending too much time dealing<br />

with economics. Included among Rothbard's economic<br />

w r i tin gsis Man, E con om y <strong>and</strong> S tate, a 9 8 5 page t r eatise<br />

on economics. Other libertarian economists, to<br />

name just a few, include James Buchanan, Israel<br />

Kirzner, Walter Block, Walter Grinder,D. T. Armantano,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Don Lavoie. One may disagree with their economics,<br />

<strong>and</strong> man y do. But toeh a rae t e r i ze the e con om i cposit ion<br />

of libertarians as based on "thoroughly unexamined<br />

assumptions" IS simply untrue.<br />

( 57 ) See Rot h bar d, ME S, p p. 560 - 660; Ro t h ba r d ,<br />

Power <strong>and</strong> Market, pp. 28-33,43-47,58-59. Also see<br />

D. T. Armantano, The Myths of Antitrust (New<br />

Rochelle: Arlingt.on House, 1972); <strong>and</strong> John S<strong>and</strong>ers,<br />

The Ethical Argument Against Government (Washington,<br />

D. C.: Un i ve r sit Y Pre s s 0 f Am e rican 19 8 0 ), pp. 1 3 3 - 54 •<br />

(58)lt should be pointed out that the Rothbardian<br />

or individualist anarchist monopoly theory is, as Frech<br />

says, "a novel one," <strong>and</strong> one that is not, it must be<br />

noted, shared by many other economists. Even <strong>von</strong><br />

<strong>Mises</strong>, "whom Rothbard claims as his mentor," comments<br />

Frech, argues in Human Action that "monopoly .prices<br />

are an important market phenomenon," that "some world<br />

cartels would exist even in the absence of any government<br />

interference," <strong>and</strong> that the consumer "is not so<br />

well served under monopoly prices as under competitive<br />

prices." Frech, pp. 150-51. Whether or not the Rothbardian<br />

monopoly theory is correct is difficult to say.<br />

I t has been largely ignored by economists. Other than<br />

the v e r y b r i e f F r e cher i t i que, the 0 n 1y e conom i cana 1y ­<br />

sis that I have been able to find was by Walter Block.<br />

Block supports the Rothbardian position. See his<br />

"Austrian Monopoly Theory -- A Critique," The Journal<br />

of Libertarian StUdies (Fall 1977), pp. 271-79. For<br />

empirical support for this position see the works cited<br />

in Chapter III, footnote 59, p. 114.<br />

( 5 9 ) Man cur 0 Ison, The Log i c 0 f ColIec t i ve Act ion<br />

(New York: Shocken Books, 1968).<br />

(60)Rothbard, Power <strong>and</strong> Market, pp. 126-28.<br />

( 6 1 ) I bid ., p. 6,; A ] s 0 see \1 u r ray Rot h bar d ,<br />

'TToward a Reconstruction of Utility <strong>and</strong> Welfare Econo-<br />

269


mics," On <strong>Freedom</strong> <strong>and</strong> Free Enterprise (Princeton:<br />

Van Nostr<strong>and</strong>, 1956), ed.,Mary Senholz, pp. 250-53.<br />

(62)John Maynard Keynes, General Theory of<br />

Employment, Interest <strong>and</strong> Money (New York: Harcourt,<br />

Bra ce <strong>and</strong> Wor I d, 1936); Joseph Schumpeter, The Theory<br />

of Economic Development (New York: Oxford University<br />

Press, 1967). For a good presentation of the "accelera<br />

tor p r inc i pIe ," see Ca r I Da uten<strong>and</strong> Lloyd Val en tine ,<br />

Bus iness Cycles <strong>and</strong> Forecasting (Cincinnati: South­<br />

Western PUblishing, 1974), pp. 101-06. The anarchist<br />

c r i.t i que 0 f theseex p I a nat ions can be f 0 undin Ro t h ­<br />

bard, MES, pp. 661-764.<br />

(63)The general feeling among economists seems to<br />

be that the Austrian theory would hold only under the<br />

unus u a 1 c i r cum s tanceo f "fu 11 em p I 0 ym e n t • tt See, for<br />

example, Dauten <strong>and</strong> Valentine, p. 101: "The thesis that<br />

credit, which is created when the market rate of interest<br />

differs from the natural rate, goes to the higher<br />

stages of production <strong>and</strong> leads to an imbalance between<br />

consumpt i on <strong>and</strong> investment would be generally true und<br />

e r cond 1 t ion s 0 f con tin u0 us f u I I em p I 0 ym en t • Howe ve r ,<br />

the ups win g 0 f the c y c I estartsat a time wh enthe<br />

economy has unused resources, <strong>and</strong> the production of<br />

both producer goods <strong>and</strong> consumer goods can be exp<strong>and</strong>ed<br />

before full em p loymen tof res 0 ur c e s is reached." For<br />

an "Austrian" reply to this type of criticism see F. A.<br />

Hayek, " F u I I Emp loymen t, PIa n n i n g <strong>and</strong> I n f I a t ion, "<br />

Studiesin Phi los 0 ph y, Pol i tics<strong>and</strong> Econom i cs (N ew<br />

York: Simon <strong>and</strong> Schuster, 1969), pp. 270-79.<br />

(64)See F. A. Hayek, Monetary Theory <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Trade Cycle (London: J. Cape, 1933), p. 101.<br />

(65)For a good summary of this process see <strong>Mises</strong>,<br />

Human Action, pp. 538-86; LUdwig <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>, The<br />

Theory of Money <strong>and</strong> Credit (Irvington-on-Hudson:<br />

F.E.E., 1971), pp. 261-410; F. A. Hayek, Prices <strong>and</strong><br />

Production (London: George Routledge, 1932), pp.<br />

76-84; Rothbard, American's Great Depression<br />

( P r inc e ton : Van Nos t ran d, 1 9 6 3 ), p p. 1 1 - 79; Ga r y<br />

North, "Repressed Depression," The Freeman (April<br />

1969), pp. 224-34; LudWIg <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>,tttElastic Expect<br />

a t ions' <strong>and</strong> the Aus t r i'a nThe 0 r y 0 f the Tr a d e Cy c Ie, "<br />

Economic8 (August 1943), pp. 251-52. A concise <strong>and</strong><br />

excellent presentation is also found in the second<br />

e d i t ion 0 f M u r ray Rot h bar d's For ANew Libe r t y (N ew<br />

Yo r k: Ma cm ill an, 19 7 8 ), Pp. 18 3 - 9 3 .<br />

(66)F. A. Hayek, "Inflation Resulting From the<br />

Downward Inflexibility of Wages," Studies in Philosop<br />

h y, Pol i tics<strong>and</strong>Ec 0 nom i c s ( N ew Yo r k : S i m0 n<strong>and</strong><br />

Schuster, 1969), p. 296.<br />

( 6 7 ) Mis e s, Hum a n Act ion, p. 4 2 7; ,L u d wig <strong>von</strong><br />

;\1 i s e s, " F l' 0 m Cran k - up t 0 Cr a c k - up." Libe r tar ian For urn<br />

270


to carry out the wishes of others. Thus we finally<br />

come to the role of the state -- that of reducing the<br />

costs of government. The reducing of bargaining costs<br />

rn a y not beterr i b I Y dig n i fied, but itis a rna t t e r 0 f<br />

great practical importance••• "<br />

272


CHAPTER VIII<br />

The Areas of Anarchist-Minarchist Agreement<br />

There is considerable agreement between the anarchists<br />

<strong>and</strong> the minarchists. The single, though very<br />

important, difference between the two factions of libertarianism<br />

centers on the issue of police, court <strong>and</strong><br />

nat ional defense services. While "minarchists" such as<br />

Ayn R<strong>and</strong>, John Hospers, <strong>and</strong> Robert Nozick do not believethat<br />

the rna r ketca n fur n ish s uc h s e r vices<strong>and</strong>advocate<br />

a "night watchman" state to provide them, the<br />

anarchists maintain that the market can be extended<br />

into these areas as well.<br />

While a "blueprint" for the operations of such a<br />

society cannot be presented for every area, their proposal<br />

s for deali n g wit h the rna j 0 r iss ue s ca n be ind i ­<br />

cated. The areas of agreement between the anarchists<br />

<strong>and</strong> minarchists will be the focus of this chapter. The<br />

anarchist proposal for providing protection services,<br />

both domestic police <strong>and</strong> courts <strong>and</strong> "national defense,"<br />

will be examined in Chapter IX.<br />

1. ROADS<br />

In the absence of government all roads would, of<br />

course, be privately owned <strong>and</strong> operated; they would be<br />

run on the same profit/loss principles as any other<br />

bus iness. Since roads are commonly thought to be a<br />

classic example of a "collective good," the typical<br />

reaction is that a viable private road system would be<br />

impossible. Yet libertarians argue that "there is<br />

not h i n gun i que abo u t t ran s po r tat ion; t hat the e con om i c<br />

p r inc i pie s we a c c e ptas a rna t t e r 0 f cour s e i n prae t i ­<br />

ca lly every other area of human experiences are appl icab<br />

I e her e too." ( 1 ) Per haps the bes t wa y topres en t<br />

the libertarian proposal in this area is by examining<br />

their responses to several of the more common criticisms<br />

that can be raised against the prospect of private<br />

roads. These are:<br />

8. Cos t •<br />

The cost<br />

be so high as<br />

enterprise.<br />

of producing <strong>and</strong> maintaining roads would<br />

to be prohibitive if left up to private<br />

273


. Eminent Domain.<br />

If the r e we r e non rig h t 0 f em i n en t doma in" the<br />

result would be that (a) the costs of road construction<br />

would skyrocket, making the entire system economically<br />

untenable, <strong>and</strong> (b) roads would have to be built around<br />

those refusing to sell, resulting in numerous bends <strong>and</strong><br />

detours.<br />

c. Inconvenience.<br />

The owners of roads would have to charge their<br />

customers for the use of their roads. Methods of collect<br />

ion, such as toll booths, would render such a system<br />

far more inconvenient than public roads, financed<br />

by taxes <strong>and</strong> permitting unlimited use by drivers.<br />

d. Price Gouging.<br />

Since there can be only a limited number of roads<br />

ina n y g i v e n area, rna r ketcom pet i t ion wo u 1d bel imit ed,<br />

enabling road owners to charge exorbitant prices. Simi­<br />

I a r I y, i n d i v i d ua I s wo u I d be p I aced a t the mer c y 0 f the<br />

owner of the road onto which their driveways entered.<br />

e. Safety"l<br />

Since an owner could set any regulations he desired<br />

for the use of his roads, private roads would<br />

result in a confusing array of regUlations that would<br />

jeopardize the safety of the drivers.<br />

Libertarians, both anarchists <strong>and</strong> minarchists, bel<br />

i eve tha t a pr iva tely owned <strong>and</strong> operated road system<br />

is not only practical but attractive, <strong>and</strong> offer the<br />

following rebuttals:<br />

a. Cos t.<br />

Libertarians see this argument as the least tenable<br />

of the five <strong>and</strong> give it short shrift. The cost of<br />

construction <strong>and</strong> maintenance is high, they agree, but<br />

then so is the number of drivers using the roads. This<br />

cost pro-rates out to roughly $130.00 per person per<br />

yea r (i n 1 9 7 5 dol 1 a r s ). To a r g ue t hat t his wo u 1d be<br />

too expensive IS to ignore the fact that we are already<br />

paying this amount through gasoline taxes <strong>and</strong> the like.<br />

Hen c e, "i f the cos t 0 f us i n g p r i vat e r oa d s we ret h e<br />

same or even somewhat more than the cost of using pub­<br />

1 ic roads," argues Jarret Wollstein, lIdrlvers obviously<br />

274


could afford to pay these costs since they are already<br />

paying them. One hundred <strong>and</strong> twenty-eight dollars is<br />

clearly the same amount whether it is collected by the<br />

state through taxes or by private road companies<br />

through tolls <strong>and</strong> other fees."(2)<br />

b. Eminent Domain.<br />

The issue of eminent domain presents both a more<br />

d 1 f f i cuI ta ndam 0 rei n t eres ting que s t ion • Wh i lethe<br />

Rothbardian or natural rights variant of individualist<br />

anarchism must, of course, repudiate the entire concept<br />

of eminent domain as nothing more than legalized theft,<br />

the ut iIi tar ian, or Friedmanite, variant finds itself<br />

inn 0 s u c h m0 r a 1st r a i g h t - j a c ke t • For F r i e drna n, a s for<br />

Tucker in the nineteenth century, private property is<br />

def ined not as a moral or natural right but as a social<br />

expedient, a valuable one to be sure, but a social exped<br />

i en t none theless. As such, the problem of the lone<br />

holdout would not appear to be an insurmountable one.<br />

Since property is a social expedient there is nothing<br />

to prevent the courts in the anarchist society -- whose<br />

operation will be ,discussed in detail in the next chapter<br />

-- from incorporating into their Law Code a provision<br />

permitting, in extreme cases, such occasional violations<br />

of property rights as eminent domain. Thus, if<br />

a sin g I e hoi do u t we r e pr even ting the con s t r uc t i on 0 f a<br />

much needed road or bui Iding there would be nothing<br />

from the utilitarian point of view to prevent the<br />

courts from seIzing the property, ascertaining its<br />

"fair ll market value, <strong>and</strong> then awarding it to the construction<br />

company on the stipulation that the company<br />

pay the dispossessed owner for it.<br />

All of this would be anathema for the libertarian<br />

moralist, for whom any such coerced exchange, even one<br />

grant ing the owner the full market value of his propert<br />

y, is i mmo r a I. As Wo lIs t e i n pu t sit:<br />

For an economic transaction to be properly<br />

regarded as trade rather than theft, it is<br />

necessary that the parties involved (in this<br />

case the government <strong>and</strong> the property owner)<br />

mutually consent to all of the terms of the<br />

transaction, including price. The property<br />

own e r has the right to set any pr ice he<br />

wishes for the purchase of his property, or<br />

tor e f use t 0 s ell i t for any price wh a t s 0ever.<br />

It makes no difference what prlee<br />

eve r y 0 the rho use in the b 10 c k wa s sol d for.<br />

275


The i n d i v i d u a I has the righ t to set his own<br />

price for his own property.<br />

To sub s tit ute the f r e e rna r k e t for em inen t doma in, he<br />

concludes, is simply to "substitute justice for<br />

injustice•••"(3)<br />

The eli min a t ion 0 f em i n en t doma i n me an s t hat any<br />

property owner would have the right not to sell his<br />

property until or unless his conditions were met. The<br />

critical questions that must be faced by libertarians<br />

are therefore whether the repudiation of eminent domain<br />

would (a) so raise the cost of road construction as to<br />

render the idea of a privately financed road system<br />

untenable <strong>and</strong>/or (b) result in a confusing network of<br />

bends, curves <strong>and</strong> detours by forcing companies to build<br />

their roads around every hold-out.<br />

Libertarians argue that [1] privately constructed<br />

r 0 ads nee d benolessst r a i gh t t han thosewe now ha ve<br />

<strong>and</strong> [2] while paying the property owner a just price<br />

for his property might tend to increase the cost of<br />

road construction, other factors would reduce costs.<br />

First, since a business can make a profit only by satisfying<br />

consumers better than its competitors, <strong>and</strong><br />

sin c e the m0 s tat tract i ve r 0 ad from the s t<strong>and</strong> poi n t 0 f<br />

both cost <strong>and</strong> convenience would probably be a relatively<br />

inexpensive road with occasional turns, rather than<br />

either arrow-straight roads constructed at exorbitant<br />

costs or cheap roads with sharp turns at every block,<br />

.t ha tis the type of road it wi 11 pay the road entrepreneur<br />

to build. Second, Wollstein points out that<br />

much of the va I ue of commercial structures<br />

<strong>and</strong> houses stems from the social environment<br />

in which they exist. Thus, if a road building<br />

company buys all of the houses in a given<br />

area, so that there are no more neighbors for<br />

a family to socialize with, or customers for<br />

a business to sell to, the value of a home or<br />

business in that area would greatly decrease.<br />

Such considerations then discourage the<br />

rational home or business owner from holding<br />

out for too long, or for asking for too much<br />

money for his property. In the extreme, if a<br />

person held out Indefinitely ... he might<br />

well find himself living in the center-strip<br />

of a highway--not a very pleasant thought.(4)<br />

Third, since there are typically alternative<br />

276


outes that are possible, albeit of varying convenience,<br />

this means, points out economist Walter Block,<br />

that the maximum amount that could be charged by any<br />

holdout could be no more than the cheapest of all the<br />

alternatIves. Moreover, Block continues,<br />

The road developer, knowing that he will be<br />

satisfied with any of five trajectories, can<br />

purchase opt ions to buy the l<strong>and</strong> along each<br />

sit e • Ifar e c a I cit rantho I do u t rna t e ria 1 i z e s<br />

on anyone route, he can shift to his second,<br />

t h i r d, f 0 u r thor f 1fth cho ice.. The compe t itition<br />

between owners along each of these<br />

passages will tend to keep the price down.(5)<br />

And finall y, even i nthe wo r s t pos sib I e case, t hat<br />

of a holdout occupying an absolutely essential plot,<br />

libertarians remain undeterred.· It is at least conceivable,<br />

they maintain, for a developer to build<br />

either a tunnel underneath or a bridge over the l<strong>and</strong>.<br />

Thus, they argue, for all of the these reasons it is<br />

not a t alIeI ear t hat the e I 1m ina t ion 0 f em i n en t doma i n<br />

would, in fact, increase the cost of road construction.<br />

But eve n i f t his we reth e Ca s e I I be r tar ians rep I y t hat<br />

this is so only because the full cost of the roads<br />

would then be borne by their users rather than being<br />

partially passed off onto the hapless property owners<br />

who, under eminent domain, often receive less than the<br />

minimum for which they would have sold their property.<br />

But libertarians do not stop here. They argue<br />

that in all likelihood the cost of road construction<br />

w 0 u I d act u a 1 I Y bel e s sin the f r e e rna r k e t • P r i vat e<br />

enterprise is constrained to strive for profit. In<br />

contrast to "pUblic" projects, efficiency is a prime<br />

consideration. And, as previously noted, the libertarian<br />

bel i eves that government intervention must suspend<br />

the mar k e t pro c e s sin any <strong>and</strong> a 11 areasin wh i chi t<br />

operates, thereby creating isl<strong>and</strong>s of calculational<br />

chaos. Since this means that there'is no way for the<br />

government to allocate flits" resources efficiently,<br />

production costs for government operations tend to be<br />

considerable higher than comparable projects in the<br />

p r 1 vat e sector. Th us, con c 1 ude rna n y 1 i be r tar ians, p r i ­<br />

vat e r 0 ad con s t rue t ion, even wit h 0 u t em i n en t d oms in,<br />

w0 u 1 d pro b a b I Y b e c h e ape. r t han pub lie r 0 a d con s t rue ­<br />

tion, even with eminent domain.(6)<br />

Finally, libertarians note that road placements<br />

are now commonly determined by political criteria.<br />

277


qUIckly find hImself with few customers. Rothbard <strong>and</strong><br />

B I 0 c k fur the r a r g u e t hat i two u I d be c us t oma r y for<br />

homeowners to negotiate long term contracts with the<br />

road owner prohibiting just such capricious price<br />

hikes. "With this sort of 'easement' provided in advance<br />

by contract," Rothbard writes, "no such sudden<br />

blockade would be allowed, since it would be an invasion<br />

of the property rights of the l<strong>and</strong>owner."(12)<br />

e. Safety.<br />

The final objection is that since a private road<br />

s y s tern w0 u I d permit the own e r s to set the i r own r u I e s<br />

<strong>and</strong> regulat ions, it would result in a confusing array<br />

of contradictory regulations which, in turn, would jeopardize<br />

the safety of the drivers. Libertarians mainta<br />

i n tha t such a scenar io is highly improbable. True,<br />

road owners would be responsible for regulating their<br />

own property. If a company were negligent in the upkeep<br />

of its roads, permitting dangerous potholes to remain<br />

unrepaired, or if it were lax in the stipulation<br />

<strong>and</strong> enforcement of appropriate h'ighway rules, permittin<br />

g r e c k I e s s d r i v e r s t 0 endange r the I i ve s of 0 the r s<br />

- - 0 r if it in any other way made cond it ions i nconvenient<br />

for its patrons -- it would soon find its custome<br />

r s us i ng other roads. Thus, says Rothbard,. "any rna verick<br />

road owner who insisted on a left-h<strong>and</strong> drive or a<br />

green for' stop' instead of 'go' would soon find himsel<br />

f wi th numerous accIdents <strong>and</strong> the disappearance of<br />

customers <strong>and</strong> users."(13)<br />

On the related question of safety the libertarian<br />

finds it ironic that anyone could defend the current<br />

system against one privately run by citing the issue of<br />

safety. The current publIC system routinely results in<br />

the deaths of 50,000 Americans a year. This can hardly<br />

be termed a raving success. As Block puts it, "a worse<br />

job than that which is presently being done by the government<br />

road managers is difficult to envision." The<br />

problem stems precisely from the disjunction between<br />

income <strong>and</strong> performance inherent In the very nature of a<br />

government operation. A civil servant, argues Block,<br />

draws hIS annual salary regardless of the<br />

accident toll piled up under his domain. But<br />

1 f hewer e apr 1 vat e own e r 0 f the r 08 d .<br />

then he would indeed lose out if his road<br />

com p i led a poor sa f e t y r e cor d. . . He wo u 1d<br />

then have every incentive to try to reduce<br />

281


accidents, whether by technologIcal innovations,<br />

better rules of th'e road, improved<br />

methods of selecting out drunken <strong>and</strong> other<br />

undesirable drivers, etc.(14)<br />

I n b r i e f, far fro rn rna king d r i v i n g rn 0 r e ha z a r dous, the<br />

1 ibertarian believes that private roads would result in<br />

a substantial reduction in death <strong>and</strong> injury tolls.<br />

Such is the libertarian proposal for a privately<br />

run road system. What can be said in the way of evaluation?<br />

First, the fact that private roads flourished<br />

in eighteenth century Engl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> in nineteenth century<br />

United <strong>State</strong>s until they were nationalized by the governrnent,(15)<br />

does not, in itself, demonstrate their<br />

pract ical ity or desirability today. In the nineteenth<br />

century l<strong>and</strong> was open <strong>and</strong> could be obtained rather<br />

cheaply. Today, however, it is neither open nor cheap.<br />

Second, since there can be only a limited number of<br />

r 0 ute s bet weenan y two po i n t s the a b iii t Y 0 f compe t i ­<br />

t ion t 0 ins u reI ow prices<strong>and</strong> h i gh qualit Y s e r vicererna<br />

ins somewhat quest ionable. Next, the response of the<br />

libertarian moralist to the problems of eminent domain,<br />

wh i len 0 ton I yin g e n i 0 usa n d bas i c a I I Y sou nd, rna y<br />

nevertheless be overly optimistic. Would it really be<br />

as simple as libertarians apparently feel either to<br />

meet the dem<strong>and</strong> of everyone whose home lay in the path<br />

of some future road or to circumvent the problem of the<br />

individual holdout by merely building over, under or<br />

around hIm? Whether or not a system of private roads<br />

co u I d pro v ide sol uti ons tothesediff i cui tie s r ema ins<br />

to be seen. Yet, on balance, the libertarian has acquitted<br />

himself well. In trying to determine whether<br />

or not an anarchist society could work, we must focus<br />

not so much on its desirability as its feasibility.<br />

Thus, even if the elimination of eminent domain would<br />

in fact raise the cost of road construction, this could<br />

place its desirability in question, even though such a<br />

system would still be feasible. And while a private<br />

road system may not be quite as desirable as the libertarian<br />

depicts it, he has, I believe, been able to demonstrate<br />

Its feasibility.<br />

2. EDUCATION<br />

Libertarians oppose compUlsory state education for<br />

a number of reasons:<br />

1. PubliC educat ion is viewed as a very dangerous<br />

Instrument by which the state is able to seize control<br />

282


3. For the natural rights advocate public school<br />

i s i mm0 r a I for a n add i t iona I r e'a son :. "i t de p r i vesthe<br />

tax victims of' their right to their entire income."(22)<br />

4. Finally, libertarians believe that public<br />

schooling invariably engenders social conflict. The<br />

government must make decisions concerning the st<strong>and</strong>ards<br />

<strong>and</strong> curricula of "its" schools. Regardless of how the<br />

decisions are made, i.e., whether they are democratic<br />

or not, the fact remains that the decisions become the<br />

policy of all the schools within the government's juri<br />

s die t ion. Con s e qu e n t I y, wh enthere are no a I t erna ­<br />

t i ves to the state, parents can obtain the type of education<br />

they want for their children only by grabbing<br />

control of the school board <strong>and</strong> imposing their personal<br />

preferences on everyone's children by making them the<br />

official government pol icy. Hence, we are daily met<br />

with conflicts over busing, sex education, school prayers,<br />

liberal versus vocational education, relevance in<br />

the cur ric u 1 urn, etc. But i nthe a bsen s e 0 f com pu Iso r y<br />

state education these controversies would disappear,<br />

for a wide variety of educational alternatives would<br />

pre sen t thems e I veson the f r e e rna r ke t • Eve r yone, libertarians<br />

feel, could then purchase the type of educat<br />

i on he des ired wi thout inter fer ing wi th the right of<br />

others to obtain the type of education they desired.<br />

Before one can discuss the type of educational<br />

system advocated by libertarians, two things should be<br />

noted. First, they deny that anyone has a "right to an<br />

education." As we have seen earlier,(23) libertarian<br />

moral ists believe that rights, by definition, inhere in<br />

the nature of man. They are universal <strong>and</strong> timeless,<br />

i.e., they belong to all men irrespective of the circumstances<br />

prevailing at anyone time or place. To<br />

"speak of a 'right' as something which can only be fulfilled<br />

in modern industrial conditions," they contend,<br />

"is not to speak of a human, natural right at all."<br />

Since schooling is just such a good it is "not embedded<br />

in the nature of man, but requires for its fulfillment<br />

the existence of a group of exploited people who are<br />

coerced into providing such a 'right'."(24) Second,<br />

libertarians maintain a sharp distinction between<br />

schooling <strong>and</strong> education. Education is seen as a lifelong<br />

process. "When the child plays or listens to<br />

parents or friends, or reads a newspaper, or works at a<br />

job, he 0 r she i s be com i n g e d u cat e d . n ( 2 5 ) For rna ]<br />

school ing is seen as only one part of one's education<br />

<strong>and</strong> for some, such as those who are good with their<br />

h<strong>and</strong>s but who have little or no interest in Shake-<br />

284


speare, calculus or political theory, not only is formal<br />

schooling a minimum part of their education, it may<br />

wei Ire tar d the ired u cat ion a Ide vel 0 pme n t . Art h u r<br />

Stinchcombe, for example, notes that much of the current<br />

schooling is useless for both the student <strong>and</strong> pros<br />

pee t i veemp loye r • " Em p loye r s con c erne d wit h securi n g<br />

reI iable workers may require high school diplomas as<br />

evidence of good discipline," he says. "Otherwise they<br />

can train workers better <strong>and</strong> cheaper than a high school<br />

can, on the job."(26)<br />

What is the libertarian proposal? Very simply,<br />

they argue that education should "be an entirely private<br />

affair." Insofar as there is a dem<strong>and</strong> for education<br />

this would be met on the market just like any othe<br />

r d e man d • But permit ting e d ucat ion tog0 c omme r cia I ,<br />

they believe, would entail a number of consequences.<br />

First, competition between schools to attract customers<br />

would mean innovation in the curriculum as well<br />

as a variety of alternatives. The current conflicts<br />

over such issues as segregated or integrated, liberal<br />

o r v 0 cat iona 1 s c h00 I s wo u I d be sol ved i f eve r yon e cou I d<br />

purchase the type, quality, <strong>and</strong> quantity of education<br />

he or she desired. Those who wanted vocational educat<br />

ion C 0 u I d 0 b t a i nit 0 nthe rna r k e t wit h 0 utimp e ding the<br />

a b iii t Y 0 f tho sewhod e sir e ali be r a I ed uca t ion from<br />

acquiring it for themselves.(27)<br />

Second, since those who received the service would<br />

be paying for it, the only ones in school would be<br />

those who wanted to learn or, for those who were still<br />

living with their parents, those whose parents felt<br />

they should learn. This, they feel, would all but<br />

el iminate the discipline problems prevalent in today's<br />

publ ic schools. As one libertarian wag remarked at the<br />

h e i g h, t 0 f the studen t rio t s 0 f the 19 60 ' S, n nob0 dyev e r<br />

sits in at Berlitz."(28)<br />

T h i r d, sin c e bus i n e sse s can not a f for d to bor e<br />

their customers or turn out shoddy merch<strong>and</strong>ise, libertarians<br />

feel that there would be a strong pecuniary<br />

inc en t i v e for teachers to prepare good, interest in g<br />

lectures. This would mean that the tenure or status<br />

or ientation of the teaching profession would be replaced<br />

by an ability orientation. Those who could not<br />

teach well, i. e .. were unable to provide their customers<br />

with a high quality service, would soon find themselves<br />

with no students <strong>and</strong> thus no job in the teaching<br />

profess Ion. (29) As Scot t Bixler notes, "the govern-<br />

285


ment expert has no incentive to really care about his<br />

'clients,' as he is paid regardless, whereas the private<br />

expert has every conceivable incentive to look out<br />

for his elientts interest."(30)<br />

Not 0 n I y dol i be r tar ians believethat compet i t ion<br />

among schools would raise the quality of education,<br />

they believe it would also force the schools to operate<br />

more efficiently, thereby reducing the cost of education.<br />

Increasing government funding has placed public<br />

school ing in a virtual monopolistic position vis-a-vis<br />

private educational institutions. It is not surprising<br />

t hat pub 1 i esc h 0 0 1 s h a v e per formedin the rna nne r 0 f<br />

other protected monopolies: costs have risen while service<br />

has deteriorated. Between 1972 <strong>and</strong> 1977, costs<br />

per pupil rose by 58 percent; professional staff<br />

increased by 8 percent. Our ing the same time, the<br />

number of students declined by four percent. And in<br />

terms of quality, as measured by st<strong>and</strong>ardized tests,<br />

the de c lin e in" e due a t iona lou t put U wa s fa r g rea t e r •<br />

Thus, the increasing monopolization <strong>and</strong> centralization<br />

of the education industry has produced increasing inputs<br />

<strong>and</strong> declining outputs.(31)<br />

Lib e r tar ian s a Iso not e t hat i tis p rima r i I Y the<br />

chi Idren of upper <strong>and</strong> middle income families who attend<br />

pUblic universities <strong>and</strong> colleges. Children of poor<br />

parents tend to enter the work force. Since they begin<br />

paying taxes, part of which goes to subsidize public<br />

e d u cat ion, thereisan e t t ran s fer tota x mo n e y from<br />

the poor to the rich. To make matters worse, college<br />

graduates tend to earn more in their lifetime than noncollege<br />

graduates. Thus, the low-sk i lIed poor are<br />

taxed to pay for the training of the wealthy, who are<br />

then able to use this training to perpetuate their posit<br />

ion i nth e soc i 0 - e con om i chi era r c hy . ( 32 ) For t his<br />

reason libertarians feel that while reducing overall<br />

costs for everyone commercial education would be especially<br />

beneficial for the poor. But what if the family<br />

were still too poor to provide for a child's education?<br />

Wollstein points out that<br />

There are numerous possible solutions to such<br />

a problem which do not involve coercion: [1]<br />

the parents could take out a lon.g-term loan,<br />

[ 2] fro m h i g h s c h 0 a I on, the son co u I d wo r k<br />

part-time, [3] schools might take the boyan<br />

as a charity case (as private physicians took<br />

on poor patients as charity cases before<br />

Medicare), [4] the boy mIght sign a contract<br />

286


probablility of better overall results for children<br />

u n d e r the f r e e e d ucat iona I s ystem seemscI ear • I tis,<br />

after all, the parents of this or that child who will<br />

make the decision for the welfare of the child. These<br />

may not be excellent or even responsible at all times;<br />

but the relationship between parent <strong>and</strong> child, character<br />

ized at least by affection <strong>and</strong> some sense or a feeling<br />

of responsibility on the parents' part, has a good<br />

c hanceo f res u 1 tingin ma x i mum per sona I con c ern 0 ve r<br />

education."(35)<br />

Libertarians have presented an excellent case for<br />

the overall superiority of voluntary, private education<br />

over compulsory, public schooling. But such superiorit<br />

y doe s not, init s elf, d em 0 n s t rat e the des ira b iii t Y 0 f<br />

the former. A listing of the possible combinations indicates<br />

that there are two additional alternatives between<br />

the two extremes discussed thus far:<br />

1. CompUlsory public schooling<br />

2. Voluntary public schooling<br />

3. Compulsory private schooling, <strong>and</strong><br />

4. Voluntary private schooling.<br />

What of the second alternative, that of schooling<br />

provided by the state but which was voluntary, in that<br />

pa r en t s cou I d -- so long as they were able to bear the<br />

additional expense -- send their children to private<br />

schools, or keep them out of school altogether? From a<br />

libertarian point of view, its voluntarism would make<br />

its up e rio r to com p u Isorye d u cat ion. Bu t since i t<br />

would continue to be provided through taxes, it would<br />

still be considered immoral. Beyond this obvious<br />

point, the need to "lure" children into the pUblic<br />

schools would probably increase the variety <strong>and</strong> quality<br />

of education. But how significant this would be is<br />

diffIcult to tell. Real competition in the "educational<br />

industry" would be mitigated by the fact that parents<br />

desiring to send their children to a private inst<br />

i tut ion would have to pay twice: directly, to the<br />

private institution at the point of service, <strong>and</strong> indirectly,<br />

to the public institution, through taxes.<br />

This, of course, would render competition from private<br />

institutions rather feeble. Thus, the only viable alternat<br />

ive to state schooling would be no schooling. It<br />

is likely therefore, that the concern on the part of<br />

public educators with the variety <strong>and</strong> quality of their<br />

education offerings would probably not be noticeably<br />

increased by a policy of voluntary, public education.<br />

288


What of the other option of making schooling compulsory<br />

but private? The voucher plan, where students<br />

would be given educational vouchers by the state to be<br />

redeemed at the school of their choosing, is the best<br />

known variant of this option. From the libertarian<br />

point of view the requirement of compulsory education<br />

would clearly render it unacceptable. But one of the<br />

mer its 0 f the program, i tis c omm 0 n I y thought, i s t hat<br />

the voucher would insure education which was responsive<br />

tot h e des ires 0 f the studen t s - - 0 r pa r en t s - - rat her<br />

than the pUbl i c author it ies. Those schools offering<br />

the best educational programs would get the bulk of the<br />

vouchers <strong>and</strong> thus make the most money. Thus, the compe<br />

tit i on between school s wou ld enhance the qual i ty <strong>and</strong><br />

variety of education. This argument is indeed dubious.<br />

It seems unlikely that the state would long permit<br />

vouchers to be redeemed anywhere. Rather, it is<br />

likely that a voucher program would include the stipulation<br />

that the vouchers would be redeemable only at<br />

those schools meet ing certain requirements -- educational<br />

<strong>and</strong> social -- <strong>and</strong>/or only at those schools located<br />

in the school district in which one lived. But<br />

wi th such restrictions there would certainly be little<br />

room for educational competition <strong>and</strong> without such<br />

competition there would ·be little incentive to increase<br />

the quality <strong>and</strong> variety of their educational<br />

programs.(36)<br />

Libertarians feel that the current system of comp<br />

u Iso r y <strong>and</strong> s tat e - sup p 0 r ted s c h 0 0 lis i mm 0 r a Ion two<br />

co u n t s • Fir s t, com p u Iso r y s c h 001 in g i s v i ewed a s a<br />

form of involuntary servitude, <strong>and</strong> second, "free" pub­<br />

I ic education is a violation of the rights of those who<br />

are taxed to pay for it. Further, they believe that a<br />

private voluntary educational system would be able to<br />

funish high quality education at a lower cost than any<br />

alternative.<br />

While the results of voluntary private education<br />

may not be everything that the libertarian expects, the<br />

argument is cogently presented <strong>and</strong> the proposal strikes<br />

·me as not only feasible but probably desirable as well.<br />

3. OCCUPATIONAL LICENSING<br />

Limiting the number of individuals or groups who<br />

can en t era par tic u I a r fie I d res u Its, I i be r tar ian s<br />

argue, in rigidity, inefficiency, <strong>and</strong> higher rices.<br />

But, even more importantly, since licensing enta Is the<br />

use of government violence against anyone ende voring<br />

289


to ···enter a lIcensed field without government permission,<br />

libertarians see it as violating natural law by<br />

employing violence to prevent nonaggressive actions of<br />

other individuals. In fact, occupational licensing is<br />

seen as a return to a type of guild system similar to<br />

that of the feudal period,(37) <strong>and</strong> libertarians call<br />

for the removal of all forms of government regulations,<br />

from the licensing of occupations to the prohibition of<br />

private drug use.(38)<br />

The moral issue aside, the practical problem with<br />

go v ernmen t lieens i ng i s t hat wh e the r i t wa s 0 rig ina I I Y<br />

implemented to regulate industry for the benefit of the<br />

consumer or was established to benefit entrepreneurs by<br />

shielding them from competition is irrelevant. Since<br />

the interest of "the public" is diverse <strong>and</strong> diffuse it<br />

is unable to focus its interests on any particular<br />

pro b I emf 0 r a sus t a i ned per i 0 d 0 f time • On the 0 the r<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, the interest of an industry is "direct <strong>and</strong> focused."<br />

The automobile industry, for example, has a dir<br />

e et<strong>and</strong> i mme d iate in t eres tin the dec i s ion S 0 f the Environmental<br />

Protection Agency. But individual members<br />

of the pUblic are affected only minimally. Hence, the<br />

automobile industry would be willing to devote much<br />

time <strong>and</strong> energy to influence the agency's decisions<br />

while the "public" will not. Moreover, since an agency<br />

cannot make decisions concerning the industry it regulates<br />

unless it possesses knOWledge about that industry,<br />

the agency officials must either be drawn from the<br />

very industries they regulate or develop close contacts<br />

with those in the industry. It is hardly surprising,<br />

notes economist Milton Friedman, that the regulatory<br />

" 0 r g ani z a t ion s h a v e beeom e the s e r van t s 0 f thosethey<br />

were supposed to protect the public from."(39) Walter<br />

Gellhorn, in fact, estimates that<br />

Seventy-five percent of the occupational<br />

licensing boards at work in this country<br />

today are composed exclusively of licensed<br />

practitioners in the respective occupations.<br />

The s e men <strong>and</strong> worn en, m0 S t 0 f wh am are 0 n I y<br />

part-time officials, may have a direct economic<br />

interest in many of the decisions they<br />

make concerning admiSSIon requirements <strong>and</strong><br />

the defInition of st<strong>and</strong>ards to be observed by<br />

licensees. More importantly they are as a<br />

rule directly representative of organized<br />

groups WIthin the occupations.(40)<br />

290


h<strong>and</strong>, these delays have caused 21,000 to 120,000 additional<br />

deaths during the same time period. Thus, on<br />

balance FDA regulations have resulted in between 4 <strong>and</strong><br />

12 deaths for every life saved.(44)<br />

In other areas, a recent study of the effects of<br />

the ban on adver tis ing prescr i ption drugs, which is<br />

universally supported by the retail pharmacists' organizations,<br />

revealed that prices in -the 34 regulated<br />

states were 5.2 percent higher than in the 16 non-regulated<br />

states, <strong>and</strong> may cost consumers as much as $380<br />

mi II i on per year. (45) Another study, by Thomas Gale<br />

Moore of Stanford University, indicated that various<br />

reg u I a t ion s 0 f the I n t e r s tat e Comm e r ce Comm iss ion,<br />

which are supported by both the American Trucking Associat<br />

ion <strong>and</strong> the Teamsters Union, may cost consumers $16<br />

billion a year.(46) And a study of television repair<br />

Ii cens ingby the Federal Trade Commission, which compar<br />

e d Lou i s ian a, wh i c h has rna nda tor y I icensing, wit h<br />

California, which requires registration without restrictions<br />

on the number of people registered, <strong>and</strong> the<br />

District of Columbia, with no controls, revealed that<br />

pr ices in Louisiana were a full 20 percent higher than<br />

in ei ther Cal i fornia or the District of Co!umbia.(47)<br />

And independent studies have estimated that licensing<br />

restrictions <strong>and</strong> other government regUlations cost the<br />

consumers $130 billion per year.(48) Clearly, says the<br />

libertarian in responding to these kinds of studies,<br />

the effect of regulations is not to reduce prices for<br />

the benefit of consumers but, on the contrary, to raise<br />

them for the benefit of the industries.<br />

The 1 i ber ta r ian feels, therefore, that government<br />

regUlation works to the benefit of the very industries<br />

being regulated. And since there is a natural tendency<br />

for the wealthy to use their wealth to obtain political<br />

power, he is skeptical of proposals to reform the regulatory<br />

commissions for the benefit of the poor. While<br />

such reforms might prove successful in the very short<br />

run, the bel iefthat s uchastit ua t ion can bema i n t a i n ­<br />

ed is akin to believing that water can run uphill. The<br />

interests of consumers, Milton Friedman notes, "are diverse<br />

<strong>and</strong> diffuse. You buy a thous<strong>and</strong> things, but you<br />

make your living producing a single product...When<br />

the chips are down, your willingness to promote your<br />

interest as a consumer of a thous<strong>and</strong> things will be far<br />

less than your willingness to engage in something that<br />

wi 11 promote your interest as a producer." Consequent­<br />

1y, areg u 1a tor y c omm iss ion may bees tab 1ishe d wit h the<br />

intent ion of protecting the consumers. But, "after the<br />

292


initial, faddish interest in the project dies down, the<br />

producers will move in with pressure for exemptions <strong>and</strong><br />

other special rulings."(49) The libertarian, therefore,<br />

opposes all regulation not only on moral but on<br />

practical grounds as well.<br />

But how would the market be able to protect the<br />

interests of the consumers in the absence of regulation?<br />

Libertarians believe that there are any number<br />

of noncoercive ways that this could be h<strong>and</strong>led. First,<br />

Hospers points out that a company's good name is its<br />

best guarantee of its future business. Businessmen are<br />

no more inherently trustworthy or honest than any other<br />

soc i a 1 g r 0 up. But the f r e e rna r ke t p I acesam0 net a r y<br />

inc e n t i veon h 0 nest y • Chea ting rna y res u Itin ash0 r t ­<br />

term gain, but a company that incurs a reputation for<br />

c h eat i n g its pa t ron s wi I Iso0 n fin d itself wit h 0 utany<br />

patrons <strong>and</strong>, thus, going out of business. Since the<br />

market works to reward honesty <strong>and</strong> penalize dishonesty,<br />

it is believed that a totally free market would actually<br />

serve to raise rather thanWlower st<strong>and</strong>ards.(SO)<br />

It is also likely that a laissez faire society<br />

w0 u 1 d g i v e r i set 0 m0 rema g a z i n e s s u chas Cons ume r<br />

Rep 0 r t s, pro v i din g sub s c rib e r s .wit h i n for rna t ion 0 n<br />

eve r y t h i n g fro m the qua lit Y 0 f pa r ticu Iarbr<strong>and</strong> s 0 f<br />

safety pins to individual physicians. While certainly<br />

not a I 1, 0 rev e n m0 s t, w0 uIdsubs c ribe t 0 s u c h rna ga ­<br />

zines, economists such as Friedman contend that even<br />

the careless shopper would be better protected in the<br />

absence of government controls. "Producers," he says,<br />

work on a margin, like everybody else. If<br />

the five percent of shoppers who are carefUl<br />

spot a clever misrepresentation, they'll<br />

leave the store. That's enough pressure on<br />

the store owner. The infrequent shopper<br />

assumes this when he goes to a store that's<br />

popular. There has to be a reason for its<br />

popularity, he decides. The reason is that<br />

it appeals to those who are very carefUl<br />

about measures <strong>and</strong> labels <strong>and</strong> that sort of<br />

thing.(Sl)<br />

There are other devices by which consumers would<br />

be able to protect themselves. While anyone in a libertarIan<br />

society would be able to enter any occupation<br />

he desires, includIng those of physician <strong>and</strong> lawyer,<br />

libertarians do not regard this as a problem. First,<br />

the market would insure that only the most competent<br />

293


ter to indirect exchange when individuals begin to<br />

realize that they can facilitate their ability to exchange<br />

for goods they desIre by first obtaining goods<br />

wit h high rna rketabi Ii ty. Consequen t Iy, cer ta i n commodities<br />

emerge spontaneously as a general medium of exchange<br />

as more <strong>and</strong> more individuals begin to dem<strong>and</strong><br />

these goods not so much for their use as consumption<br />

goods but for their use in facilitating exchange. Eventually,<br />

this second use becomes dominant, <strong>and</strong> the commod<br />

i t Y comes to be dem<strong>and</strong>ed almost solely for its use<br />

as a general medium of exchange.(55)<br />

What kind 0 f goods wi 1 1 emerge as mo ne y has va r i e d<br />

from soc i e t y t 0 soc i e t y ? S ome a gricu 1t ur a Isoc i e ties<br />

have used cows; fishing societies have used fishhooks<br />

or seashells, etc. But generally metals, <strong>and</strong> in particuI<br />

a r gold <strong>and</strong> s i I ver, ha ve pre va i led for a n urn be r 0 f<br />

reasons. They are durable, fairly portable, <strong>and</strong> highly<br />

divisible. All of these greatly facilitate exchange.<br />

Whi Ie the state, whether for purposes of obtaining easy<br />

revenue or to protect society from fraud, has gradually<br />

assumed a monopoly on the issue of money -- the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s government, in fact, did not finally prohibit<br />

private coinage until 1863(56) -- the important point<br />

i s t hat m0 neyemer g e d s pon tane 0 us I Y from the rna r k e t .<br />

Libertar ians note that some economists even contend<br />

that it was impossible for the state to create money by<br />

declaring some good legal tender <strong>and</strong> ordering the public<br />

to accept it. "It IS not the <strong>State</strong>, but the common<br />

practice of all those who have dealings in the market,<br />

that creates money," says LUdwig <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>. "It follows<br />

t hat S tatereg u 1a t Ion a t t ributi n g g e nera I powe r 0 f<br />

deb t - 1 i qui d a t ion t 0 a c omm 0 d i t Y i suna bleofit s elf t 0<br />

make that commodity into money."(57)<br />

1fthestate wa s not r e qui rOe d to br i ng mo neyin to<br />

e xis ten c e, ne i the r isit ne c e s sa r y topres e r ve it. Go vernment<br />

control over the monetary system leads to at<br />

least two very serious problems. First, since money is<br />

the n e r veeen t e r 0 f the en t ire e con omy, the libe r tar ian<br />

believes that if "the state is able to gain unquestioned<br />

control over the unIt of all accounts, the state<br />

wi II then be in a position to dominate the entire system,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the whole society.n(5S) And second, if any<br />

one person or institution such as the government can<br />

obtain control over the supply of money, there IS nothing<br />

to prevent It from using this control to add to its<br />

wealth simply by printing new money. There is, they<br />

contend, no real difference between the printing of<br />

new money by the government. <strong>and</strong> the activities of a<br />

296


counterfei ter. Both act ivi ties reduce the value of<br />

the monetary unit by increasing its supply. The effect<br />

in both cases is to transfer purchaSing power from all<br />

other members of society to the government or the count<br />

e r f e i t e r. Not 0 n I y i s t his not h i n g moret han the f t ,<br />

but, they argue, it reduces popular control over government<br />

by enabling the government to exp<strong>and</strong> its expenditures,<br />

<strong>and</strong> thus the scope of its activities, without<br />

first having to obtain popular consent for increasing<br />

taxes. (59 )<br />

The individualist anarchist chides those individuals,<br />

such as the members of the Chicago School, who advocate<br />

freedom of competition for nearly all goods<br />

except money. One argument in favor or a government<br />

money monopoly is that money can fulfill its function<br />

as a med i urn of exchange only so long as it is scarce.<br />

Since money can be printed at practically no cost, free<br />

compet it ion would lead to hyper-inflation. Thus the<br />

supply of money must be governmentally controlled to<br />

prevent the breakdown of the monetary system.<br />

It is admitted that free banking in a monetary<br />

system based on paper would lead to its destruction.<br />

Yet, this is precisely what most libertarians <strong>and</strong> all<br />

individualist anarchists desire. Not only does a paper<br />

system require government control but, since its supply<br />

can be so easily Increased, it is seen as the cause of<br />

the t r ad e eye Ie. F r e e ban king wo u 1dIead tothereemergence<br />

of "natural" money, i.e., one that spontaneous<br />

1y emerged from the market process. Because of such<br />

a d van tage s 0 r s carcit y, d i vis i b iIi t y, po r tabiii t y, d u r ­<br />

abi 1 i ty <strong>and</strong> homogeneity this would almost certainly be<br />

gold <strong>and</strong>/or silver. Since it is difficult <strong>and</strong> costly<br />

to dig these metals out of the ground their supplies<br />

could not, like those of paper, be increased at will.<br />

Thus, not only would their values be stabilized <strong>and</strong> secure<br />

but the prospect of inflation <strong>and</strong> depression would<br />

be greatly reduced.<br />

Far from leadIng to perpetual inflation free banking<br />

would, they argue, actually lead to a much sounder<br />

monetary system than we now have. "Suppose that I decided<br />

to ab<strong>and</strong>on the slow, difficult process of produc­<br />

Ing services for money, or of mining money, <strong>and</strong> instead<br />

deCIded to print my own," hypothesizes Rothbard.<br />

What w0 u 1 d P r 1 n t ? I mig h t rna n u fa c t urea<br />

paper ticket, <strong>and</strong> pr int upon it "10<br />

Rot h bar d s . II I co u 1d the n procIa 1m the tiC ke t<br />

297


In shor t, 1 i ber tar ians do not bel ieve that money<br />

requires thesuper.vision of government. Far from free<br />

banking leading to hyper-inflation, the libertarian bel<br />

ieves that the reverse is true. The money monopoly,<br />

says James Rolph Edwards, "has the defect of all monopolies,<br />

that one must use their product even if it is<br />

unsatisfactory." It is only with "currency substitution·,"<br />

i.e., competition between alternative monies,<br />

that "money of stable <strong>and</strong> reliable value" can be<br />

insured.(63)<br />

Since private mipters could not force people to<br />

use their money, they could stay in business only by<br />

developing a reputation for honesty. The more sterling<br />

one's reputation the more willing individuals would be<br />

to use a minter's coins or a printer's certificates.<br />

The lib e r tar ian poi n t s to his tor y to bo1st e r his ca s e •<br />

Private coins circulated widely throughout the world,<br />

inclUding this country. During the Civil War, for example,<br />

the federal government took coins out of circulation<br />

to help relieve the metal shortage. This in<br />

turn produced a shortage of coins, which was alleviated<br />

by the appearance of private mint-masters. It is reported<br />

that possibly 10,000 varieties of private coins<br />

circulated during this time. In the 1830's an individual<br />

named Christopher Bechtler entered the minting<br />

business <strong>and</strong> within nine years minted nearly two <strong>and</strong><br />

one-half million dollars. HIS coins received such wide<br />

circulation that as late as 1920 the Bechtler dollars<br />

were st ill be ing accepted in parts of this country at<br />

par with "official money."(64)<br />

Finall y, how rna nycur r en c i e s w0 u I d beex pe c ted t 0<br />

e mer g e ? Lib e r tar ian sadmit t hat therei s no wa y t 0<br />

know for sure. But given the transaction costs inherent<br />

in currency conversions, Edwards argues that the<br />

"public would not permit more than three or four currencies<br />

to circulate widely at anyone time."(65)<br />

Wha t can be sa i d abou t such a proposal? At the<br />

least, it is certainly ingenious. But is it pure fantasy?<br />

I think not. Not only is the argument presented<br />

logically but a wealth of historical examples are also<br />

introduced to demonstrate its feasibility. But quest<br />

ion sst i I I r ems in. W0 u 1d the con c ern for 0 ne 's reputation<br />

be enough to prevent fraud, or at least hold it<br />

to a minimum? To this the libertarian might respond<br />

that whatever fraud would occur would no doubt be less<br />

than that perpetuated by the government through its<br />

dollar monopoly. And is fra·ctional-reserve banking<br />

299


i n her en t I Y f r a u d u 1en t, as the lib e r tar ian rno r ali s t<br />

claims? What if banks frankly told their customers<br />

'8 b 0 u t the i r fr act iona I - res e r ve p r act ice, inc 1 uding its<br />

advantages -- such as no fee for deposits -- <strong>and</strong> its<br />

disadvantages -- such as a remote possibility that one<br />

might not be able to redeem one's deposit in an economicc<br />

r i sis? Solong a s a ban k f rank I Y a dm itte d its<br />

practice, I do not see how it can be accused of fraudulent<br />

behavior. And if consumers desired such a policy,<br />

I do not see how libertarians could prevent the market<br />

from supplying it. But this is a minor point. The<br />

libertarian proposal for the deregulation of money is<br />

convincing.<br />

5. EOOLOGY<br />

Libertarians believe that an adequate solution to<br />

the problems of pollution <strong>and</strong> conservation can be found<br />

only in a system of universal private property.<br />

a. Pollution.<br />

Pollut ion may be defined as "the transfer of harmful<br />

matter or energy to the person or property of another<br />

without the latter's consent."(66)<br />

Government has considered certain types of property<br />

as too important to be privately owned. It ha,s designated<br />

these areas as "public property" <strong>and</strong> assumed<br />

control over them. Lake Erie as well as Lake Baikal In<br />

the S 0 vie tUn ion are "pubi i c I y own e d . " R i ve r s, too,<br />

are owned by the "public" as is air space. And it is<br />

pre cis ely i nth e sea rea s t ha t we s u f fer from rna s s i ve<br />

<strong>and</strong> harmful poll ut ion. Conversely, one does not find<br />

i n d i v i d u a I s po I I uti ng e i the r the i r own 0 r the i r ne ighbor's<br />

property. This is so, libertarians contend, because"<br />

in the normal course of events, an individual<br />

finds it much easier <strong>and</strong> more rational to protect<br />

things which he owns, rather than things he does not<br />

own."(67) Libertarians therefore seek the solution to<br />

the pollution problem in the extension of individual<br />

pro per t y rig h t sintot h 0 seareasin wh i c h they are now<br />

denied.<br />

Government spawns pollution, they argue, because<br />

the entIre concept of "public property" is a myth. "The<br />

publIC" is merely a hypostatized construct that has no<br />

counterpart in real ity. If the "publ ic" does not<br />

ex i s t, I t can not ow nan y t h i n g . " Pub 1 i c good s II are<br />

actually owned by the offIcials running the government<br />

300


at any particular time. It is the decision of the government<br />

that determines how much or how little pollution<br />

of air <strong>and</strong> water we are to have. But how does the<br />

government arrive at these decisions? The public policy<br />

was to treat air space <strong>and</strong> water as "free goods" unowned<br />

by anyone. Since no one was permitted to own any<br />

particUlar unit of the air space or water, no one had<br />

either the incentive or even the means to prevent any<br />

par tic u 1 a run i t fro m b e i n g des poi led • Con seq ue n t I Yf<br />

sewage of all kinds was disposed of by dumping it into<br />

the wa t e r 0 r byin j e c t i. n g its r ema ins i ntothe air.<br />

But as air <strong>and</strong> water became more polluted, the government,<br />

as owner, eventually altered its policy. Air <strong>and</strong><br />

water were no longer considered "free goods" equally<br />

accessible to all, but were to be regulated by the government<br />

in the "public interest." The question, howe<br />

v e r, ishow mu c h 0 r h ow lit tie po II uti on is in the<br />

" pub lie i n t e re s t " ? The go vernmen t rna y use "sc i en t i f i c<br />

tests" to determine at what level pollution becomes a<br />

heal th hazard <strong>and</strong> then permi t pollut ion up to that<br />

point. But, as important as such studies are, even<br />

t his met hod i s arb i t r a r y . S om e i n d i v i d ua I s rna y be<br />

e s pee i a I 1 Y sensit i vet 0 po 11 uti on <strong>and</strong> wou I d pr e fer a<br />

lower level, while others might prefer a higher level<br />

pr ov i ded it would lead to a higher st<strong>and</strong>ard of 1 i ving.<br />

At the Stockholm Conference in 1972, for example, the<br />

less developed countries made it clear that they would<br />

not t a k e any s t e pst 0 red u c e pol I uti 0 nth a t wo u I d<br />

i n h i bit i n d u s t ria Idevel 0 pm en t . ( 68 ) M0 reov e r, solong<br />

as the decision is made by the government, libertarians<br />

feel that it will be a political decision. Most businesses<br />

are opposed to strict pollution st<strong>and</strong>ards, at<br />

least for their area of operations. And as already<br />

noted there is no reason to believe that the interest<br />

of the "public" will triumph over that of "business."<br />

The interest of the "public" is diffuse <strong>and</strong> often contradictory<br />

while that of "business" is concrete <strong>and</strong><br />

immediate. The automobile manufacturers, for example,<br />

are adversely affected in an immediate <strong>and</strong> concrete way<br />

by the impos it ion of auto-emission st<strong>and</strong>ards, <strong>and</strong> can<br />

be coun t ed on to lobby strongly in oppos i t ion to them.<br />

The "public" may be in favor of such st<strong>and</strong>ards. But<br />

its interests are neither as immediate nor as concrete<br />

a s tho s e 0 f the aut 0 rna n u fa c t u r e r s, <strong>and</strong> i tis un I ike I y<br />

that many individuals would be willing to sacrifice the<br />

time <strong>and</strong> money necessary to effectively counter that<br />

group. And even some of the "public," such as those<br />

who intend to buy new cars <strong>and</strong> would have to pay the<br />

extra cost of the pollution equipment, might oppose<br />

emission st<strong>and</strong>ards altogether. ThIS means, at best,<br />

301


that the government policy would be some sort of<br />

compromise between the interests of the "public" <strong>and</strong><br />

tho s e 0 f' "b u sin e s s • " Itse em s I ike I y, howe ve r, t hat<br />

those of business would gradually emerge dominant.<br />

Libertarians, in short, believe that government<br />

itself is solely responsible for pollution. Its<br />

failure to recognize property rights in water <strong>and</strong> air<br />

spa c e has res u I ted i nth em be i n g t. rea ted a s n f r e e<br />

goods," which meant that since no unit of these goods<br />

would be individually owned or valued, they were abused<br />

<strong>and</strong> wasted, i.e., polluted. And they further argue<br />

that no government can deal effectively with pollution<br />

si nee i nth e a b senceofIn d i v i d ua I owner s hip of air<br />

space <strong>and</strong> water, there is no market in these areas.<br />

Thus the government has no way of determining how the<br />

sup ply 0 f air spac e <strong>and</strong> wa t e r 0 ugh t to be a I I 0 catedt 0<br />

enhance the ut iii ties of all members of society. The<br />

only alternative is to establish arbitrarily a certain<br />

1 eve I 0 f pol I uti 0 n a s the rna x i murn <strong>and</strong> then imp0 s e i t<br />

upon everyone. But since many would be willing to endure<br />

greater amounts in return for such benefits as a<br />

h i g her s tan dar d 0 f I i v i ng, wh i leothe r s wo u I d pre fer a<br />

lower level of pollution, this method satisfies practically<br />

no one.<br />

We do not have a problem of l<strong>and</strong> pollution. A<br />

cannot dump his garbage into B's backyard. It is important<br />

to realize that this is so only because property<br />

rights in l<strong>and</strong> are usually well defined. Once proper<br />

t y rig h t sin air spa c e <strong>and</strong> wa t e r we repe r mit ted,<br />

lib e r tar ian s rna i n t a i ntha t the prob I em 0 f pol I uti 0 n i n<br />

these areas would likewise cease to exist. In a system<br />

of universal private property, A's injection of soot or<br />

noise into the air space of B would be just as much a<br />

violation of the latter's property rights as if A willfully<br />

destroyed B's shrubs by pouring poison on them.<br />

The remedy I ies in the courts upholding the neighbor's<br />

pro p er t y rig h t s by for c i ng t he po I I uter, i. e ., t he inv<br />

a d e r 0 fan 0 the r 's pro per t y, t 0 rna keres tit uti 0 n to<br />

the victim.<br />

The question of how much pollution should exist<br />

would be determined by the actions of each property<br />

owner.(69) Each individual would be free to use his<br />

property as he saw fit but would be responsIble for any<br />

" s p ill 0 v e r" 0 n t 0 a not her's proper t y • Thosewhow0 u I d<br />

be willing to suffer a higher level of pollution in<br />

ex c han g e for m0 net a r y com pensat Ion from the po I 1uti ng<br />

source would be free to do so. Consequently, such<br />

302


<strong>and</strong> therei s nor e a son the Uti lit a ria n wo u I d proh i bit<br />

this. Thus, a firm might enter into an agreement in<br />

which an owner grants the firm the right to pollute his<br />

property above the limit stipulated by the courts in<br />

return for compensation. Or, an individual who felt<br />

the legal limits were too high could pay a firm to keep<br />

its pol I uti 0 n below the lim it. Nurn e r 0 usot her<br />

scenarios are conceivable.<br />

While more complicated, the difficulties such<br />

problems pose for the libertarian moralist are not, I<br />

think, fatal. The application of the Lockean "homes<br />

tea din g a x i om ," viz., t hat un own e d proper t y bel 0 n g s to<br />

its first user, would be instrumental in resol ving many<br />

of the seeming difficulties. "If a town were to spring<br />

up around a remote· paper mi 11, or a new subdivision<br />

were to be built at the end of an airport runway,"<br />

remarks Wi 11 iam Burt, "subdivided properties could be<br />

sold with the contractual underst<strong>and</strong>ing that air or<br />

noise pollution will be tolerated. (Even where this<br />

underst<strong>and</strong>ing was not historically defined in deeds, we<br />

would have to grant that the pollution rights had been<br />

already homesteaded at the time of property sale.)"(71)<br />

This means that a Mr. Clean could not bring the<br />

city to a halt or that a Mr. Slick could not hold it up<br />

for ransom. For, in the absence of clear <strong>and</strong> valid<br />

contractual evidence to the contrary the "pollutIon<br />

rights," as Burt says, "had been already homesteaded at<br />

the tIme of property sale." What Mr. Clean, or Mr.<br />

Slick, could do would be to buy the pollution rights<br />

over his home from the current homesteaders. Thus, if<br />

the A-I Widget Factory were next door, Mr. Clean could<br />

purchase A-I's pollution rights to the space above his<br />

home. This would mean that A-I could no longer pollute<br />

Mr. Clean's proper ty. But another homesteader, the<br />

Acme Frisbee Company located on the other side of Mr.<br />

C I e an' s pro per t y, w 0 u Ids til Ire t a i nit s po I I uti 0 n<br />

rights over that air space until <strong>and</strong> unless it sold<br />

them to :\1r. Clean. In short, air space, or at least<br />

pollution rights to it, would become a commodity just<br />

like l<strong>and</strong>. While it might become customary for air<br />

space <strong>and</strong> l<strong>and</strong> to be sold in one package this would not<br />

be m<strong>and</strong>atory <strong>and</strong> would depend on the particular contractual<br />

arrangements. Thus, one could buy l<strong>and</strong> that<br />

became historically "separated," as it were, from the<br />

air space above it. And just as one is free to purchase<br />

l<strong>and</strong> adjacent to one's property, so one could<br />

purchase the space above one's property as well.<br />

304


There is another method by which such apparently<br />

thorny problems could be h<strong>and</strong>led, viz., that of restrictive<br />

covenants. A convenant is simply an agreement<br />

in which the parties mutually agree to abide by<br />

certain stipulations on the use <strong>and</strong> sale of their l<strong>and</strong>.<br />

The covenant would probably be the most convenient device<br />

for use by owners of new subdivisions, shopping<br />

malls <strong>and</strong> the like. Thus, subdivision owners might<br />

sell their units only to those who agree to respect<br />

certain noise, water or pollution st<strong>and</strong>ards. The<br />

covenant is an extremely flexible device that would<br />

g rea t I Y s imp I i f y the prob I em s 0 f po I I uti 0 n con t r 0 lin a<br />

libertarian society. As Burt points out:<br />

Covenants can also be useful in presenting<br />

a corporate phalanx to the non-consenting<br />

world. A prospective polluter, in the first<br />

place, would have to deal with only one representative<br />

in order to obtain pollution<br />

rights over the covenanted properties. And<br />

this cuts two ways: a group of neighbors who<br />

despise automobile exhaust could Improve<br />

their ability to stop it by organizing into<br />

an "air pollution district" such that when<br />

aut 0 mob i 1 e poIlu t ion inc rea sed they wo u I d<br />

on I y h a vet 0 provet hat s 0 me 0 f them we r e<br />

invaded by fumes.<br />

At the s imp I est I eve Is, covena n t s are<br />

merely bilateral agreements. Inclusion of<br />

more participants may be dem<strong>and</strong>ed to deal<br />

with certain kinds of environmental conflict<br />

(as with the air pollution district), <strong>and</strong><br />

more specificity or elaboration may be<br />

needed to h<strong>and</strong>le subtler kinds of goods. The<br />

latter becomes especially important when the<br />

law recognizes no independent method to establish<br />

simple property in such goods as<br />

"neighborhood character" or other esthetic<br />

values. The peak of inclusion <strong>and</strong> elaboration<br />

is that womb of security, the proprietary<br />

community, wherein management of the<br />

social aspects of living has been left<br />

(either by deed restriction or subsequent<br />

c 0 v e nan t) t 0 ace n t r a I c omm unit y "I <strong>and</strong> lor d ft<br />

who res 0 I v e sal 1 i n te rna 1 envir 0 nmen tal disput<br />

e sout 0 f co u r t . Examp I e s 0 f t his ph en om ­<br />

enon may be seen in huge shopping malls,<br />

hot e I com pIexes, r e c rea t ion a 1 comm unit i e s ,<br />

<strong>and</strong> industrial parks.(72)<br />

305


The foregoing is a highly imaginative approach to<br />

the pro b I e m 0 f pol I uti 0 ncon t r o·}. Wh i I e per haps m0 r e<br />

cumbersome than the more direct regulatory approach<br />

currently in use, it has the advantage of great flexib<br />

iii t Y • And wh i let heli be r tar ian 0 r na t urair i g h t s<br />

approach would be even more complicated than the utilitarian,<br />

its program strikes me as being at least Ceasib<br />

1 e . Wh e the r its compIex i t Y rna kesit des ira blei s<br />

another question. It could well be, however, that<br />

these complexities are exaggerated by the failure to<br />

rea liz e the rna r ketinc e n t i veexis tingin t his cas e for<br />

the simplification of procedures. As Burt says, "we<br />

have every reaSon to expect the system to be only -as<br />

complicated <strong>and</strong> 'utopian' as it needs to be."(73)<br />

b. Conservation.<br />

Lib e r tar ian s a r g u e t hat the prob I em 0 f res 0 u r c e<br />

conservation could be solved in the same way. Richard<br />

<strong>and</strong> Ernestine Perkins argue that universal private property<br />

would create a "cycle of protection." They note<br />

that while such endangered species as seals, birds <strong>and</strong><br />

f ish are i n va ria b I Y f 0 undon governmen t - own e d air, I <strong>and</strong><br />

or wa t e r, ani ma 1sthat are p r i vat ely own e d s uchas<br />

t u r key s, chi c ken s, h 0 r s es, cows, etc., are not inany<br />

danger of extinction. The reason for this is obvious.<br />

Sin c e there co u ] d be no chi eken breeders wi tho u t chi c kens<br />

the owners must make sure that they breed at least<br />

as many as they kill.(74) Universal private property<br />

would permit the extension of the "cycle of poverty"<br />

into many areas in which it is now inoperative. "Baby<br />

seals, as well as many other wild animals whose fur or<br />

meat has commercial value," contend the Perkinses,<br />

would be deliberately <strong>and</strong> scientifically<br />

farmed on a business basis, in the same way<br />

that thous<strong>and</strong>s of chickens <strong>and</strong> turkeys are<br />

raised in farms specializing in their production.<br />

The unreasonable killing of animals,<br />

inclUding birds, whose lives are of value in<br />

the ecologIcal cycle, simply would not occur,<br />

because the property in which they lived<br />

would be privately owned. The owners would<br />

pro tee t the m, jus t as dome s tic ani rna 1s are<br />

protected today. When nearly all such property<br />

is privately owned, there would be as<br />

much chance of reading in the newspapers of<br />

the senseless slaughter of seals, as there is<br />

today of the senseless slaughter of an<br />

English farmer's dairy herd.(75)<br />

306


allocating resources between current <strong>and</strong> future uses.<br />

If forests were privately owned, <strong>and</strong> a lumber shortage<br />

was expected the forest owners would have every incent<br />

i v e bot h toeur t a i I theireur r en t produe t ion 0 f I urn be r<br />

<strong>and</strong> to plant more trees in the expectation of selling<br />

at a higher price in the future. These activities<br />

would benefit consumers <strong>and</strong> conserve resources. On the<br />

other h<strong>and</strong>, if lumber was becoming very plentiful or<br />

wa s to be replaced in the near future by another rna terial,<br />

the forest owners would rush to produce as much<br />

lumber now, when it would still be of some value, as<br />

they could. Hence, notes Rothbard, "the market economy<br />

contains a marvelous built-in mechanism whereby the<br />

resource owner's decision on present against future<br />

produe t ion w i I I bene fit not 0 n I y the i r own incom e <strong>and</strong><br />

we a 1 t h, but a Iso t hat 0 f the rna s s 0 f cons ume r s<strong>and</strong> 0 f<br />

the national <strong>and</strong> world economy."(77)<br />

Economist E. J. Mishan argues that there cannot be<br />

proper ty rights in air <strong>and</strong> water because, in contrast<br />

to l<strong>and</strong>, "they do not take on physically identifiable<br />

forms."(78) But the libertarians do not believe that<br />

t his i s a s e rious, prob I em . Fir s t, they poi n t 0 u t t hat<br />

many goods now on the free market do not have identiflabl<br />

e forms. Music is one; ownership of radio frequenc<br />

i es is anot her. And second, t hey note tha t modern<br />

technological advances such as electronic fencing have<br />

faci Ii tated the development of property rights in these<br />

areas.<br />

Whether Mishan is correct cannot really be decided<br />

un til the e f for tis rna de to devel 0 p proper t y righ t sin<br />

these areas. It should be remembered that prior to the<br />

d eve lopmen t 0 f pro per t y righ t sin I<strong>and</strong>, itt00 wa s a<br />

" col lee t i ve goo d • " Its e ems 1 ike 1y tome t hat sueh<br />

problems are solvable by the universal private property<br />

approach. But this merely means that it is one possible<br />

method for dealing with the problems of pollution<br />

control <strong>and</strong> conservation. It does not mean that it is<br />

the best or most desirable approach. It could be that<br />

its complexities would make it less convenient than<br />

direct regUlation. On the other h<strong>and</strong>, its greater<br />

fie x i b iii t yeo u I d rna ke t his a p pr oa c h qui teef fie i en t .<br />

But these issues cannot be settled so long as the government<br />

policy is to arrogate to itself ownership <strong>and</strong><br />

control of air space <strong>and</strong> water.<br />

6. PUBLIC UTILITIES<br />

How would "public utilities" such as gas, electricity,-<br />

water, sewage dIsposal, <strong>and</strong> telephones, be han-<br />

308


a1 either market or non-market -- means of providing<br />

such services.<br />

After an extensive search for goods that are inherently<br />

public or collective, ranging from insect cont<br />

r 0 1 top 0 I ice pro t e c t ion, co u r t s, pa r ks, r 0 ads <strong>and</strong><br />

eve n nat ion a Ide fen s e, e conom i s t Kennet h Go I din con ­<br />

c 1 ude d t hat ff caseaf t e r cas e, a 1thoug h in i t i a 1 I Y P Iausible<br />

has failed to fit the framework of public goods<br />

theory." The evidence suggests, he continued,<br />

that we are not faced with a set of goods<br />

<strong>and</strong> services which have the inherent charact<br />

e r i s tic s 0 f pub 1 i ego 0 d s • Ra ther, we are<br />

faced with an unavoidable choice regarding<br />

eve r y goo d 0 r s e r vic e: s ha lIeve r yon e ha ve<br />

e qua I ace esst 0 the s e r vice (i n wh i c h ca s e<br />

the s e r vice will bes i milart0 a pu b I i c good)<br />

or shall the service be available selective­<br />

1y: t 0 s 0 me, but no t too the r s ? In pr a ct<br />

ice, publ i c goods theory is often used in<br />

such a way that one overlooks this important<br />

cho ice problem. Often it is suggested that a<br />

c e r t a ins e r vic e i s a pub lie good. And on ce<br />

this suggestion is made, it is usually<br />

assumed that the service must be equally<br />

available to everyone. But this is seriously<br />

misleading as, in general, equal access to<br />

government services is neither necessary nor<br />

efficient.(81)<br />

Lighthouses, Goldin points out, are often considered<br />

a "textbook example" of a public good, simply<br />

because "economists cannot imagine a method of exclusion."<br />

But lighthouse owners have been routinely doing<br />

the unimaginabLe for years. Since lighthouse users<br />

mus tal so be harbor users, one method has been to make<br />

harbor use contingent upon the payment of lighthouse<br />

fee s. A I I t his pro ves, Go I din dry I y r ema r ks, "i s t hat<br />

economists are less imaginative than lighthousekeepers."(82)<br />

And insect control is also often classified<br />

as a public good, which generally means that the local<br />

government must hire an airplane or a fleet of trucks<br />

to spray the entire city. But, Goldin notes, there are<br />

actually a plethora of alternatives to such a policy.<br />

For example, it can simply be left up to each citizen<br />

to bu y his own chemi ca I s <strong>and</strong> spray his own yard. "Although<br />

this may be more costly than airplane spraying,"<br />

he says, "efficiency does not depend on costs alone.<br />

H<strong>and</strong> spraying allows greater diversity in chemicals,<br />

310


tim i n g, <strong>and</strong> ext en t 0 f s pray i ng, <strong>and</strong> rna y y i e 1d subs tan ­<br />

tially greater benefits."(83)<br />

Example could be piled upon example, but what is<br />

vi tall y impor tan t about the Goldin art icle is that he<br />

cogently demonstrates that in every area commonly<br />

assumed to be collective, <strong>and</strong> thus entailing equal <strong>and</strong>/<br />

or unrestricted access for all, the method of distribut<br />

ion is, inac t uali t y, a rna t t e r 0 f c hoi c e, <strong>and</strong> t hat i t<br />

is on I y a I a ck of imag i na t i on among academi cs tha t has<br />

prevented them from recognizing this.<br />

But even if there are no goods that are inherently<br />

collective, this still does not mean that such goods as<br />

gas 0 r tel e p h 0 n e s e r v icesoug h t to· be prov idedon the<br />

f r e e mar k e t. For· a s Go I din f r eel y a c knowledg es, 0 ne<br />

may have a choice of distribution systems but the economically<br />

rational choice for some goods might still be<br />

to treat them as if they were collective. Thus, while<br />

i t mig h t bee0 n c e i va bleor pos s j b 1e torely 0 nthe ma r ­<br />

ket for the provision of a certain set of services,<br />

t his w0 u Ide n t a i I wa s t e f u 1 d upi i cat ion <strong>and</strong> s hodd Y s e r ­<br />

vice <strong>and</strong> could therefore not be practical or desirable.<br />

But, argue both minarchists <strong>and</strong> anarchists, this<br />

once again underrates the flexibility <strong>and</strong> adaptability<br />

ofthemark e t s y s tern <strong>and</strong> the i nge nu i t Y 0 f the rna r ke t<br />

particip1lnts. A free market telephone system, for<br />

example, is popularly depicted as lining every street<br />

with a plethora of telephone lines <strong>and</strong> with customers<br />

unable to call anyone subscribing to a competing agency.<br />

But, as John Hospers points out,<br />

no private telephone company that wanted to<br />

del i ver the best service at the lowest price<br />

compatible with making a profit would dream<br />

o f h a v i n g s u chan u t t e r I y c r a z y s ystem • • •<br />

The fa c tis, 0 f co u r s e, t hat jus t as in the<br />

case of water supply, private companies would<br />

dea I wi t h one another for thei r mutual benefit<br />

<strong>and</strong> prof it. Company A would make it easy<br />

for its subscribers to call the subscribers<br />

of Company B, <strong>and</strong> Company B would do the same<br />

for the subscribers to Comapny A -- not particularly<br />

because each wanted to confer profit<br />

s on the other one, but because that would<br />

be the on 1 y way to get them. If there was a<br />

telephone company that refused to cooperate<br />

with the other ones, it would get only a<br />

sma 11 number of subscr ibers, for one would be<br />

311


less likely' to subscrIbe to a company that<br />

could reach only five percent of the populat<br />

i on than to one that could reach most or a I I<br />

ofthem. ( 84)<br />

Moreover, even if the most efficient selling unit<br />

for s e r vic e s I ike wa t e r supply, gas <strong>and</strong> e 1e c t ric i t Y 0 r<br />

sewage disposai, proved to be a city block, a neighborhood<br />

or even an entire city, instead .of the household,<br />

wri ters like Rothbard <strong>and</strong> Spencer Heath MacCallum argue<br />

that there is no reason why the market couldn't adapt<br />

its elf tot his con d i t ion. ( 8 5 ) As was the ca s e for<br />

po 11 uti on con t r 0 1, probably the eas iest means in such<br />

cases would be the formation of community corporations<br />

or proprietary communities. A developer could make<br />

membership in such a corporation a condition of ownership<br />

in a new subdivision, or the corporation could be<br />

formed af t er the fact by means of covenants. The possibilities<br />

are numerous. The corporation could then<br />

appoint a single body to represent it in negotiations<br />

with "outside" utility firms to supply such services as<br />

gas, electricity, <strong>and</strong> water, either to the community as<br />

a whole, i.e., on an equal access basis,or selectively,<br />

in which case individual households would be<br />

charged on the basis of use. Not only are such arrangements<br />

possible, they are, in fact, in use now. The<br />

Rural/Metro Fjre Department Inc. is a private company<br />

that, since 1952, has contracted with Scottsdale, Arizona,<br />

a ci ty of nearly 100,000 people, for the provision<br />

of fire protection. The Rural/Metro operates at a<br />

prof i t <strong>and</strong> yet is able to provide its services at only<br />

$5.70 per person per year, or less than one-fourth the<br />

national average of $24.39 for cities of comparable<br />

size. Not only is the cost much less, but the service<br />

is considerably better. "Over the past 12 years the<br />

per capita fire loss in Scottsdale has averaged $4.44<br />

per year. The national average over this period was in<br />

the $12 range." Rural/Metro is so successful that "The<br />

company added three stations in 1971, five in 1972,<br />

s eve n i n 1 9 7 3, <strong>and</strong> e i ghtin 19 7 4 . As 0 f 19 7 6 the company<br />

is providing fire protection to thirteen ArIzona<br />

commun it ies -- in seven on a contract basis <strong>and</strong> in the<br />

o the r six to i nd i v i d ua I subs c ribe r s . ( Rur a I /M e t r 0 a 1s 0<br />

provides contract security patrol service to fIve new<br />

towns, <strong>and</strong> ambulance service to five communities.)"(86)<br />

And a recent study of private waste collection companies,<br />

or "refuse agglomerates" as they are called, disclosed<br />

that there are over 10,000 private sector refuse<br />

fIrms with total revenues of $3.5 billion a vear. What<br />

is significant is that a survey of thirty c'ities util-<br />

312


izing prIvate contractors revealed that:<br />

Cities, without exception, reported that the<br />

contractors had been both responsive <strong>and</strong><br />

reliable. The contractor, of course, has a<br />

vested interest in doing a good job ••• Of<br />

all of the cities contacted, not one jndicat<br />

edt hat the con t r act 0 r had fa i 1edt 0 me e t<br />

the st<strong>and</strong>ards required••• What about going<br />

back to a municipal operation? Says [A. G.]<br />

Raymondi [Superintendent of Public Works for<br />

the cit Y 0 f Qui n c y, Ma s s • ] ,. "We wo u 1d never<br />

be able to get back to it now."(87)<br />

Several recent studies have disclosed that public<br />

colle c t ion s e r vic e s are a p prox i rna tel y f 0 u r times as<br />

costly as private ageneies.(88)<br />

But community corporations would not have to contract<br />

out. In "mutualistic" fashion a la Proudhon they<br />

cou I d, ei ther independent ly or in federat ion wi th other<br />

c omm un i tie s 0 reo r po rat ion s, buy the i r own capit a I<br />

equipment <strong>and</strong> then either operate the utilities themselves<br />

or hire outside firms to do so.(89) Such corporations<br />

might even find it profitable to sell their<br />

s e r vicest 0 sur r 0 unding c omm un i tie s . 0 r the c omm un i t Y<br />

corporations might even find it wise to combine the two<br />

approaches. For services in which the capital investment<br />

would be relatively small <strong>and</strong>/or mobile, like fire<br />

<strong>and</strong> gar bag e col lee t ion, a c omm unit yeo r po rat ion migh t<br />

wish to bring in outside firms. For if dissatisfied<br />

with the quality of the service they could fire the<br />

current firms <strong>and</strong> bring in new ones without much disr<br />

u p t ion 0 f s e r vice s • But the supply 0 f wa t e r, gas <strong>and</strong><br />

electricity is much different. Here, the capital<br />

e qui pm e n t d em<strong>and</strong> e dis bot h I a r g e <strong>and</strong> s tat iona r y • On e<br />

could not fire one firm <strong>and</strong> hire a new one without some<br />

disruption of service. In thiS case, a community corpo<br />

rat ion mig h t fin d i t be s t to ownit sown capita 1<br />

equipment <strong>and</strong> either operate its own plants or hire an<br />

outs ide firm to run them. Numerous other possibilities<br />

are con c e i v a b I e <strong>and</strong> precisely wh i c h 0 n e s wo u I d preva i I<br />

is impossible to tell in advance.<br />

The libertarian wrItings on public utilities tend<br />

to be rather scarce <strong>and</strong> theoretically abstract. Consequently,<br />

I have taken these occasional <strong>and</strong> theoretical<br />

remarks <strong>and</strong> tried to construct various scenarios, consistent<br />

wIth the lIbertarian paradigm. What the foregoing<br />

indIcates is that, gIven the ingenuity of the<br />

313


market, probably fewer services than is commonly<br />

thought need to be suppl ied on a collective or equal<br />

access basis. This means that it would be practical to<br />

supply most of such services on a selective basis<br />

directly to the individual household or subscriber.<br />

M0 reo v e r, g i v enth e fIe x i b iIi t Y 0 f the rna r ke t, even<br />

those situations in which it would be more efficient or<br />

convenient to treat certain services as if they were<br />

collective, would probably not preclude their provision<br />

through the market. But as in earlier sections, it<br />

must be cautioned that to say that such a policy is<br />

feasible is not to say that it is desirable. This is a<br />

value decision that must be left up to the individual<br />

reader.<br />

Thus far we have dealt with the libertarian proposals<br />

for the provision of services in which the use<br />

of violence is absent. While we have not been able to<br />

con c Iud e t hat s u c h a I a iss e z f air e soc i e t y wo u I d be<br />

superior in every aspect to any alternative, it is<br />

significant that we also have not encountered a problem<br />

whose solution would necessitate government. That is,<br />

while the implementation of some of their proposals<br />

might render life less convenient, we have thus far not<br />

uncovered a flaw in the paradigm that would make such a<br />

society impossible or unfeasible. In short, up to this<br />

point the libertarian pradigm must be pronounced<br />

sound. It is now to the more difficult question of<br />

the pro vis ion 0 f s e r vicesin wh i c h the use 0 f vi 0 len c e<br />

is present that we now turn.<br />

314


FOOTNOTES<br />

( 1 ) Wa 1 t e rB 1 0 c k , "Free Market T ran s po r tat ion:<br />

Denationalizing the Roads," The Journal of Libertarian<br />

8 t udies ( 8 umm e r 19 7 9 ), p. 2 1 4 •<br />

(2)Jarret Wollstein, Public Services Under<br />

Laiseez FAire (Private Publisher, n.d.), p. 35.<br />

(3)Ibid., pp. 45-48.<br />

(4)Ibid., pp. 46-67. On these points also see<br />

John Hospers, Libertarianism (Santa Barbara: Reason<br />

Press, 1971), p. 359.<br />

(5 )Block, p. 218.<br />

(6)For a devastating <strong>and</strong> eXhaustive critique of<br />

government attempts to rationally allocate its roads,<br />

see Walter Block, "Congestion <strong>and</strong> Road Pricinf,"<br />

Journal of Libertarian Studies (Summer 1980), pp.<br />

299-330.<br />

(7)See Clarence Carson, War on the Poor (New<br />

Rochelle: Arlington House, 1969), pp. 204-16.<br />

( 8 ) M u r ray Rot h bar d, For aNew Libe r t y ( New Yo r k :<br />

Ma cm ill an, 1973), p. 214.<br />

( 9) w0 lIs t e in, p. 4 0; <strong>and</strong> Rot h bard, New Libe r t y ,<br />

pp. 217 -1 8 •<br />

(10)Robert Cervero, "Deregulating Urban Transport<br />

a t Ion ," The Cat 0 J 0 urn a I (S p r i n g / S umm e r 19 85 ), PP •<br />

236-38.<br />

( 11 ) B 10 c k, "F r e e Ma r k e t ,T1 Pp. 234 - 35 •<br />

(12)Rothbard, New Liberty, p. 205; Block, "Free<br />

Market," pp. 219-21.<br />

(13)Rothbard, New Liberty, p. 210.<br />

(14)Block, "Free Market," p. 216.<br />

(15)Rothbard, New Liberty, pp. 217-18; <strong>and</strong><br />

Wi II iam Wooldr idge, Uncle 8am the Monopoly Man (New<br />

Rochelle: Arlington House, 1970), pp. 128-40.<br />

(16)Rothbard, New Liberty, pp. 136-38.<br />

(17)Murray Rothbard, Education, Free <strong>and</strong><br />

Compulsory (Wichita: Center for Independent Education,<br />

n.d.), p. 7.<br />

(18) Rothbard, New Liberty, p. 153.<br />

(19) Ibid., p. 134; <strong>and</strong> Rothbard, Education, p.<br />

9 •<br />

(20)Rothbard, New Liberty, pp. 154-55.<br />

(21)Rothbard, Education, p. 13.<br />

(22)Richard <strong>and</strong> Ernestine Perkins, Precondition<br />

for Peace <strong>and</strong> Prosperity: Rational Anarchy (St.<br />

Thomas, Ontario: Phibbs Printing, 1971), p. 116.<br />

(23)See above, Chapter II.<br />

(24)Rothbard, New Liberty, p. 150-51. Also see<br />

Hospers, p. 377, <strong>and</strong> Perkins <strong>and</strong> Perkins, pp. 115-16.<br />

315


(49 )M. Friedman t "Playboy Interview," p. 56. Good<br />

historical documentation of this'tendency for the commi<br />

ss ions to be "captured" by the industries they regu­<br />

1ate can b e f 0 u ndin Jar 0 1 Man n h e i m, De j a Vu ( New<br />

Y0 r k: St. Ma r tin t s Pres s, 19 7 6 ), e s pee i all y pp. 1 61 - 8 6 •<br />

Interestingly Mannheim then argues for new <strong>and</strong> stronger<br />

regulatory measures, including a Department of Consumer<br />

Affairs.<br />

(SO)Hospers, p. 364.<br />

(51)M. Friedman, "Playboy Interview,"p. 56.<br />

(S2)M. Friedman, Capitalism aod <strong>Freedom</strong>, pp.<br />

1 5 5 - 5 8 • For a n e I aborat i on of these idea s see ibid.,<br />

pp. 149-60; Hospers, pp. 363-67; <strong>and</strong> D. Frjedman, pp.<br />

56-60 <strong>and</strong> 121-25.<br />

(53)William J. Baumol, "Reasonable Rules for Rate<br />

Regulation: PlauLible Policies for an Imperfect World,"<br />

The Crisis of the Regulatory Commissions, ed. Paul W.<br />

MacAvoy (New York: Norton, 1970), pp. 196-97.<br />

(54)Edward Renshaw, "Possible Alternatives to<br />

Direct Regulation," The Crisis of the Regulatory<br />

Commiss ions, e d. P a u I W. MacA v 0 Y ( New Yo r k: Nor ton,<br />

1970) pp. 209-10.<br />

(55)See Rothbard, Mao, Economy <strong>and</strong> <strong>State</strong> (Los<br />

Angeles: Nash, 1970), pp. 653-58. An excellent case<br />

study is found in R. A. Radford, "The Economic<br />

Organization of a Prisoner of War Camp," Economica<br />

(November 1945), pp. 189-201. In WfJ II P.O.W. camps,<br />

R a d for d not e s, "c i gar e t t e s r 0 s e from the s tat us 0 f a<br />

normal commodity to that of currency."<br />

(56)Wooldridge, p. 54.<br />

(57)L. <strong>von</strong> <strong>Mises</strong>, The Theory of Money aod Credit<br />

(Irvington-on-Hudson: F.E.E., 1971), p. 78. Also see<br />

Car I Men g e r, P r inc i pIe s a fEe0 0 om i c s (G lencoe, I I I • :<br />

Free Press, 1950).<br />

(58 )Mur ray Rot hba r d, The Case for a 100 Percent<br />

Gold Dollar (Washington, D.C.: Libertarian Review<br />

Press, 1974), p. 2.<br />

( 59 ) I bid., pp. 2- 3.<br />

( 60 ) I bid., p. 7.<br />

(61)Rothbard t MES, pp. 867-71; also see L. <strong>von</strong><br />

<strong>Mises</strong>, Humao Action (Chicago: Henry Regnery, 1966),<br />

pp. 434-48.<br />

(62)Rothbard t 100 Percent, pp. 24-27.<br />

(63)James Rolph Edwards, "Monopoly <strong>and</strong> Competition<br />

in Money," The Journal of Libertarian Studies (Winter<br />

1982), p. 107.<br />

(64 )On the role of private coinage in history see<br />

Wooldridge, pp. 54-74. Interestingly, the Nobel Prizewinning<br />

economist, F. A. Hayek, has endorsed a system<br />

permitting private coinage of money. See his address,<br />

318


other ways that animals could be protected. Zoos <strong>and</strong><br />

w i I d - I i f e soc i e tie s are two t hat come tom i nd • Sueh<br />

g r 0 ups w0 U1 d des ire toprot ectan i rna 1s for the i r own<br />

sake <strong>and</strong> there is no reason they could not protect<br />

endangered animals. Even hunting groups would desire<br />

well-stocked game areas.<br />

(75)Perkins <strong>and</strong> Perkins, p. 128.<br />

( 7 6 ) Rot h bar d, " Con s e r vat ion ina F r e e Ma r k e t ," p.<br />

113.<br />

( 77 ) I bid., P • 112.<br />

(78)E. J. Mishan, Technology an4 Growth (New<br />

York: Praeger, 1969), p.37. '<br />

( 7 9 ) The p ion e e r i n g w0 r k on non exc 1udab iIi t yi s<br />

Mancur Olson, The Logic of Collective Action (New<br />

York: Shocken, 1965). The pioneering work on nonrivalry<br />

is Paul Samuelson, "The Pure Theory of Public Expenditure,"<br />

Review of Economics <strong>and</strong> Statistics (November<br />

1954), pp. 387-89.<br />

(80)Paul Samuelson J "Aspects of Public Expenditure<br />

Theory," Review of Economics <strong>and</strong> Statistics (November<br />

1958), p. 332. For a good critique of "public goods"<br />

theory from a libertarian perspective see Barry<br />

Brownstein, "Pareto Optimality, External Benefits <strong>and</strong><br />

Public Goods: A SUbjectivist Approach," The Journal of<br />

Libertarian Studies (Winter 1980), pp. 93-106.<br />

(81)Kenneth Goldin, "Equal Access vs. Selective<br />

Access: A Critique of Public Goods Theory," Public<br />

Ch 0 j c e (S p r i n g 19 7 7 ), pp. 53- 54 • Ro t h ba r d a Iso rna ke s<br />

the pungent comment that if a pure public good dId<br />

exist it would not be an economic good at all but "a<br />

natural condition of human welfare, like air superabundant<br />

to<br />

p. 885.<br />

all, <strong>and</strong> therefore unowned by anyone." MES,<br />

.<br />

( 82 ) Go I din, p • 62.<br />

(83)Ibid., p. 54.<br />

(84)Hospers, pp. 351-52.<br />

(85)See Rothbard, MES, pp. 883-90; <strong>and</strong> Spencer<br />

He a I t h MacCal I um, The Art 0 f C omm unit y (M enloPark,<br />

Ca I .: Ins tit ute for Huma neSt udies, 19 70 ) •<br />

(86)Robert Poole, "·Fighting Fires for Profit,"<br />

Reason (May 1976), pp. 6-11. For more on the question<br />

of private fire companies see Wollstein, pp.<br />

28-31; Hospers, pp. 352-54; <strong>and</strong> Wooldridge, pp. 124-27.<br />

Also see Wi II iam D. Burt, Local Problems; Libertarian<br />

Solutions (Washington, D.C.: Libertarian National<br />

Corom itte e, n. d . ), Chapte r 5, pp. 1-10.<br />

( 8 7 ) Wi I I i a m For est ell, "Re f use Agglomera t e s: \\ hY<br />

Cities Use Them," The American City (April 1974), p.<br />

46. Many other such examples could be cited. See, for<br />

example, Hospers, pp. 349-50; <strong>and</strong> Wooldridge.<br />

320


( 88 ) See, for e x amp Ie, Rob e r t R in ger, Res tor i ng<br />

the American Dream (New York: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1979),<br />

pp. 118-22.<br />

( 8 9 ) The i de a 0 f the pro p r i eta r y comm u nit y i s<br />

ex c ell en t 1 Y de vel 0 p e d by Ma cCa I I urn in his TheArtot<br />

Community (New York: Laissez Faire Books, n.d.). Note<br />

here the similarity between this scenario <strong>and</strong> the proposals<br />

of many New Leftists <strong>and</strong> socialIsts. See, for<br />

example, Milton Kotler, Neighborhood Government<br />

(Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1976); <strong>and</strong> Murray<br />

Bookchin, The Limits of the City (New York: Harper<br />

<strong>and</strong> Row, 1974). I do not see any incompatibility bet<br />

weenthe prop r i eta r y comm un i t yon the 0 ne h<strong>and</strong> 8 nd the<br />

operat ion of the market on the other, for such corporat<br />

ions, regardless of their internal structure, would<br />

s til I be 0 per a tin g wit h i n 8 nove r a I I f ram e wo r k 0 f<br />

market coordination. See, for example, Assar Lindbeck,<br />

The Political Economy of the New Left (New York:<br />

Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1971), pp. 93-95.<br />

321


322


CHAPTER IX<br />

Controlling Aggression:<br />

Anarchism's Uilique Solution<br />

It is at this juncture that the agreement between<br />

the minarchist <strong>and</strong> anarchist factions of libertarianism<br />

is s evered. Wh i lethem inarchis t s deny t hat the rna r k e t<br />

can adequately provide for the provision of police <strong>and</strong><br />

c 0 u r t s e r vic e s, <strong>and</strong> the r e foreop t for a "n i g h t wa t c hrn<br />

an" s tate, the a narchis t sextend the irma r ketana 1ysis<br />

into these areas as well. The individualist anarchist<br />

program will be the focus of this chapter.<br />

1. POLICE AND THE COURTS<br />

a. The Rule of Law.<br />

Probably the most common criticism of anarchism in<br />

general, <strong>and</strong> one that is often directed against individualist<br />

anarchism as well, is that anarchism is inconsistent<br />

because, while its goal is liberty, not only<br />

liberty but even society itself is impossible without a<br />

rule of law. The goal of a rule of law is to let the<br />

individual know in advance what he may <strong>and</strong> may not do.<br />

By establishing formal rules applicable to everyone the<br />

rule of law facilitates social cooperation by reducing<br />

or el iminating altogether the arbitrary use of power by<br />

any agent in society. Not only ooes the rule of law<br />

faci I i tate the protection of liberty, runs the common<br />

argument, but liberty cannot be preserved by any other<br />

means. For, in the absence of the rule of law there<br />

would be no check on man's aggressive instincts <strong>and</strong> the<br />

me mb e r s 0 f soc i e t y wo u I d be p I aced at the me r c y 0 f the<br />

strongest, <strong>and</strong> "rights" <strong>and</strong> "justice" would be determi<br />

ned by him who could garner the greatest power. Might<br />

w0 u I d b e rig ht<strong>and</strong> even t ua I 1Y the s t rongest wo u I d prevail.<br />

Anarchism is contradictory precisely because,<br />

Richard Taylor argues, "It is.•. through the legal<br />

order. that human freedom becomes possible." This<br />

means, he concludes, that "<strong>Freedom</strong> is therefore possible<br />

only within a legal order, or which is the same<br />

thing, only within a vastly powerful state."(l)<br />

This is probably the most persistent criticism of<br />

Individualist anarchism. The libertarian "rninarchist,"<br />

John Hospers, for example, points out that "Law... is<br />

a necessity for any form of social organization," <strong>and</strong><br />

323


then adds that "since there is no government, there is<br />

no law." Consequently, individualist anarehism "would<br />

simply be a war -- civil war --among various groups<br />

holding different convictions."(2) And Richard Wheeler<br />

argues that in the absence of a legal order "there is<br />

nome a n s b y wh i c h the cond i t ions t hat cons tit ute the f t<br />

can be established other than on the basis of individual<br />

arbitrary whim. In such a society any <strong>and</strong> all definitions<br />

of what constitutes one's property can claim<br />

e qua I val i d i t y, <strong>and</strong> theref 0 r e node fin i ti 0 n 0 f proper ty<br />

rights in such a society has any validity whatsoever."<br />

Thus, "if no rights are possible without property<br />

r· i g h t s, <strong>and</strong> no pro per t y rig h t s .are pos siblewi thou t<br />

legal i ty -- then in a. society that dispenses with legali<br />

t y, suehas t hat a d v 0 cat e d by free rna r ke t anarchism,<br />

no rights are possible."(3) Peter Crosby maint<br />

a ins t hat nthe d i I emma for the a narchistis t hat itis<br />

o n I yin the con t ex t 0 f a s ystem 0 f pr i rna r y law t hat a<br />

case for the connection between profits <strong>and</strong> morality<br />

can bedeve lop e d • On e migh t even a r g ue t hat the ve r y<br />

point of a legal system is to make sure that crime<br />

doesn't pay." But, "since the anarchist eschews all<br />

talk of law; constitutional, statutory or even common,"<br />

there is "no way to legally guarantee anything."(4)<br />

The result would be chaos <strong>and</strong>/or despotism.<br />

This would indeed be a devastating criticism of<br />

individualist anarchism. The problem, however, is that<br />

far from oppos ing law, one finds continual references<br />

in individualist anarchist literature to "natural law,"<br />

"objective law," "common law," the "libertarian law<br />

cod e ," etc. ( 5 ) What the a narchi s t soppose i s not 1aw<br />

but legislation. Not only do they recognize the crucial<br />

importance of the rule of law but one of their<br />

arguments is that legislation itself constitutes a<br />

violation of a true rule of law. The rule of law, as<br />

we have seen,. is intended to eliminate the arbitrary<br />

use of violence. But, the Tannehills argue that the<br />

dilemma of legislation is that it must make laws that<br />

are universally applicable <strong>and</strong> inflexible on the one<br />

h<strong>and</strong>, <strong>and</strong> flexible enough to apply to a wide range of<br />

cases on the other. Insofar as they are inflexible,<br />

men wi II of t en be convicted or released not on the intent<br />

of the law but on "nothing more than the technical<br />

interpretation of an obscure wording in some statute."<br />

But, insofar as the legi slat ion is flexible, the law<br />

becomes simply a grant of arbitrary power to be used at<br />

the discretion of the agent. Thus legislation is<br />

caught, or so it is argued, on the horns of a dilemma.<br />

The rule of law IS supposed to guide the individual in<br />

324


king but was a completely novel phenomenon that appeared<br />

only when popular sovereignty supplanted the concept<br />

of divine sovereignty during the seventeenth <strong>and</strong> eighteenth<br />

centuries.(ll) Bruno Leoni said that it was only<br />

o v e r the I a s t few cen t ur i es the t t he view emer ged the t<br />

rather than being discovered, law was a comm<strong>and</strong> or some<br />

" s 0 r t 0 f d i k t e t t hat the winn i ng rna j 0 r i tiesin the legislative<br />

assemblies impose upon the minorities ••• "(12)<br />

Historian Norman Cantor admits that the English common<br />

law "had no concept of eit·her legislation or royal<br />

authority to make law by the kingfs will." And, he<br />

adds, "Not unt i I the seventeenth century is the idea<br />

that legislation is the manufacturing of new law<br />

clearly formulated <strong>and</strong> grasped."(13) And Frederic J.<br />

Stimson stated that<br />

The "I a w" 0 f the A ng 10 - S a x 0 n peopIe wa s r e ­<br />

garded as a thing existing by itself •.. It<br />

was 500 years before the notion crept into<br />

the minds, even of the members of the British<br />

Pa r I iaments" that they could make a new<br />

law. What they supposed they did, <strong>and</strong> what<br />

they were understood by the people to do, was<br />

mer ely t 0 dec 1are the I a w, asit wa s the n<br />

<strong>and</strong> as it had been from time immemorial.<br />

"The notion of law as a statute, a thing passed by<br />

a legislature, a thing enacted, made new by a representative<br />

assembly," he continued, "is perfectly modern,<br />

<strong>and</strong> yet it has so thoroughly taken possession of our<br />

minds. that statutes have assumed in our minds the<br />

main bulk of the concept of law as we formulate it to<br />

ourselves."(14)<br />

But if law need not be a comm<strong>and</strong> from above, i.e.,<br />

ei ther enacted by a legistature or imposed by a king,<br />

how did j t emerge <strong>and</strong>, moreimp 0 r tan t 1y, a c qui reva lidity<br />

for the members of the society? Both Hayek <strong>and</strong><br />

Leon i have ar gued that both classical Roman civi 1 law<br />

<strong>and</strong> Engl ish common law were "almost entirely the product<br />

of law-finding by jurists <strong>and</strong> only to a very small<br />

ext e n t the pro d u c t 0 fIe g i s I a t ion. rr ( 15 ) "The Roma n<br />

j uri s t ," say s Leon i, "wa s a so r t 0 f sci en tis t: the obi<br />

e c t i ve s 0 f his res ear c h weret he sol uti on s to ca s e s<br />

that ci t i zens submitted to him for study, just as industrialists<br />

might today submit to a physicist or to an<br />

engineer a technical problem concerning their plants or<br />

the i r product ion. Hence, private Roman law was something<br />

to be described or dIscovered, not something to<br />

be enacted."(16)<br />

326


Whi Ie this no doubt took place, its extent is a<br />

matter of dispute <strong>and</strong> it is possible that Leoni exagg<br />

era t est h earn 0 u n t 0 f j udie i a} I a w- rna king by Roma n<br />

jurists <strong>and</strong>, accordingly, underrates the importance of<br />

legislation. The renowned legal historian Edward<br />

Jenks, for exampl e, points out that the Roman Emperor<br />

c I aim ed, <strong>and</strong> wa sacknowledgedt 0 posse s s, the "r i g h t t 0<br />

leg i s I ate." And J e n k s a r g u e s, i n fa c t, t hat leg is 1a t ion<br />

is a product of Roman ideas.(17) And H. F. Jolowicz<br />

notest hat the two for ma Iso u r ces 0 f Roma n Law we r e<br />

statute <strong>and</strong> professional opinion <strong>and</strong> writings; ttit is<br />

eve n do u b ted," he adds, "whe the r the c I ass i cal j uri s t s<br />

recognized custom as a source of the law at all ••• "<br />

However, Jolowicz goes on to point out that the import<br />

a nee 0 feu s tom " was i mmens e • Not on} y werethe s y s ­<br />

terns with which the revived Roman law came into contact<br />

themselves customary, but the medieval mind looked to<br />

custom as the ultimate authority in any case•••"(18)<br />

What eve r the rei a t ion between c us t om <strong>and</strong> leg i s I a ­<br />

tion in ancient Roman law, there can be little doubt as<br />

the relatively greater signficance of custom in the<br />

Eng lis h comm0 n I a w . This i s no t t 0 say t hat leg is} a ­<br />

t ion was tot a I 1Y a bsen t • P I uc knet t c ommen t s t hat even<br />

in this bastion of common law "we find a fairly cons<br />

tan t s t ream 0 f }e g is} a t ion, from the ve r y beg inn i n g 0 f<br />

authentic Anglo-Saxon legal history about the year 600<br />

cont inuously down to the present day." But, he quickly<br />

adds, thi s was generally used for "only comparatively<br />

t r i v i a I mat t e r s • " ( 1 9) And, a s Ca r t er<strong>and</strong> Her z po i n t<br />

out,<br />

If all legislation in Engl<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s were suddenly declared null <strong>and</strong> void<br />

there would still be a body of common law <strong>and</strong><br />

equity on which to depend ••• If, on the<br />

other h<strong>and</strong>, common law <strong>and</strong> equity were suddenly<br />

swept away, the basic foundation in<br />

bot h coun t r i es for the rules governing such<br />

matters as contracts, wills, trespass, or<br />

I i bel would be missing, except insofar as the<br />

r u 1 e sin the s e fie 1d s ha ve been em bod i edin<br />

1e g i s I a t ion. ( 20 )<br />

The common law is law based on custom <strong>and</strong> tradition,<br />

<strong>and</strong> Pre-Norman Engl<strong>and</strong> had a complicated network<br />

of "county courts" rendering decisions based on existi<br />

n g c u s tom s. And a I tho ugh Will i a m the Ba s tar d, 0 r<br />

Wi II iam the Conqueror as he was better known, appointed<br />

his own men to pr e ide over these courts in the elev-<br />

327


ficiency of the common law as the sole method of lawrna<br />

kin g . A c cordin g toth i.s ·c r i tic ism, the ve r yina b i 1fty<br />

of the judge to alter the law is not only the<br />

strength but also the weakness of the common law. "The<br />

development of case law," says Hayek,<br />

is in some respects a sort of one-way street:<br />

when it has already moved a considerable<br />

distance in one direction, it often cannot<br />

ret rae e its s t e p s whensom e impliea t ions 0 f<br />

earlier decisions are seen to be clearly<br />

undesirable.<br />

Fur ther, the gradual development inherent in common<br />

law "may prove to be too slow to bring about the<br />

desirable rapid adaptation of the law to wholly new<br />

circumstances." In such situations, not only is the<br />

judge, as we> have see, unable to alter the law but it<br />

would be undesirable even if he could, for it would be<br />

unjust to apply the new law<br />

to transactions which had taken place when a<br />

different rule was regarded as valid. In<br />

such situations it is desirable that the new<br />

rule should become known before it is enforced;<br />

<strong>and</strong> this can be effected only by<br />

pro m u I gat in g anew r u I e wh i chi s t 0 be<br />

applied only in the future.<br />

Consequently, concludes Hayek, while the overwhelming<br />

b u I k 0 f I a w 0 ugh t t 0 bethe s pon taneously emerg i ng <strong>and</strong><br />

evolving common law, one cannot dispense with positive<br />

legislation entirely. Legislation is required to remedy<br />

the occasional shortcomings of the common law.(23)<br />

This raises a very serious question for the individualist<br />

anarchists for, if they are unable to find<br />

some way around this problem, it would appear that<br />

there would be no alternative to at least occasional<br />

legislation <strong>and</strong> therefore to some form of government.<br />

Yet, surprisingly, I have been unable to uncover any<br />

·direct attempt by any individualist anarchist to deal<br />

with this question.<br />

However, the wr it i ngs of some non-anarchist authorities<br />

on the common law do place the validity of<br />

t his c r i tic ism i n t 0 que s t ion. Wo r mserac know1e d ge s<br />

that theoretically the principle of stare decisi$<br />

should make the common law static or fixed law that<br />

could be changed only by legislation. But, he contln-<br />

329


ues, in actuality, "the common law has been able to<br />

grow wi thout constant interference by legislation because<br />

judges have b.een able in various ways to circumvent<br />

disagreeable or obstructive precedents."(24)<br />

P I u c k net t, for ex amp Ie, 0 b s e r ve s t hat i n rna nyca sest he<br />

facts are such that the real question is which of<br />

several possible precedents or customs, or which combination<br />

of them, to use. This, clearly, gives the<br />

j u d g e s s om e I a tit u de inad apt i ng the law to new <strong>and</strong><br />

changing situations, or at least guiding it away from<br />

clearly outmoded precedents.(25)<br />

Another important device for this has been noted<br />

by wr i ters such as James B. Scott <strong>and</strong> Sir Henry Maine.<br />

It "grew out of actual practice," says Scott in speaki<br />

n g 0 f the a n c i e n t Rom a n I aw 0 f the jus gen t i urn , <strong>and</strong><br />

was "molded <strong>and</strong> interpreted in response to the needs of<br />

daily life." But sometimes conditions changed or unfor<br />

e see n sit u a t ion s a r 0 s e for wh i ch no I aw ex i s ted.<br />

And it was here, he says, that "theory came to the aid<br />

of practice." The jurisconsults looked for legal or<br />

phi los 0 phi cal p r inc i piescornpat i b lewi t h the pr act i cal<br />

common law. These principles were then used as guides<br />

for applying the common law in new cases as well as<br />

pro v j din g new i n t e r pre tat ion s 0 f ex i s ting c omm 0 n I aw<br />

where new situations made such law outmoded or undesirab<br />

Ie. The j ur i sconsul ts found the natural law aspects<br />

of the Greek doctr ine of Stoicism quite useful here,<br />

<strong>and</strong> it was in this way that the common law gradually<br />

became associated with natural law. "If Rome conquered<br />

Greece materially," says Scott, "Greece conquered Rome<br />

spiritually."(26) And Maine points to the simIlar<br />

de vel 0 pm entin the Eng lis h common law. " I t wa s ," he<br />

says, "taken absolutely for granted that there is somewhere<br />

a rule of known law which will cover the facts of<br />

the dispute not litigated, <strong>and</strong> that, if such a rule be<br />

not dis covered, itis 0 n 1y t hat the ne c e s sa r y patienee,<br />

knowledge, or acumen is not forthcoming to detect<br />

it."(27) Thus, by this "system of rationalization,"<br />

Wormser adds, "law was found where it did not exist,<br />

<strong>and</strong> a I I the c I eve r device s 0 f the log i cian we r e use d to<br />

this end."(28)<br />

Qui t e c I ear I y, the for ego i n g prov ide s a wa yin<br />

which an anarchist common law legal system might be<br />

able to deal with the question raised by critics like<br />

Hayek. One example, say that of pollution control,<br />

ought to suffice to illustrate the process. The important<br />

point here is that not that the common law dId not<br />

recogn ize ownership rIghts to air space but rather that<br />

330


u n til r e c e n t I Y c I e a n air wa s soplen t i f u I t hat i t wa s<br />

not an economic good <strong>and</strong> hence the question of<br />

ownership rights to it never really arose. But as<br />

pol I uti 0 n b e c am e a grow i n g prob I em , c 1e a n air, for the<br />

first time, became a relatively scarce, <strong>and</strong> hence an<br />

economi cally val ued, good. Thus, a judicial decision<br />

declaring pollutants to be a violation of property<br />

rights would constitute not so much the creation of an<br />

altogether new law as simply the application of the<br />

existing law prohibiting violation of another's life<br />

<strong>and</strong>/or property into a new area, i.e., air space. It<br />

is also important to realize that since the decision of<br />

the common law judge is binding only on the immediate<br />

parties in a dispute, he has no power to impose his<br />

dec i s ionson "s 0 c i e t y • " Thus, wh e the r 0 r not s uc h a<br />

legal opinion would be upheld would depend largely on<br />

the state of both public opinion <strong>and</strong> the views of other<br />

judges. In this case, too, reference to the routine<br />

pro c e s s b Y wh i c h the t r a d i t ion a I c omm 0 n I aw h<strong>and</strong>ied<br />

such problems is of relevance here. Doubt created by<br />

gaps in the law, Wormser points out, were dispelled<br />

when fl a further case decides the point about,which the<br />

earl ier judge speculated. And if the judge who uttered<br />

the dictum was well respected, other judges after him<br />

might continue to follow it."(29) I see no reason why<br />

such an approach could not be made to work today. And<br />

if this is so, it should be possible to extend the<br />

common law into such novel areas as those of pollution<br />

once it is recognized that new conditions have arisen<br />

which required the reinterpretation of existing law.<br />

For if the initial decision were warmly received, it is<br />

likely that it would be followed by other judges <strong>and</strong><br />

gradually become part of the body of law.<br />

But this raises an additional question: could the<br />

evolution of the law take place with the rapidity required<br />

to cope successfully with the changed circumstances?<br />

Legislated law is at an advantage here. It<br />

can literally change the law overnight. But I think<br />

that the speed with which the common law can change is<br />

often underrated. Plucknett, for example, argues that<br />

ntheremar k a b I e f eat ureof c us tom wasits fiex i b iii t Y<br />

<strong>and</strong> adaptabi I i ty. n fl In modern times," he says, fl we<br />

hear a lot too much of the phrase 'immemorial custom.'<br />

Ins 0 far as t his ph r a s e imp 1 i est hat c us tom i s 0 r<br />

ought to be immemorially old it is historically inaccur<br />

ate. n I n fa c t, PI u c k net t sa ys, a cu s tom wa s considered<br />

old if it had been in existence for ten to<br />

t wen t y yea r s, ve r y old 1 fit da ted from abo u t t hi r t y<br />

years, <strong>and</strong> ancient if It had been around for as long as<br />

331


forty years.(30) In short, while it may not react as<br />

quickly as legislation, I see,no reason why the pure<br />

common law approach could not successfully deal with<br />

changing situations.<br />

T his r a i s esan0 the r que s t ion: i f the c omm 0 n 1aw i s<br />

really so flexible, how can this square with the very<br />

certainty <strong>and</strong> stability of law that is supposed to be<br />

its greatest attribute? It is no doubt true that the<br />

art iculation of the common law into novel areas, or the<br />

al ter Lng of the meaning of old precedents, does create<br />

an element of instability. This is unfortunate <strong>and</strong><br />

should bern in imized as much as possible. But it ought<br />

to be real i zed that the idea of a gaplesslaw is just<br />

that : an ideal • Even legislated law wi I 1 inevitably<br />

con t a ins 0 mega p s, <strong>and</strong>, as not e d earl i e r, t he un c e r ­<br />

tainty of such law tends to be compounded by the very<br />

process of legislating ever new or more laws. It is<br />

probably impossible to say precisely what is the "best"<br />

mix of stability <strong>and</strong> flexibilty. This is a personal<br />

val ue judgement that depends on many factors. What can<br />

be done is to indicate in a general way the relative<br />

strengths <strong>and</strong> weaknesses of judge-made as opposed to<br />

legislated law.<br />

The strength of legislated law is not only the<br />

speed wi t h wh i ch it can adap t to chang i ng ci rcumstances,<br />

but since it is law that is consciously created<br />

by a body of men <strong>and</strong> presented to the public in<br />

closely worded written statutes, it tends to be more<br />

precis e t han the comm0 n law. On the 0 the r h<strong>and</strong>, the<br />

m0 r e compre hen s i veon e t r i est 0 rna kea' s tat ute, the<br />

more likely it will be for a clause to conflict with a<br />

c I au s e inanot her precis ely wr itten, c losely wor ded ,<br />

comprehensive statute, or even to conflict with another<br />

clause in the same statute. Perhaps more importantly,<br />

since the legislature created the law, it can change<br />

it, <strong>and</strong> change it overnight. The strength of legislated<br />

law is the certainty of the law it provides in the<br />

short run; its weakness is the instability <strong>and</strong> uncert<br />

a i n t y i ten t a i I s for the Ion g run. Con ve r s ely, the<br />

weakness of the common law is not only that it must<br />

adapt more slOWly to changing situations but also the<br />

instability that is created by the transition. Its<br />

strength is that because no one can repeal existing law<br />

or create completely new law the continuity of the<br />

law is maintained, thereby giving individuals the<br />

secur ity of knowing what the law is day in <strong>and</strong> day out.<br />

That is, while there is greater transitional, or short<br />

run, u nee r t a i n t y ass 0 cia ted wit h the c omID 0 n I aw, the r e<br />

332


is also far greater long run stability.(31)<br />

There is one final procedural problem that must be<br />

dealt with. Assuming that a judge in our previous example<br />

does h<strong>and</strong> down a decision declaring pollution to<br />

be a viola t i on of proper ty rights, how can the poll uter<br />

be held responsible for actions that were not in violation<br />

of the law when they were performed? This is a<br />

technical problem that would arise only during the occasional<br />

adaptations of the common law to novel situations,<br />

but its importance should not be ignored. There<br />

would appear to be no reason why a situation like this<br />

could not be h<strong>and</strong>led in much the same way that legislation<br />

would h<strong>and</strong>le it: do not hold the individual responsible<br />

for his past actions but enjoin him not to<br />

pollute in the future. Then, if after a stipulated<br />

period of time the pollution had not ceased, he could<br />

be held responsible for his actions <strong>and</strong> ordered to make<br />

restitution to those he subjected to the pollution,<br />

i.e., the victims. After the injunction against pollution<br />

became incorporated into the law <strong>and</strong> it became<br />

clear to everyone that pollution constituted an invasion<br />

of property rights, the original proviso would be<br />

meaningless <strong>and</strong> pollution would then be treated as a<br />

violation of property rights on a par with any other<br />

violation.<br />

The above remarks are not meant as a conclusive<br />

rebuttal to Hayek, but rather one possible avenue by<br />

which the individualist anarchist might respond to the<br />

Hayek ian c r i t i que 0 f the pur e c omm 0 n I a w a pproa c h . At<br />

any rate, the anarchist believes that a system of spontaneously<br />

emerging common law not only has many advantages<br />

over legislation but also that it is the social<br />

c 0 u n t e r par t, 0 r "twin," 0 f the i r I a iss e z fa ire e con om i c<br />

program. "If legislation is replaced by such judgemade<br />

law," argues Rothbard,<br />

fixity <strong>and</strong> certainty (one of the basic<br />

requirements of the 'rule of law') will<br />

replace the capriciously changing edicts of<br />

statutory legislation. The body of judgemad<br />

e 1awe han g e s ve r y s I ow 1y; fur the r rna r e ,<br />

sin c e j u d i cia Idecis ion s can 0 n I y be rna d e<br />

when parties bring cases before the courts,<br />

<strong>and</strong> since decisions properly apply only to<br />

the particular case, judge-made law -- in<br />

contrast to legislation -- permits a vast<br />

body of voluntary, freely-adopted rules, bargains,<br />

<strong>and</strong> arbitrations to proliferate as<br />

333


soc i e t y • But the imp 0 r tan t poi ntis t hat wh i len0<br />

legal system, <strong>and</strong> particularly that of the common law,<br />

can long run widely counter to views dominant in the<br />

communit y, c omm 0 n I a w j ud i cia Idecis ion s mus t res u Itin<br />

a body of law establishing the protected domains of individual<br />

action. Consequently, the common law probably<br />

moves the community in a libertarian direction.<br />

A further point should be made. Since the common<br />

I a w wa s not enact e d <strong>and</strong> no i nd i v i dual or g r 0 up had the<br />

power to change it, the common law served as a barrier<br />

to power, <strong>and</strong> in particular, government power, But<br />

sin c e law as made by the sovereign, i. e • , the king ora<br />

1e g i s I a t u r e, i sacomma nd by the s 0 vere i gn<strong>and</strong> binding<br />

on all its sUbjects, it is no longer a barr ier to power<br />

but "an instrument for the use of power."(33) It is<br />

therefore not surprising that the anarchists find<br />

common law, though f I awed, fa r more acceptable than<br />

legislated law. Rothbard, for example, advocates<br />

" t a kin g the I a r gel y lib e r tar ian c omm 0 n 1aw, <strong>and</strong> corr<br />

e c tin g i t b Y the use 0 f rna n 's rea son, be for e ens h r i n ­<br />

ing it as a permanently fixed libertarian code or<br />

construction."(34)<br />

The problem with this position is that the common<br />

law must reflect the prevailing views of the community.<br />

Thus a "permanently fixed libertarian code" can be enshrined<br />

only within an overwhelmingly libertarian communit<br />

y • The comm0 n 1a w ma "y pus h the c omm un i t yin a<br />

libertarian direction, but it seems unlikely, even<br />

within an anarchist society, that it would ever be completely<br />

successful in this. There will probably always<br />

b e abod y 0 f tho ugh t 1a r geenough topreve n t the complete<br />

<strong>and</strong> permanent triumph of the libertarian code.<br />

The foregoing enables us to deal with the<br />

anarchist-minarchist debate raised in Chapter I. The<br />

minarchist charged that the natural rights anarchist<br />

placed himself in a dilemma since the institutional<br />

framework of anarchism rendered him incapable or protecting<br />

the substantive principles he purports to<br />

cherish. The anarchist replied that the natural rights<br />

minarchist was hImself in a contradiction since the<br />

I ibertarian "non-aggression axion" was, strictly speaking,<br />

imcompatible with government. Probably both are<br />

right: the anarchist because government is inconceivable<br />

wi thout at least some initiated coercion; <strong>and</strong> the<br />

min arc his t b e c a use therei s lit tIe do ub t t hat the common<br />

law would ever become the complete exemplification<br />

of pure 1 i b e r t.a ria n ism . Buta reformulation of the<br />

335


que s t ion w i I I permit us tog0 bey 0 n d t his rat her em p t Y<br />

answer: which system, anarchism or minarchism, is more<br />

I ikely to result in a more libertarian society?<br />

Given, on the one h<strong>and</strong>, the libertarian propensity of<br />

the common law <strong>and</strong>, on the other, the historical tendency<br />

for states to exp<strong>and</strong>, I think it likely that the<br />

anarchist is more correct on this issue than the<br />

minarchist.<br />

b. The Courts.<br />

Even granting that there can be law in the absence<br />

of legislation, would it be possible for the common law<br />

to operate in the absence of government. It. is to this<br />

question that we now turn.<br />

The first thing to be noted is that the anarchist<br />

simply assumes that the legal order would exist within<br />

a lib e r tar ian soc i e t y, i. e., a soc i e t yin wh i c h the use<br />

of violence would tend to be justified only against<br />

those who had ini t iated its use. Rothbard, for exampIe,<br />

s tatest hat "t h e en t ire 1 i be r tar ian s ystem ineludes:<br />

not only the abolition of the <strong>State</strong>, but also<br />

the general adoption of a libertarian law code." It<br />

"seems clear to me," he continues, "that if the majori<br />

t Y 0 f the publie are not I i be r tar ians, the Stat e wi I I<br />

not be abolished. "(35) And likewise, David<br />

Friedman remarks that an lI a narcho-capitalist society<br />

would be heavily biased toward freedom."(36)<br />

It is important to recognize what is not being<br />

claimed here. The anarchist is not assuming that<br />

everyone would be libertarian, but that the environment<br />

would be largely libertarian. Isn't this simply<br />

que s t ion - beg gin g ? I s n 't he ass urn i n g precisely t hat<br />

which is most in need of demonstration?<br />

I do not think so. The popular view of law, derived<br />

from the "mechanical" <strong>and</strong> power-grounded philosophies<br />

of Jean Bodin, Thomas Hobbes, <strong>and</strong> John Austin,<br />

views law as the comm<strong>and</strong> of the "sovere i gn" to the subjects.<br />

But this exaggerates both the extent <strong>and</strong> the<br />

effectiveness of power. Law, as the legal philosopher<br />

Lon Fuller correctly notes, does not operate in a<br />

social vacuum. Law is not so much "vertical·," i.e., a<br />

comm<strong>and</strong> from the sovereign, as "horizontal," in that<br />

any functioning legal order is dependent upon the<br />

"existence of a relatively stable reciprocity of<br />

expectat ions between law giver <strong>and</strong> subject..."(37)<br />

Much the same thing has been noted by Friedrich Hayek:<br />

336


I t would•.• probably be nearer the truth if<br />

we inver ted that plaus i ble <strong>and</strong> widely held<br />

idea that law derives from authority <strong>and</strong><br />

rather thought of all authority as deriving<br />

from law--not in the sense that law appoints<br />

authority but in the sense that authority<br />

comm<strong>and</strong>s obedience because (<strong>and</strong> so long as)<br />

it enforces a law presumed to exist independently<br />

of it <strong>and</strong> resting on a diffused<br />

opinion of what is right.(38)<br />

Thus, while laws will tend to be obeyed so long as they<br />

are seen as worthy of obedience, i.e., as "legitimate,"<br />

the decisions of the legal order will no longer be generally<br />

felt as binding if they are continually at variance<br />

with popular opinion of what is right. The American<br />

experience with alcohol, gambling, prostitution,<br />

<strong>and</strong> drug laws are obvious cases in point. I think it<br />

true to a point seldom realized that no social system<br />

of which the legal order is a major component -- can<br />

long endure without the, at least passive, support of a<br />

large majority. I therefore do not see any problem,<br />

for purposes of exposition, in granting the anarchist<br />

his initial assumption of a generally libertarian environment.<br />

Whether, in actuality, that point could<br />

ever be reached is another question altogether.<br />

What, specifically, would be the process by which<br />

the rule of law would emerge <strong>and</strong> be enforced in an<br />

anarchy? In the absence of government there would be<br />

no tax-supported <strong>and</strong> government-imposed "protection<br />

service." No one would have to purchase protection if<br />

he did not des ire it. Yet, law is obviously a good<br />

highly valued by most, if not all, of us. In the wake<br />

of the abolition of the government monopoly in this<br />

area, anarchists believe it is likely that, as in other<br />

industr ies, companies would quickly form to supply defense<br />

o.r protect ion services to those who want them.<br />

There is little doubt that this would entail some<br />

i nit i a I u nee r t a i n t y as. compan i e s 0 f fer e d a va r i e t y 0 f<br />

leg a leodes <strong>and</strong> "p rot e c t ion packages" to con s ume r s ,<br />

although much would depend on the nature of the transition,<br />

i.e., radical abolition or a gradual phase outph<br />

a s e i n pro c e s s . But, a r guesthe f r e e rna r ketana r ­<br />

chist, there are factors that would facilitate the<br />

rather quick emergence of a rule of law, even in such<br />

"morally underdetermined areas" as legal procedures.(39)<br />

First of all there is what may be termed<br />

"economies of st<strong>and</strong>ardization." A plethora of conf<br />

I 1 C tin g leg a I cod e s w0 u 1d rna ke the provis ion 0 f de-<br />

337


f e ri s e- s e r vic e s bot h needie s sly i n e f fie i ent<strong>and</strong> proh i ­<br />

bit ively expensive. In order for any protection agency<br />

to offer reliable service in such a situation, it would<br />

have to enter' into an extensive series of negotiations<br />

wi th all other companies offering different packages.<br />

Only in this way could it be decided which provision of<br />

wh i ch code would take precedence in the event of a di spute<br />

between its client <strong>and</strong> that of an agency offering<br />

a SUbstantially different package. As a result, argues<br />

John Sneed,<br />

there would .•• be a tendency for codes to<br />

st<strong>and</strong>ardize, especially in minor detail, due<br />

t o· con sid era t ion s 0 f t ransac t ions cos t s<strong>and</strong><br />

the costs of maintaining a stock of knowledge<br />

of other cOdes. Di fferences in codes would<br />

pe r sis t on I y in those areas where the dem<strong>and</strong><br />

for non-st<strong>and</strong>ard enforcement over-rides the<br />

economies of st<strong>and</strong>ardization. These areas<br />

WOll ld cons i s t largely of enforcement dem<strong>and</strong>s<br />

based upon moral <strong>and</strong> religious convictions,<br />

which, while not irrational, can be classed<br />

as non-rational <strong>and</strong> not subject to profitmaximization<br />

behavioral assumptions. Thus, a<br />

substantial move toward st<strong>and</strong>ardization would<br />

occur in the treatment of crimes of violence<br />

<strong>and</strong> infractions of commercial codes, while<br />

d 1 ve r sit Y w0 u I d per sis tin the dema nd for<br />

mores-enforcement.(40)<br />

The uncertainty of the transition would be minimized<br />

by a second factor. Given the assumption of a<br />

largely libertarian society it is likely, believe the<br />

anarchists, that the protection packages offered would<br />

tend to be based on the already existing -- <strong>and</strong> largely<br />

1 ibertarian -- body of common law. Moreover, since all<br />

property would now be -privately owned, the "public<br />

arena" will have ceased to exist. That part of the<br />

existing law dealing with that arena, i.e., the nonlibertarian<br />

provisions, will have become irrelevant,<br />

leaving only those laws regulating the use <strong>and</strong> abuse of<br />

private property. Still assuming a libertarian society,<br />

it is likely that dem<strong>and</strong>s for non-libertarian stipulations<br />

on property use would be too small to make it<br />

profitable for most companies to include such provisions<br />

in their packages. Asa result, the anarchists<br />

bel ieve that not only would a rUle of law emerge, but<br />

it would emerge along generally libertarian lines.<br />

Would this mean that everyone, even non-libertarians,<br />

be forced to live according to libertarian life-styles?<br />

338


The answer is clearly negative. Since a libertarian<br />

code would contain only the injunction against the<br />

i nit i a t ion 0 f v i 0 lence, i two u I d permit the emergen ce<br />

of a complex system of voluntary contractual relations,<br />

or "bilateral law." Such laws would be created on the<br />

s pot by the i n d i v i d u a I s con C ern e d • The y wo u 1d be<br />

des igned to deal with a particular problem <strong>and</strong> would be<br />

bin din g 0 n 1 y up 0 nth 0 s e v0 I un tar i I Y bindin g thems e 1ves<br />

to it. And they would autoffia t i cally lose the i r val idity<br />

as soon as the conditions which they were designed<br />

t 0 d e a I wit h no Ion ge r he 1d • An ex amp lewill rna ke t his<br />

clear. Since the purchase, sale <strong>and</strong> consumption of<br />

drugs does not constitute the initiation of violence,<br />

there could be no proscription of these activities in a<br />

1 i b e r tar ian leg a 1 s ystem. Neve r the 1e s s, the own e r 0 f<br />

an apartment building might rent to someone only under<br />

the condition that the tenant agreed not to use drugs<br />

on the premi ses. Bi lateral law would be created between<br />

the apartment owner <strong>and</strong> a tenant with the signing<br />

of the contract or lease. This law would be binding<br />

on I yon the par tie s d irec t I Y can cerned<strong>and</strong> wo u 1d I a s t<br />

o n I y a s Iongas the i n d i v i d u a I r ema i ned atenantin<br />

that buiding. Since the owner has the right to set any<br />

condition for the use of his property that he desires,<br />

the violation of the contract by the tenant is a violation<br />

of the owner's property rights. Similarly, a<br />

l<strong>and</strong>lord wi th a par t i cu larly acute aversion to noise<br />

might decide to rent only to those who agree that they<br />

wi II not listen to radio or television or stereo <strong>and</strong> be<br />

i n bed bye i g hto' c 1 0 c k eve r y n i g h t • Itis proba b I e<br />

t hat sue h a I <strong>and</strong> lor d w0 u I d fin d few tenant s • I f he<br />

were to relax his restrictions to attract more tenants,<br />

he would be deciding that tenants <strong>and</strong> few restrictions<br />

is better than no tenants <strong>and</strong> rigid restrictions. Simi<br />

larly, the tenants would be deciding that the contract<br />

offered by the l<strong>and</strong>lord is a better "package" than that<br />

of any other l<strong>and</strong>lord. In this way, the anarchist<br />

feels, the common law provides for the working out by<br />

means of voluntary contract or bilateral law an immensely<br />

complex <strong>and</strong> flexible set of arrangements that<br />

i s not 0 n 1 y a b 1 e tot reateac h ca s e on its own me r its<br />

but, since i t r eq u ires the vo I un tar y comm i tmen t 0 f ea ch<br />

<strong>and</strong> every individual concerned, must be to the mutual<br />

benefit of all parties.<br />

It takes little imagination to envision just a few<br />

oft h e po s sib iii tie s t hat suehal egalor de r wo u 1d permi<br />

t. For example,those who find capitalism Tldistasteful"<br />

could pool their property <strong>and</strong> establish socialist<br />

339


or collective communities. As Jerome Tuccile once<br />

wrote, nObv i ous ly, some people prefer a collectivist<br />

style of life <strong>and</strong>, as long as they do it voluntarily<br />

wit h 0 u t for c i ngot her s t 0 sup p 0 r t them, therei s no<br />

reason why they cannot 'coexist' peacefully alongside<br />

the i rca pit a lis tic ne i g h b 0 r s • Peopie co u I d then compare<br />

differing life styles <strong>and</strong> perhaps adapt varying<br />

e I erne n t sintot h e i rown wa y 0 f I i f e • n ( 41 ) I n a ve r y<br />

s i mil a r v e i n Ka r I He s s rna i n t a ins t hat agenera I libe r ­<br />

tar ian or laissez faire framework<br />

i s the 0 n 1 y for m 0 f soc i a I / e con om i corgani ­<br />

zation that could tolerate <strong>and</strong> even bless a<br />

kibbutz operating in the middle of Harlem,<br />

a hippie selling hashish down the street <strong>and</strong>,<br />

a few blocks farther on, a firm of engineers<br />

ou t to do in Det roi t wi th a low-cos t nuclear<br />

vehicle.<br />

The kibbutz would represent, in<br />

effect, a voluntary socialism... The hash<br />

seller would represent institutionalized-but<br />

voluntary -- daydreaming, <strong>and</strong> the engineers<br />

would represent unregulated creativity.<br />

All would represent laissez faire capitalism<br />

ina c t ion <strong>and</strong> non e wo u 1 d nee d a po 1 i t i ca I<br />

off iceholder or a single bureaucrat to help,<br />

hinder, civilize or stimulate.(42)<br />

While the foregoing may be overly fanciful, it<br />

. doe s ill u s t rat e what the a narchistin pa r ticu I a r, <strong>and</strong><br />

the libertarian in general, believes to be the innate<br />

ability of a libertarian legal order to reconcile<br />

otherwise incompatible life styles. This raises an<br />

interesting question. Libertarians tend to believe<br />

that in the absence, or even the minimization, of the<br />

state the market would become all but universal; buying<br />

<strong>and</strong> selling would become practically the only relationship<br />

between individuals. I suspect, however, that<br />

t his i s not what w0 u 1 d hap pen • The prob I em i s t hat<br />

Ii ber tar ians tend to ignore the social sphere. When<br />

they look at society they see only the individual <strong>and</strong><br />

the state <strong>and</strong> they see these as antagonistic. This is<br />

true in many cases, especially today. But as noted in<br />

a n ear lie r c hap t e r ( 43) i tis his t or i cal I y fa 1se: ind i ­<br />

vidual ism <strong>and</strong> the state both emerged with the break-up<br />

oft h e c omm un i t Y s t r u c t ureof the me dieval w0 rId . M0 r e<br />

importantly, the social <strong>and</strong> psychological dimensions of<br />

man tend to be ignored. This has important ramifications<br />

for the free market anarchist perspective of what<br />

340


would "naturally" prevail in the absence of statist restrictions.<br />

As Emile Durkheim noted in his Suicide,<br />

<strong>and</strong> hewa son 1yon e 0 f man y soc i 0 log i s t s t 0 rna ke the<br />

sam e 0 b s e r vat ion, 0 n e 0 f rna n 's rno s t fun damen t a I need s<br />

is that of attachment, of belonging, of security.<br />

Sin c e t his i s d iff i cui t t 0 a chi eve 0 nthe pur e rna r k e t ,<br />

many peopl e, as Tucc ill e commented. simply prefer a<br />

col I e c t i vis t I i f e - styIe. I s us pect. therefor e, t hat a<br />

1 i be r tar ian 1ega lorde r wo u I d res u I t not ina so r t 0 f<br />

universal market permeating all aspects of everyone's<br />

life, but rather in a variety of communities, some of<br />

wh i ch wo u 1 d no doubt es tabl ish themsel ves -- or try to<br />

-- on collectivist or socialist principles, thereby becoming<br />

oases for refugees, so to speak, from the market<br />

system. So long as these were operated vo1untaristically,<br />

I do not see what the individualist anarchist<br />

could do about them. In fact, while libertarians might<br />

con d e mnit asec0 n om i cal I y i r rat ionaI, therei s nore a ­<br />

son why some propr ietary communities could not stipulate,<br />

say, minimum wages, or even some sort of tariffs,<br />

for their communities.<br />

But none of this, it should be cautioned, is necessar<br />

i Iy incompatible with the market as a coordinating<br />

mechanism. Exchange could still take place not only<br />

between individuals regardless of their attachments to<br />

their communities, just as "international" trade now<br />

takes place between individuals of two different count<br />

r i e s, but i t c 0 u I d a Iso t a ke p I ace between c omm un i ­<br />

ties, themsel ves, much in the "mutual istic" fashion<br />

advocated by Proudhon.<br />

In short, I think the lure of both individualism<br />

<strong>and</strong> the mar k e t ten d s t 0 beexa ggera ted by rna n y libe r ­<br />

tarians. People are more than economic atomatons; life<br />

is more than buying <strong>and</strong> selling. Rothbard is fond of<br />

referr ing to the market as "the natural system of liberty."<br />

It is certainly a wonderfUl -- <strong>and</strong> indispensable<br />

- coordinating agent, but I suspect that it is<br />

m0 rea c cur ate tor e fer tot hemarketasone comp0 ­<br />

nent, albei t the most important, of the natural system<br />

of liberty. Since the only requirement of that "systern"<br />

is the principle of voluntarism, it is potentially<br />

compatible with any number of competing economic, <strong>and</strong><br />

soc i aI, 1 i f e - sty 1 e s, s om e 0 f wh i ch wou I d no doub t be<br />

es tabl i shed.<br />

Finally, the foregoing enables us to deal with a<br />

persistent criticism of the individualist anarchist<br />

mora lis t. The legal order of such a society, goes the<br />

341


"Secondly <strong>and</strong> similarly, the two parties, unable to<br />

rea c hag r e e men t, may dec ide t 0 s ubm i t v0 I un tar i I Y t 0<br />

the decision of an arbitrator." This agreement, says<br />

Rothbard, may "arise either after a dispute has arisen,<br />

or be provided for in advance in the original contract."(46)<br />

This, too, as the anarchists are fond of<br />

point ing out, is a method often used in our society to<br />

an ex t en t not us uallyre cogn i zed • Wi IIi am Wooldridg e<br />

has noted that insurance companies regularly settle in<br />

excess of 50,000 claims each year. And in 1970 the<br />

American Arbitration Association<br />

con d u c ted 0 v e r t wen t y- two tho usa ndarbit r at<br />

ions. I ts twenty-three thous<strong>and</strong> associates<br />

avai lable to serve as arbitrators may outnumber<br />

the total number of jUdicial personnel -federal,<br />

state <strong>and</strong> local -- in the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s ••• Add to this the unknown number of<br />

individuals who arbitrate disputes within<br />

particular industries or particular localitie<br />

s, wit h 0 u t AAA a f f iIi a t ion, <strong>and</strong> the qua n ­<br />

titatively secondary role of official courts<br />

begins to be apparent.(47)<br />

T h i r d 1 y, the r e wo u I d be no pro b I em inca s e s wh ere<br />

both parties subscribed to the same court company or<br />

arbitration agency. Since both parties had contracted<br />

to abide by the court's decision, that decision would<br />

be binding.<br />

But what if the parties subscribed to different<br />

agencies? There would be no diffculty if both courts<br />

reached the same decision. This, argue the anarchists,<br />

is not as unlikely as it may seem at first glance,<br />

since no court company could stay in business by rendering<br />

unjust decisions in order to protect the illicit<br />

activities of its clientele. If the Smith Court Company<br />

acquired a reputation for protecting criminals, it<br />

would attract criminals as clients. But, anarchists<br />

ask, who would be willing to sign a contract with a<br />

criminal-client of the Smith Company agreeing that in<br />

the event of a dispute between the two individuals, it<br />

w0 u I d bet a ken tot h e Smit h Com pan y ? Sin c e bot h the<br />

Smith Company <strong>and</strong> its clients would be suspect, a nonclient<br />

would be willing to do business with a Smith<br />

Company client only if the latter signed a contract<br />

a g r e e i n g tot a k e a dis put e t 0 ani nd e penden t com pan y .<br />

Consequently, argue the anarchists, the only disputes<br />

that would be Submitted to the Smith Company would be<br />

those between its own clients. If it then rendered<br />

343


decisions unjustly favoring one of its clients over<br />

an 0 the r, i t wo u I d los e a pa r t 0 fit sown eli en tel e • In<br />

this way the Smith Company would be forced to render<br />

just decisions or go out of business.<br />

It is important to realize that this position is<br />

not predicated on the naive belief that all, or even<br />

most, are good or desire justice.(48) It is based,<br />

rather, on the proposition that no one desires to be<br />

s win die d • Ami g h t wi s h to s i g n a con t rae t to buy a<br />

piece of l<strong>and</strong> from B which would include an agreement<br />

to take any future dispute concerning the l<strong>and</strong> to an<br />

agency A knew would favor him. B would desire to have<br />

an y dis pu t e taken to a company tha t would be favorable<br />

to him. Since, 'Obviously, neither would agree to the<br />

other's terms, the transact ion could be consummated<br />

on 1 y i f A <strong>and</strong> Bag r eedt 0 s u bm itan y dis put e to a<br />

neutral agency. This means, the anarchist believes,<br />

that the greater a judge's reputation for honesty the<br />

more cases he will receive. "An arbiter who sells his<br />

services in a free market," comment the Tannehills,<br />

"knows that he must be as scrupulously honest, fair,<br />

<strong>and</strong> i m pa r t i a 1 a s pos sibleor no pa i r 0 f dis putant s wi I 1<br />

bUy his services to arbitrate their dispute."(49)<br />

Similarly Rothbard says that<br />

What k e e p s A& P h 0 n est i s the c ompetit ion,<br />

actual <strong>and</strong> potent.ial, of Safeway, Pioneer,<br />

<strong>and</strong> countless other grocery stores. What<br />

keeps them honest is the abi I i ty of consumers<br />

to cut off their patronage. What would keep<br />

the free-market judges <strong>and</strong> courts honest is<br />

the lively possibility of heading down the<br />

block or down the road to another judge or<br />

c 0 u r t i f sus pic ion s h 0 u I d des cend upon any<br />

particUlar one. • These are the real,<br />

active checks <strong>and</strong> balances of the free market<br />

economy <strong>and</strong> the free society.<br />

Consequently, he concludes, "in a totally free<br />

society, any suspicion of a judge or court will cause<br />

their customers to melt away <strong>and</strong> their 'decisions' to<br />

be i g nor e d • T his i s a far m0 r e e f f i c i en t s ystem 0 f<br />

keeping judges honest than the mechanism of<br />

government."(SO)<br />

But how would a dispute be h<strong>and</strong>led when agencies<br />

did arrive at different decisions? If, argue the anarchi<br />

s t s, 0 negran t s sue h fir ms even a mod i cum 0 f Comm 0 n<br />

sensea n d for e s i ght, itse ern s proba b 1e t hat toprot e C t<br />

344


themselves <strong>and</strong> their customers from attempts by con men<br />

<strong>and</strong> other unscrupulous people to playoff one court<br />

against another for their own benefit, the various<br />

courts, as part of their policies, would have worked<br />

out a g r e em en t s wit h 0 n e an 0 the r s p e c i f ying to wh i c h<br />

appeals court a legal proceeding involving two differen<br />

t courts would be taken. Prudent ial <strong>and</strong> Metropol i tan<br />

Co u r t Compani es, for exampl e, may dec i de in advance to<br />

take all differences betwee.n them to Acme Appeals Court<br />

Company. But Prudential <strong>and</strong> Zenith Companies may agree<br />

tot a k e s uc h casest0 Que e n CityAppea 1s Cou r t Com pany •<br />

In th i s way the cho i ce of appeals courts would be a<br />

routine matter. The decision of the appeals court<br />

would be binding.(51)<br />

Finally, what of a dispute where one or both<br />

parties do not have prior contractual agreements <strong>and</strong><br />

one 0 f the par ties ref used to s ubmitthe cas e to arb i ­<br />

tration? In the first place, argue the anarchists,<br />

" the rep uta t ion 0 f a rna n wh 0 ref usedar bit rat ion wit hout<br />

good reasons would suffer. People would hesitate<br />

do i ng bus i ness wi th him for fear that they, too, would<br />

be involved in a protracted legal dispute."(52) But<br />

eve n i f 0 nest i I Ire f used, the a narchis t rna i n t a ins t hat<br />

there is no reason why the judicial process could not<br />

pro c e e d . I f S mit h b r i n g s c ha r g esin Co u r t A a g a ins t<br />

Jones then "Court A can only invite rather than subpoena<br />

Jones to attend his trial. Of course if Jones<br />

refused to appear or send a representative, his side of<br />

the case wi II not be heard. The trial of Jones proceeds."<br />

If Court A finds Jones innocent then that<br />

would be binding. But if Court A finds Jones guilty<br />

the n Jonesca n e i the r a c c e p t the j ud gmentor con t est<br />

the dec i s ion by t a king itt0 Cou r t B for r e - t ria I . I f<br />

Court B upholds the original decision then Jones is<br />

guilty. But if the courts disagreed they would submit<br />

the matter to a previously agreed upon appeals<br />

court.(53)<br />

What if the courts do not have a prior agreement<br />

.<strong>and</strong> can no t agree on an a ppea I s cour t ? This i s f e I t to<br />

be amos t un likely occurrence. There would be a monetary<br />

incentive for the courts to reach an agreement.<br />

The i r CllS t orner s, after all, are paying them to decide<br />

the issue <strong>and</strong> if they are regularly unable to decide<br />

they will lose their clients. Moreover, if the<br />

Maver ick Court Company acquired a reputation for delaying<br />

<strong>and</strong> disrupting the proceedings, other courts would<br />

simply announce to their own customers that they will<br />

refuse to h<strong>and</strong>le disputes involving clients of<br />

345


Maver ick. This would make individuals most hesitant to<br />

h a v e bus i n e s s d e ali n g s wit h the pa t ron s 0 f Ma verick •<br />

Hence, Maver ick's clients would be for'ced to use other<br />

c 0 u r t sin all 0 f the i r bus i n e s s deali ngs<strong>and</strong> Ma ve rick<br />

would have to either mend its way or go out of<br />

business.<br />

A t t his poi ntit mig h t be weI 1 to s u mm a r i z e<br />

briefly the anarchist view of the legal process:<br />

[1] I f two parties belong to the same court<br />

company, the decision 6f that court would be binding.<br />

[2] I f they have no contractual agreement but<br />

a g r e eon wh i c h compan y t 0 s ubmitthe dis put e to', the<br />

decision of that court would be binding.<br />

[3] If they subscribe to separate courts, the<br />

decision is binding if the two courts agree. If they<br />

di s8/gree they wi II subrni t the dispute to an appeals<br />

court, which will usually have been chosen in advance,<br />

<strong>and</strong> that decision would be binding. If there is no<br />

pr i or agr eemen t <strong>and</strong> the courts cannot decide on which<br />

appea I s court to take the issue to, then the individual<br />

parties can work out an agreement on their own. If<br />

this, too, cannot be done, then no decision can be<br />

made. This is considered most unlikely, for if a company<br />

continual.ly engaged in protrated <strong>and</strong> costly legal<br />

proceed ings, dther courts would refuse to do business<br />

wit hit, ca u sin g itt 0 los e rna n y 0 r mo s t 0 fit s<br />

customers.<br />

[ 4 ] I f 0 n e i nd i v i d ua Iref uses to s ubmita dis put e<br />

for arb i t rat ion, the 0 ther par t y rna y goahead<strong>and</strong> submi<br />

t it to his company <strong>and</strong> the decision of that court<br />

would be binding unless the original party then submits<br />

his case to another court. In that case, the decision<br />

wi II be binding if the two courts agree. If they disagree,<br />

it would be submitted to an appeals court as<br />

described in point [3].<br />

But wha t if someone pledged to abide by the decision<br />

of the arbitrator <strong>and</strong> then reneged? The anarchists<br />

believe that this would be unlikely since, argue<br />

the Tanneh ill s t such a man would be very unreal iable<br />

<strong>and</strong> 0 the r bus i n e ssm e n W 0 u I d, 0 u t 0 f the i r own self ­<br />

interest, cease doing business with him. To avoid<br />

ostracism it would therefore be to his interest to<br />

comply wi th the decislon.(54) Some empirical support<br />

for this proposition can be found In the Anglo-American<br />

346


mer c han t I a w • Mer c han t sin bothEng I <strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> Arne rica<br />

developed a system of private <strong>and</strong> voluntary law that<br />

wen t a cons i derable way in replacing government law in<br />

this area. These private courts were highly successful<br />

<strong>and</strong> their decisions were nearly always complied with.<br />

not e s Wool d rid g e. des pit e the fa c t t hat they we r e<br />

unenforceable in the government courts prior to 1920.<br />

Like their medieval forerunners. merchants in<br />

the Americas did not have to rely on any<br />

sanctions other than those they could collectively<br />

impose on each other. One who refused<br />

to pay up might find access to his association's<br />

arbitral tribunal cut off in the<br />

future. or his name released to the membership<br />

of his trade association; these penalties<br />

were far more fearsome than the cost of<br />

the award with which he disagreed. Voluntary<br />

<strong>and</strong> private adjudications were voluntarily<br />

<strong>and</strong> privately adhered to. if not out of<br />

honor. out of sel f- interest of businessmen<br />

who know that the arbitral mode of dispute<br />

settlement would cease to be available to<br />

them very quickly if they ignored an<br />

award.(55)<br />

And Rot h bar d bel i eve s t hat sin c e "moder n t e c hno logy<br />

makes even more feas i ble the collection <strong>and</strong> dissemination<br />

of information about people's credit ratings <strong>and</strong><br />

records of keeping or violating their contracts or<br />

arbitration agreement." the system of voluntary justice<br />

would be even more effective today.(56)<br />

Moreover, argue the anarchists, if one still refused<br />

to abide by a decision the victim would "have the<br />

right to make whatever arrangements [he] could with<br />

other individuals or companies who had financial dealings"<br />

with the aggressor.<br />

P rae ticall y s pea kin g, m0 s t ban k s wo u I d no<br />

doubt have a pol icy of cooperating••• in<br />

such matters, since a policy of protecting<br />

ban k a c co un t s from jus t cIa i ms wo u I d tend to<br />

attract customers who were undependable. thus<br />

increasing the cost of banking <strong>and</strong> forcing<br />

the bank to raise its charges. The same<br />

would tend to be true of employers only more<br />

so. Most employers would hesitate to attract<br />

un d e pen dab leI abo r by ins e r tin g a cIa use in<br />

the i r employment contracts guaranteeing pro-<br />

347


teet ion from just claims against them.(57)<br />

Thus, while the anarchists feel that the use of<br />

retal iatory force is justified in forcing the aggressor<br />

to reimburse the victim for the damages caused him,<br />

they also believe that it would be only rarely<br />

required.<br />

c. Police Protection.<br />

Even granting that physical force would be<br />

required only occasionally, a crucial question is how<br />

c 0 u Ids u chas y s t em cop e withitsus e when i t wa s<br />

required?<br />

The a n arch.i s t s a r g ue t hat 0nat0 t a I I Y f r e e rna r ke t<br />

many defense agencies or police companies would emerge<br />

<strong>and</strong> provide protection services to consumers on a cont<br />

rae t u a I bas is. Wh i 1 e therea r e n ume r 0 us wa y s t his<br />

could be done, perhaps the most likely is that "such<br />

services would be sold on an advance-subscription<br />

bas is, wi th premiums paid regularly <strong>and</strong> services to be<br />

supplied on call."(58) The various defense agencies or<br />

pol ice companies would offer their services on the mark<br />

e t. Any i n d i v i d u a 1 couIde i the r prov ide for his own<br />

defense or purchase the services of one of the various<br />

police companies. Just as with any other good, the<br />

market would provide for a plethora of protection policies<br />

offered at different rates <strong>and</strong> designed to meet a<br />

h 0 s t 0 f d iff ere n t con sumerne e d s sothat thos e wh 0<br />

desired twenty-four-hour-a-day bodyguards could hire<br />

them, while those who merely desired an occasional<br />

nightly check of the premises could get what they wante<br />

d • N0 0 new0 u 1 d be for c ed, i. e ., t a xed, to pay for<br />

protection he did not want <strong>and</strong> everyone would be free<br />

to purchase the quant i ty <strong>and</strong> qual i ty of protection<br />

services he desired, including none at all.<br />

It is impor tant to real ize exactly what the anarchi<br />

s t s are referr i ng to wh enthe y s peak 0 f con t raeting<br />

for protective services, for there has been much confusion<br />

on this issue. Charles J. Wheeler, for example,<br />

says that the anarchist is opposed to government<br />

because "the government must be a coercive monopoly,<br />

which logically entails the initiation of force against<br />

would-be compet i tors to remain in existence." Since<br />

anarchists are opposed to this monopoly they therefore<br />

must have "no objection to a society that has more than<br />

one institution, i.e., several, that enforces rules via<br />

ini tiatory force••. Free market anarchism posits...<br />

348


a SOcIety, not in which no institution can initiate<br />

force, but in which any institution can initiate<br />

force."(59) This is surely a misinterpretation. With<br />

the sin g leex c eDt ion 0 f 0 a v i d Fr i e dma n, f r e e rna r ke t<br />

a narc his m s tar t s from the nat u r a I law pos i t ion t ha t<br />

eve r yon e has a righ t to his own I i f e <strong>and</strong> tothe f r u its<br />

of his own labor. It follows, they believe, that<br />

everyone has a right to defend his life <strong>and</strong> property.<br />

This he can do either himself, or by contracting the<br />

services of another. Since specialization results in<br />

both cheaper <strong>and</strong> better services, anarchists believe<br />

t hat the a g en c i e sspe cia 1 i z i ngin s uc h s e r vice s wo u 1d<br />

be the primary means by which protection would be h<strong>and</strong>led.<br />

But when one contracts the services of a police<br />

com pan y t hi s me an s t hat "the agen t rna y t a k e any act ions<br />

whie h the man hims elf wo u I d ha vether i g h t tota ke but<br />

may not do anything which the man himself would not<br />

have the right to do. ."(60) Since no one has the<br />

fIght to initiate the use of violence, police companies<br />

could not legally use violence against noninvasive individuals<br />

<strong>and</strong> could be sued if they did. If companies<br />

e i the r i nit i ate d for ceo r pro t e c ted thos e wh 0 did,<br />

"they would not be competing agencies of retaliatory<br />

force at all. Rather, they would be criminal gangs<br />

pur e <strong>and</strong> s imp 1 e • " ( 61 ) Thus, wh i 1e Wh eel e r i s cor r e c t<br />

in pointing out that anarchists view government as a<br />

coercive monopoly, he is incorrect in stating that they<br />

oppose government because it is a monopoly. They have<br />

no objection to non-coercive monopolies, i.e., those<br />

monopolies that maintain themselves by providing better<br />

services at cheaper prices than any competitor. They<br />

oppose government because it is an agency of initiated<br />

force. Consequently, as Louis Rollins points out, far<br />

from advocating a society in which any individual or<br />

agency has the right to commit aggression, free market<br />

a narc hismad v 0 cat esa" soc i e t yin wh i c h no ins tit ution<br />

holds any authority to commit aggression."(62)<br />

The only exception to this is the alternative propo<br />

sed by Oa vi d F r i e dma n • Sinc e F r i e dma n i s aut iii tar ­<br />

ian rather t han a nat ur a 1- righ t sadv0 cat e , he takes the<br />

pos i t ion tha t pol ice <strong>and</strong> court companies would enforce<br />

those "laws" which were most profitable. There would<br />

s til 1 bear u 1 e 0 f 1aw, he fee 1s, sinc e not even rna ny<br />

"murderers would wish to live under laws that permitted<br />

the m t 0 k ill <strong>and</strong> b e k i I led . " Conseq uen t 1y, s uchIaws<br />

as those prohibiting murder <strong>and</strong> other common crimes<br />

would arise in every society <strong>and</strong> any agency that simply<br />

sold "justice by deciding in favor of the highest<br />

bidder" would be driven out of business. "That would<br />

349


e sUIcidal," Freidman says, for "unless they maintained<br />

a reputation for honesty, they would have no customer<br />

s - - u n I ike 0 u r pre sen t j u d ge s • " F r i e dma n fee I s<br />

that since most people "are willing to pay a much higher<br />

price to be left alone than anyone is willing to pay<br />

to push them around," the "laws of an anarcho-capitalist<br />

society should be heavily biased toward freedom."<br />

Whi Ie acknowledging that his system might well lead to<br />

I a ws pro h i bit in g the use of dr ugs, even on one's own<br />

property, or to laws discriminating against racial<br />

minor i tie s , he feels that this wo u Idre sui t in addicts<br />

or racial minorities leaving areas where they were discr<br />

iminated against. A resident of Los Angeles might be<br />

willing to pay a high price to obtain laws against<br />

drugs in Los Angeles, but he "would have little to gain<br />

by paying a much higher price to have heroin illegal in<br />

New York, as well." The result would be a complex netw0<br />

r k 0 f s epa rat e C omm unit i e s repres entingamu I tit ude<br />

of individualized life-styles <strong>and</strong> all dispersed in such<br />

a faShion as to insure their autonomy. Thus, Friedman'S<br />

exception to the natural law prohibition of acts of<br />

i nit i ate d for c e i s not a s g I a r i ngas i t rna y seem a t<br />

first blush.(63)<br />

Several arguments have been advanced against the<br />

idea of competing police agencies. An examination of<br />

these, together with the anarchist responses, will<br />

serve to clarify several important aspects in the prop<br />

0 s a Ito pro v ide .pol ice s e r viceson the rna r ke t . Th e s e<br />

arguments are as follows:<br />

[1] The argument that either a "minimal<br />

s tat e " 0 raMa f i a Age n c y wo u I d erne r ge<br />

through economic competition.<br />

[2] The argument that a Mafia Agency would<br />

emerge through aggression.<br />

[3] The argument that selling defense<br />

services on the market would be both<br />

inconvenient <strong>and</strong> unjust.<br />

[4] The argument that domestic peace is a<br />

"public good" which cannot be supplied<br />

on the market.<br />

Each of these will be examined in turn.<br />

[1] The Competition Argument.<br />

350


Phi losopher Robert Nozick, as we have seen in<br />

Chapter I, maintains that the system of competing protect<br />

ion agencies will give way to single "dominant protection<br />

agencies," or DPAs, operating in geographically<br />

distinct areas. This is due to the nature of the service<br />

being offered. Nozick believes that the degree of<br />

protection any agency can provide varies positively<br />

with the s i zeof the agency. Thus, as one agency<br />

begins to prosper, individuals will clamor to join. As<br />

the income of the compet ing agencies declines, the<br />

scope <strong>and</strong> qual i ty of the protect ion they can offer<br />

likewise declines. The competing agencies, he says,<br />

get "caught in a declining spiral," <strong>and</strong> the result is<br />

the emergence of a DPA.<br />

Nozick believes that the DPA should proceed to<br />

provide protection services to everyone in its geographical<br />

area. It would therefore become a minimal,<br />

or "nightwatchman," state.(64) But philospher John<br />

Hospers argues that the agency could also use its<br />

dominant pos i t ion to victimize rather than to protect<br />

"its" clients. "Perhaps the most important assumption<br />

of all," says Hospers,<br />

is that there would continue to be a group of<br />

defense agencies (<strong>and</strong> courts) which would<br />

remain competitive. This is indeed one way<br />

in which the scenario could be written. But<br />

there are other ways. Suppose that one<br />

agency became so superbly efficient•.• that<br />

it became la rger than any of the other agencies,<br />

<strong>and</strong> continued to grow larger with time,<br />

until it had, say 99% of the business for a<br />

thous<strong>and</strong> miles around••• We would then have<br />

a defense agency grown so swollen with success<br />

that it could do just what it liked: it<br />

co u I d t urn in t 0 a c rim ina I g an g. • • Th is<br />

wou'ld be in fact, if not in name, a military<br />

takeover. And the result would be again in<br />

fact if not in name, a government -- an<br />

aggressive b<strong>and</strong>it government.(65)<br />

In response, the anarchists note that Nozick <strong>and</strong><br />

Hospers envision the emergence of a number of dominant<br />

agencies whose areas of operation are geographically<br />

distinct. But if the advantages of being a client of<br />

the dominant agency are so irresistable, <strong>and</strong> if, as<br />

N0 z i c k commen t s, "e con 0 m i e s 0 f sea 1e U are posit i vel y<br />

correlated with increased size, the Uthe protection<br />

agency of optimal size will include the whole world."<br />

351


Apparently, says Lawrence Moss,<br />

something imposes a limit on the expansion of<br />

a single protection agency in a given geog<br />

raphiea 1 area • If, for examp1e , the rna rginal<br />

cost of adding individuals to the protection<br />

agency rises, there may come a point,<br />

wi t h r is i ng average cost, at which the marg<br />

i oa I sacr i f ice of pr i vate goods ·as percei ved<br />

by the choice-making individual is greater<br />

t han the mar gina I ga i n inse cur i t Y• At t his<br />

poi 0 t.. the 0 p t i rna 1 s i z e for the pro t e ction<br />

agency has been achieved.(60)<br />

In the United <strong>State</strong>s today there are approximately<br />

40,000 pol ice forces, ranging in size from one man to<br />

3 0 tOO 0 men. Eve·n i f the 0 p tima lee0 nom i c s i z e 0 f a<br />

pro tee t ion age n c y weresuc h t hat the rna r ke t wo u I d not<br />

support 40,000 agencies, the anarchist believes that<br />

therei s nor e a son t 0 sup p 0 s e, s h 0 r t 0 f rna king the<br />

unrealistic assumption that average costs will steadily<br />

decl ine as the size of the agency increases, that this<br />

will lead to the emergence of a dominant agency.<br />

The empirical evidence appears to support the anarchist<br />

on this issue. According to conventional wisdom<br />

the consolidation of many of the 40,000 departments<br />

would result in much more efficient <strong>and</strong> effective police<br />

service. This wisdom was placed in considerable<br />

doubt, however, when several recent studies, such as<br />

thosed 0 n e 0 fIn d ian a pol is, I n d iana; Gr<strong>and</strong> Ra p ids,<br />

Michigan; St. Louis, Missouri; <strong>and</strong> Nashville-Davidson<br />

County, Tennessee, all indicated that relatively small<br />

pol ice forces were not only more efficient but also<br />

more economical. In summarizing the findings of a<br />

nation-wide study conducted at Indiana University,<br />

Vincent Ostrom wrote:<br />

our colleagues found that most statistically<br />

significant relationships ran contrary<br />

to the hypothesis that an increase in the<br />

s i z e 0 f j uri s die t ion wo u 1d be pos i t i ve 1y<br />

ass 0 cia ted wit h h i g her 1eve 1 s 0 f po lice<br />

performance. In examining different size<br />

ranges they found that for the smaller size<br />

range, service levels increase with the<br />

city size to an optimum size of approximately<br />

20,000 for suburban communities <strong>and</strong><br />

100 , 000 for c en t ere i tie s . Beyond t hes e<br />

sizes, the relationship reverses so that<br />

352


large SIze is associated with lower levels<br />

of performance.(67)<br />

But i f 1 a r g e j uri s die t ion s are e con om i c a I I Y <strong>and</strong><br />

socially irrational, they would not be supported on the<br />

free market. And if that is the case, the scenario<br />

depicted in the Nozick-Hospers critique could not<br />

o c cur. Not 0 n 1 y i s the r e no e con om i ereas 0 n to<br />

expect the emergence of a dominant agency, if the<br />

foregoing studies are correct the optimal size might be<br />

such tha t the number of agenc i es opera t i ng in the<br />

te?ritorial United <strong>State</strong>s would actually increase.<br />

[2] The Aggression Argument.<br />

Another criticism is that there would be nothing<br />

to prevent an agency from using force to conquer or<br />

absorb weaker agencies until it attained a position of<br />

u n c h a lIe n g e d d 0 miance, wh i chiteou 1d thenuse to ex ­<br />

plo it its subjects. In contrast to the previous objection,<br />

the Mafia Agency would achieve its domiance<br />

through aggression rather than economic competition.<br />

While not specifically directed at anarchism, this is<br />

the cr iticisrn that George Berkley <strong>and</strong> Douglas Fox raise<br />

against any decentralized political system. Germany's<br />

Weimar Republic, they point out, rested on a federal<br />

ba s e. Mos t German s ta tes out lawed the Naz i Par ty, but<br />

Bavaria did not. "This gave the Nazis a sectional base<br />

on which to build. Then, when they did become a<br />

nationwide movement, they found that the individual<br />

governments of the states ••.were each too weak to curb<br />

their frequently unruly <strong>and</strong> unlawful tactics. There<br />

were thirty-three police forces in Germany at the time<br />

<strong>and</strong> the Nazi Party soon became stronger than anyone of<br />

them." In contrast, the French government was centralized<br />

<strong>and</strong> acted with vigor. With a single police force<br />

for the entire country it was able to take decisive<br />

act ion a g a ins t the a t t emptedNa z i<strong>and</strong> Corom un i s t t a ke ­<br />

overs of 1934.(68)<br />

T his i san i n t ere s tin g c r i tic i sm. Wha tis the<br />

.anarchist reply? The anarchist believes that the forego<br />

i n g ish i g h I Y un I ike I y <strong>and</strong> rna i n t a ins, in fa c t, t hat<br />

violence, or any use of force, would probably decline<br />

in an anarchy. What is the basis for this conclusion?<br />

The anarchist begIns with the assumption that most<br />

people are opposed to aggression. "In a profound<br />

sen s e ," remark s Rot h bar d, Tl nos 0 cia I s ystem, wh e the r<br />

anarchist or statist, can work at all unless most<br />

353


people are 'good' in the sense that they are not all<br />

hellbent upon assaulting <strong>and</strong> robbing their neighbors.<br />

If everyone we're so disposed, no amount or protection,<br />

whether S tat eor private, could succeed in staving off<br />

chaos."(69) .<br />

Starting from this assumption, i.e., that while<br />

nearly everyone desires protection only some will desire<br />

aggression against others, he be.1ieves that those<br />

companies most adept at providing protection will get<br />

the bulk of the protection business. But the moment<br />

any agency turned from attracting customers by providing<br />

protection services to coercing individuals into<br />

buying its policies, it would simply "compel them to<br />

buy prot e c t ion fromit scornpet itor s<strong>and</strong> d r i ve itself<br />

out of business."(70) If an agency initiated violence<br />

against individuals who were not its customers, continues<br />

the anarachist scenario, it would be forced to deal<br />

wi t h the i r defense agencies. Since other agencies are<br />

paid toprot e c t the ireu s t ome r s wh i lethe a g gres s i ve<br />

organization is paid to terrorize others, it would find<br />

itself in direct confrontation with all other agene<br />

i e s • This W 0 u I d rna ke wo r kin g for the c rim ina I agenc y<br />

increasingly risky <strong>and</strong> it would have to pay its employees<br />

more money to compensate for this. Aggression<br />

would become correspondingly less profitable <strong>and</strong> therefor<br />

e 1 e s sat t r act i ve as the inc rea sed cos t s tot he<br />

criminal company compelled it to raise its premiums.<br />

The victims of theft, argues David Friedman,<br />

will b e will i n g t 0 pay m0 ret 0 be pro t e c ted<br />

than the thieves will pay to be able to steal<br />

(since stolen goods are worth less to the<br />

thief than to the victim). Therefore the<br />

noncr iminal protection agencies will find it<br />

profitable to spend more to defeat them. In<br />

e f f e c t, the c rim ina I s fig h t a hope I e s s wa r<br />

with the rest of society.(71)<br />

Further, since the defense agencies are paid to protect<br />

their clients from aggression, they would have no reason<br />

to cooperate with the criminal agency. Even if the<br />

criminal agency had its own "court," it is unlikely<br />

that its decisions would be heeded, for any other court<br />

honor ing the decisions would begin to lose its own customers.<br />

Finally, since insurance companies indemnify<br />

their policy-holders against the destruction or theft<br />

oft h e i r pro per t y, a n arc his t s a r g ue t hat the y wo u 1d<br />

have a "vested interest in seeing that values are prot<br />

e c ted <strong>and</strong> a g g res s i v e v i ole n c e h e I d t 0 ami n i mum. "<br />

354


"Coercive acts are destructive of values," note the<br />

Tannehills, "<strong>and</strong> value-destruction is expensive for<br />

insurance companies." Consequently, not only would<br />

insurance policies "probably specify certain st<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

protective measures which the insured must take in<br />

order to buy at the lowest rates -- burglar alarms<br />

connected to the defense company's office, for<br />

example," but<br />

Policies would also state that the insured<br />

mus t buy hi s protect ion from a defense agency<br />

which met the st<strong>and</strong>ards of the insurance company,<br />

to avoid having him hire an inefficient<br />

or fly-by-night defense agency at a cheap<br />

price while counting on his insurance to make<br />

up for any loss which their ineffectiveness<br />

caused him.<br />

Thus, it is held,<br />

Insurance companies, without any resort to<br />

physical force, could be a very effective<br />

f act or i n b r i n gin g an un r u 1y de fenseage n c y<br />

to its knees via boycott <strong>and</strong> business ostracism.<br />

It would be difficUlt, indeed, for<br />

any defense company to sur v i vei f the major<br />

insurance companies refused to sell insurance<br />

not only to it, but to anyone who dealt with<br />

it. Such a boycott would dry upa major part<br />

of the defense company's market in short<br />

order; <strong>and</strong> no bus iness can survive for long<br />

wi thout customers. There would be no way for<br />

a defense agency to break such a boycott by<br />

the use of force. Any threatening or aggress<br />

i v e act ion s towa r d the ins u rance compan i e s<br />

involved would spread the boycott as other<br />

bus i n e sses<strong>and</strong>ind i v i d ua Isat t empted to s t a y<br />

as ,far away from the coercive agency as<br />

possible.(72)<br />

The p 0 S sib iIi t Y 0 f col Ius ion am 0 ng s ever a 1 agen -<br />

,cies would not alter the situtation. The anarchist bel<br />

ieves that there would be numerous agencies operating<br />

in the protect i on area. We have seen that there are<br />

goo d rea son s, bot hana 1y tica 1 <strong>and</strong> em p i ricai, for t his<br />

bel i ef. Thus, even if a Mafia Cartel were formed, the<br />

pre senceofin d e pendentage nc i e s wo u 1d mo s t ass ured 1y<br />

bring about its quick collapse for the reasons already<br />

discussed.<br />

355


The anarchists contend that this particular criticism<br />

is actually far more app,licable to gove nments<br />

than anarch i es. An anarchy would be character zed by<br />

multiple centers of power. But the state, w th its<br />

monopoly on the use of force, is characterized by a<br />

single center. Since it would be much easier for a<br />

tyrant to take over a single center of power than<br />

multiple centers, "the objection that a tyrant might<br />

take over is actually a devastating, argument against<br />

government."(73), Further the anarchist argues that<br />

those who argue for a state on the ground that the<br />

pol ice companies might ban together to obtain a<br />

monopoly on the use of force are inconsistent, for what<br />

they are rea lly saying is that we should have a state<br />

bee a use a n archis m mig h t res u I tin the emerge nee a f a<br />

state.(74)<br />

In short, anarchists argue that the prospect of<br />

society being victimized bye Ma f i a Police Agency or<br />

even a Mafia Cartel is quite remote. Moreover, given<br />

the expected negative returns on aggression, the free<br />

market anarchist believes that both the crime rate <strong>and</strong><br />

the use of force would be well below what it is in our<br />

statist society.<br />

The foregoing argument is difficult to evaluate.<br />

Anarchism is not a panacea. Problems would exist <strong>and</strong><br />

the poss i bi I i ty of a Maf ia Agency cannot be entirely<br />

dismissed. But this possibility must be placed in pers<br />

pee t i v e • Jus t a s the r e c 0 u 1 d beerim inalor Ma f i a<br />

.agencies in an anarchy, so there could be, <strong>and</strong> as the<br />

widespread pol ice <strong>and</strong> government corruption clearly<br />

shows, there are, state <strong>and</strong> city police departments<br />

that can only be termed criminal.(75) It is significant<br />

that since citizens have no alternative to these<br />

pol ice agencies, there are no, or only weak, checks on<br />

police corruption <strong>and</strong> victimization. If so, one would<br />

expect to find less police corruption in a system in<br />

which police services were offered on a private basis<br />

<strong>and</strong> in which individuals could take their business<br />

elsewhere than in a system where competition is absent.<br />

The empirical evidence on this issue is, of course,<br />

min i ma I. However, the c losest examp leof a compietel y<br />

private, autonomous police agency is the Protection<br />

Section of the American Railway Association. This<br />

"Section" was studied by Jeremiah Shallou for the<br />

Amer ican Academy of Political <strong>and</strong> Social Science in the<br />

1930' s, when it constituted a force of over 10,000 men.<br />

The record compiled by the railway police, or "private<br />

arm i e s" asS h a I lou c a lIs them, wa s not h i ng I essthan<br />

356


incredible. Between 1919, when they were organized,<br />

<strong>and</strong> 1 9 29, when S h a I lou's stu d y wasund e r t a ken, the y<br />

S lJ c c e e d e din red u c i ng f rei gh t c I aim pa ym e n t s for robberies<br />

from $12,726,947 to $704,267 per year, or by<br />

97.7%. And their percent of arrests turning into convic<br />

t ion s was I i kew i s e phe nom e na I : regu I a r I y 0 ve r 80% •<br />

But what par tic u I a r Iyin t eres ted Sha I lou wa s the compor<br />

tmen t of the ra i lway agents themselves. "The fact<br />

that so few complaints have been directed against<br />

them," says Shallou, "is eloquent of the efficiency<br />

with which they are controlled by the railroads. In<br />

Pen n s y 1 van i a .the s tat e exere i s e s no con t r 0 1 whateve r<br />

over these pol ice••• Rai lroad police are responsible<br />

to the company by which they are employed <strong>and</strong> paid, <strong>and</strong><br />

to no one else."(76) And as William Wooldridge<br />

pungently notes:<br />

Shallou's reference to the railway police's<br />

widespread reputation for good character <strong>and</strong><br />

high ability contrasts with the present stat<br />

u s 0 f rna n y big- citY pub I i c for c e s: san c t ions<br />

against misconduct are so ineffective or<br />

roundabout that they may as well not exist,<br />

however theoretically comforting the forces'<br />

status as servants of the people may be.(77)<br />

The foregoing by no means "proves" that criminal<br />

agencies would be non-existent in an anarchy. But it<br />

does serve to put this criticism into perspective.<br />

Criminal agencies might exist in an anarchy. But one<br />

must not forget that they do exist in today's statist<br />

societies. The important question is which system is<br />

more likely to result in a greater amount of criminal<br />

act i v i t Y on the par t 0 f t h os e who are ex p e c ted to<br />

u Phoi d the I a w ? The a narchis t s ha vemad e a ered i b I e<br />

case. And if a competitive system automatically works<br />

to minimize the incidence of corruption <strong>and</strong> criminality<br />

b y the pol ice, i t wo u I d I i kew i s e wo r k tom i n imi z e the<br />

possibi'lity of would-be dictators, of contemporary<br />

Hitlers, from gaining the "Bavarian base" they require<br />

to launch their programs.<br />

[3] The Inconvenience <strong>and</strong> Injustice Argument.<br />

In addition to his argument that the provision of<br />

defense services on the market would lead to the emergence<br />

of a dominant agency, Nozick contends that the<br />

knOWledge that one is I iving in a society permitting<br />

individuals to engage in acts of "private justice"<br />

would produce insecurity. A protection agency, he<br />

357


says, may therefore forbid even nonmembers from engaging<br />

in acts of self-defense against clients of the compan<br />

y pro v ide d "t he c lien t s 0 f the prot e c t i ve agen c y • • •<br />

compensate the independents for the disadvantages imposed<br />

u p 0 nthem by be i ng proh i bit e d self - he 1penfor c e ­<br />

ment of their own rights against the agency's clients."<br />

Compensat ion would be in the form of "protective services<br />

to cover those si tuations of conflict with the<br />

paying customers of the protective agency."(78) Since<br />

competition would ostensibly reduce the number of protective<br />

agencies, <strong>and</strong> since the principle of compensat<br />

ion permit s the d om inan t proteet i ve agenc y t 0 for bid<br />

even nonclients (including their agencies) from defendi<br />

n g thems e 1 v e s pro v ide d the y r e c e i v e compensa t ion,<br />

N0 z i c k fee Ishe has pro v ide d a jus t i fica t i on for a<br />

minimal state.<br />

Nozick's criticism is two-fold: the practical consider'ation<br />

that such a society would be most inconvenient,<br />

<strong>and</strong> the moral proposition that such types of nonaggressive<br />

act ivi ty as "self-help enforcement" can be<br />

forcibly prohibited provided compensation is granted.<br />

As noted above, the anarchists deny that their society<br />

wou I d be i nconven i ent. On the contrary, they bel ieve<br />

that since no one could legally initiate force for any<br />

reason <strong>and</strong> s i nee er ime would not pay, there would be<br />

considerably less need for punishment of any kind,<br />

"private" or "public," <strong>and</strong> thus little need to fear it.<br />

Further, since everyone would be held responsible for<br />

the actions he performs, accidents, excessive use of<br />

for c e, etc., W 0 u I d,. not r e c e i ve imm unit y because they<br />

occurred in the "pursuit of justice." As the Tannehills<br />

note, "In the process of collecting from the aggressor,<br />

the victim (or his agents) may not carelessly or viciously<br />

destroy values belonging to the aggressor or<br />

take more from him than the original property (or an<br />

equivalent value) plus costs occasioned by the aggress<br />

ion • " ( 7 9 ) I fanyin d i v i d ua lor em p loye e 0 f a<br />

defense agency did<br />

negl i gently or aggressively apprehend individ<br />

u a 1s, the imp r 0 per 1y de t a i ned i nd i v i d ua 1 rna y<br />

c h a r get h e de fen sea g e n t employe e withaggression<br />

or negligence. The mistakes by defense<br />

agents will be covered by the insuring<br />

bonding company. Under these conditions, a<br />

d e fen sec 0 mpan y w i I I not ret a inan em p loye e<br />

making an unreasonable number of mistakes,<br />

because the cost of insuring such personnel<br />

would soon become prohibitive for them. There<br />

358


i s t h us an aut oma tic pr 0 tee t ion 0 find i v i d ua I<br />

rights as well as protection against "police"<br />

brutality, which cannot occur in a legal<br />

society.(80)<br />

Two fin a I poi n t s s h 0 u I d bema de inth i s con t ext •<br />

First, its supporters hasten to point out that anarchism<br />

does not necessarily mean that every individual<br />

nee d pro v ide for his own defenseat a I I times • I tis<br />

en t ire I y con c e i va blethat I<strong>and</strong> lor d s wo u 1d supply the i r<br />

tenants with police protection just as various other<br />

util i ties are usually supplied now. Insurance compani<br />

es, anx i ous to keep crime rates down, might provide<br />

protect ion to their subscribers as part of their policies.<br />

And the owners of var ious business complexes<br />

such as shopping centers or downtown areas would have<br />

to rna i n ta in safe <strong>and</strong> pleasant surroundings in order to<br />

attract customers to their stores. Any number of other<br />

scenarios are possible.<br />

And second, not only would protection be better<br />

<strong>and</strong> more convenient in an anarchy but, they contend,<br />

since government operations are inherently inefficient<br />

due to the absence of the market, they would be much<br />

less expensive as well.(81)<br />

As for the moral consideration,<br />

distinction," says R<strong>and</strong>y Barnett,<br />

"The crucial<br />

is while voluntarily paying a purchase price<br />

makes an exchange permissible, compensation<br />

does not make an aggress ion permissible or<br />

justified. It is not permissible to deprive<br />

you 0 f f r e e s p ee c h pro v ided I "com pensat e "<br />

you. You would have the right to defend<br />

yourself. If you were unsuccessful, unable<br />

or unwilling to defend yourself, you would<br />

then, in add it ion, have a right to compensation.<br />

Put in more analytic terms, voluntar<br />

iness is a necessary condition for a<br />

morally permissible exchange of values. Compensation<br />

is not a sufficient condition for<br />

justifying or permitting a violation of<br />

rights.(82)<br />

The compensation argument is easy to evaluate. If<br />

one believes in natural rights, aggression is impermissible,<br />

regardless of whether compensation is offered.<br />

T heo the r issues are more difficult. Assuming the<br />

ex i s t ence of a clear rule of law, <strong>and</strong> gIven the advan-<br />

359


tages of specialization, it seems reasonable to suppose<br />

t hat 8 c t s 0 f "p r i v 8 t e jus tice" wou I d be few <strong>and</strong> fa r<br />

between <strong>and</strong>, wh e n pe r formed, wouI d be done wit h a fa i r<br />

degree of care. If so, the possibility that such acts<br />

could occur should generate little insecurity.<br />

One fin a 1 ques t ion t hat i s reI e vantat t his po i n t<br />

i s what 0 f the i n d i v i d ua 1 wh 0 i s too po0 r topur c has e<br />

pro t e c t ion? W0 u 1 d h e 0 r she be for cedt 0 go wit h0 ut<br />

protection? It must be admitted that this is 8 possibi<br />

1 i ty. Al though it is to be lamented, it should be<br />

b 0 r n e i n min d t hat it" i s not un i que tothe f r e e rna r ­<br />

ket ar rangement ••• There have always been groups of<br />

people in human society who have been inadequately protected<br />

by their governemnts."(83) Few can contend that<br />

American blacks or Russian Jews receive adquate protect<br />

ion from the i r g 0 v ernmen t s • Mo reover, i f the a na r ­<br />

chist is correct <strong>and</strong> the incidence of poverty would<br />

decl ine in an anarchy while the provision of protective<br />

services on the market would be cheaper than the current<br />

tax-based monopoly, there would be very few who<br />

could not afford protection. Finally, as one anarchist<br />

wrote, there is nothing to prevent a poor individual<br />

from getting "together with others in a similar situation<br />

to cooperatively provide the most important of<br />

defensive services, in a protection association."(84)<br />

For a I 1 0 f th e s erea s on s , the f ear t hat the poor<br />

w0 u I d r e c e 1 ve inad equa t e pro t e c t ion wo u I d not a ppea r to<br />

be a s e rio u s pro b 1 em. I tis 1 ike I y t hat they wo u 1d<br />

recei ve as much protection as they do now from government,<br />

<strong>and</strong> probably more.<br />

[4] The Public Goods Argument.<br />

A very common view is that "law <strong>and</strong> order," or<br />

"domest ic peace," is a "public good." This means that<br />

it cannot be broken down into marginal units <strong>and</strong> sold<br />

on the market. One individual cannot obtain order or<br />

peace without others also obtaining it, i.e., it is<br />

nonexcludable. We have already noted the Olsonian<br />

argument that individuals will have little or no incentive<br />

to contribute to the provision of a nonexcludable<br />

good. This means that if it were provided voluntarily,<br />

through the market, it would be supplied only suboptimally,<br />

if at all. Hence, coerced contributions, i.e.,<br />

taxes <strong>and</strong> a government, are necessary for its<br />

provision.<br />

John S<strong>and</strong>ers has taken up the Olsonian gauntlet.<br />

360


that i tma k e s little difference whether an individual<br />

punished for say, rape, is ac.tually guilty of the<br />

crime. Since punishment is justified on the ground<br />

t hat i t w i I Ide t e rother s from comm itt i ng c rimes, the<br />

act u a I g u i I t o:r inn 0 c e nee 0 f the per son be i ng pun ishe d<br />

is, strictly speaking, irrelevant.<br />

I t i 's precis ely t his aspe c t 0 f de t err ence, i. e • ,<br />

sacr i f icing one individual for the good of others, that<br />

the natural rights anarchists find objectionable. These<br />

anarchists therefore reject deterrence <strong>and</strong> justify punishment<br />

of criminals on the grounds of either retribution,<br />

i.e., that the individual deserves to be punished,<br />

or restitution, i.e., that the individual violated<br />

someone else's rights <strong>and</strong> therefore ought to provide<br />

compensation to his victim.<br />

A difficulty for the natural rights anarchist,<br />

howe v e r, i s t hat itis dub i 0 us wh e therei the r pa r a d i gm<br />

can, in itself, afford a complete <strong>and</strong> satisfactory<br />

set 0 f p r inc i pie s for d e t e r min i ng wh en, <strong>and</strong> to wh a t<br />

extent, punishment is justified. Since all anarchists<br />

incorporate some form of restitution into their paradigms,<br />

we will examine this proposal first. The principle<br />

that the criminal ought to pay compensation to<br />

the vict im so as to restore the latter, as closely as<br />

possible, to the position he occupied prior to the<br />

c rime, i s qui tea t t rae t i ve • Howe ver, s eve r a I a r g ume n t s<br />

have been raised against it.<br />

It is some times argued that murder presents a dilemma<br />

for the restitutionist: since the victim is deceased,<br />

how can the criminal possibly make restitution?<br />

The restitutionist replies that restitution is owed the<br />

victim. Since he can't collect, it rightfully belongs<br />

to his heirs. Yet another criticism of restitution is:<br />

how can 0 ne pos sibI Y be so ca I lous as toplac e a "g0 i ng<br />

rat e " 0 r "ex c hange val ue " 0 n a huma n I i f e ? Tothis the<br />

restitutionist responds by pointing out that there is,<br />

in fact, a "going rate" now. The only difference is<br />

that now it is set in time rather than in money or services.<br />

The rea I problem, says R<strong>and</strong>y Barnett, is "one<br />

of incommensurability":<br />

Just as there is no rational relationship between<br />

a wrongfUlly taken life <strong>and</strong> ten years<br />

in prison, there is little relationship between<br />

that same life <strong>and</strong> twenty thous<strong>and</strong> dollars.<br />

Still, the nature of this possibly insoluble<br />

puzzle reveals a restitutional ap-<br />

362


proach theoretically superior to punishment.<br />

For it must be acknowledged that a real, tang<br />

i b 1 e los s had 0 c cur red. • • Re s tit uti 0 n provides<br />

some tangible, albeit inadequate, compen<br />

sat ion for per son a lin j u r y • Pun i s hme n t<br />

provides none at all."(87)<br />

Another common fear is that if compensation would<br />

de t e r min e the limito f f us t i f i a b 1 e pun i s hme nt, the<br />

"cost" of the crime to the criminal would be practical­<br />

1 y nil: if one gets caught steal ing $100 then the only<br />

justifiable punishment would be to return the $100.<br />

Even worse would be a situation in which A fires a gun<br />

at B with the intention of murdering him. But A, being<br />

a bad s hot, miss e s Ban d mer e 1· y b rea ks his wind ow •<br />

Wouldn't compensation limit punishment to replacement<br />

of the window? And if A's shot were completely errant,<br />

would A then get off with no punishment at all? Since<br />

s imp 1ere s tit uti 0 n, a c cor din g tothe c r i tics, wo u I d<br />

place the criminal in a "no lose" situation, it would<br />

actually encourage crime. Restitutionists object to<br />

this conclusion. "The goal is not the suppression of<br />

crime," says Barnett·, ·"it is doing justice to victims."<br />

And full compensation, no more <strong>and</strong> no less, is what the<br />

victim is entitled to. But, he points out, total costs<br />

are act u a I I Y qui t e h i gh • " I n add i t ion toeom pensat ion<br />

for p a inan d s u f fer i ng, the c rim ina I mus t pa y for the<br />

costs of his apprehension, the cost of the trial <strong>and</strong><br />

the legal expenditure of both sides."(88) But what of<br />

the case of attempted murder? The restitutionist might<br />

res po n d t hat B did s u f fer dama ges<strong>and</strong> they we r e qui t e<br />

severe: he had the wits scared out of him. The damages<br />

would also include B's anxiety from knowing that unless<br />

A were apprehended <strong>and</strong> punished he might try again, <strong>and</strong><br />

th i s time wi th better results, at least from A's point<br />

of view. A would not be punished in order to deter him<br />

from f u t urea t tern p t s t 0 k i I I B, a I t ho ugh t hat rna y be<br />

one 0 f .its con seq u enc e s • Ra ther, B wo u I d beentit led<br />

to compensation for the severe psychological damages<br />

caused by A.<br />

But theres til Irerna ins atIeas t the po s sibiii t Y<br />

t hat the nat u reo f the c rim e W 0 uIdse em to dema nd a<br />

punishment more severe than that permitted by restitution.<br />

Attempted theft would be a good example. Since<br />

nothing was stolen <strong>and</strong> since it is ordinarily unlikely<br />

that the same "criminal" will try to rob the same "victim"<br />

more than once, there would be no physical damage<br />

an d ve r y lit tie ps ychologi ca I damage. Such cases appear<br />

to contain an asymmetry between the amount of<br />

363


This doe s I' a i sea n i n t ere s tin g que s t ion. Who<br />

would receive the "second tooth," i.e., the excess<br />

between the full compensation received by the victim<br />

<strong>and</strong> the full penalty paid by the criminal? The victim<br />

would be entitled to the first tooth but surely not the<br />

sec 0 n d • But i f not the vic tim, then wh 0 ? I nth0 s e<br />

rare asymmetric cases where the penalty stipulated in<br />

the 1ega I cod e e x c e e dedthe victim's compensat ion t I<br />

see no reason why it could not become common practice<br />

for a judge to award any excess to The Salvation Army,<br />

the Uni ted Negro College Fund, The American Diabetes<br />

Association or some other charitable or nonprofit<br />

organization of the victim's choice. Under such a<br />

proposal, the viet im would receive full compensation,<br />

the c I' i min a I wo u I d I' e c e i ve his full pena I t y, <strong>and</strong> ye t<br />

neither party would benefit from criminal activities.<br />

We can now examine the proposal for the operation<br />

of prisons. What if the criminal either refused or was<br />

unable to make restitution? "If the aggression were<br />

not of a violent nature <strong>and</strong> the aggressor had a record<br />

of trustworthiness," the Tannehills maintain, "it might<br />

be sufficient to leave him free <strong>and</strong> arrange a regular<br />

s c h e d u leo f paymen t s, jus t a s wo u I d bed0 n e for any<br />

ordinary debt." But, they continue, if the person were<br />

untrustworthy or found guilty of a violent crime, some<br />

confinement would probably prove necessary. In a statist<br />

society the criminal is placed in jails operated by<br />

the state. It is obvious that in the absence of the<br />

state, jails would have to be operated privately <strong>and</strong><br />

t hat, 0 f co u r s e, mea n son apr 0 fit / los s basis. How<br />

would such a system operate?<br />

The viet im, according to the anarchist scenario,<br />

could h<strong>and</strong>le his case on his own <strong>and</strong>, through the<br />

courts, arrange wi th the criminal a regular "schedule<br />

of payments." But since this would be inconvenient <strong>and</strong><br />

time-consuming for him, the anarchist believes that<br />

m0 s tin d i v i d u a I s w0 u Idinsur e thems e I vesaga ins t v i 0lence<br />

<strong>and</strong> would thus be immediately indemnified by the<br />

insurance company in the event of a'loss. Since the<br />

company would then assume the loss theerim i na I would<br />

now owe the company. In such a case, argue the anarchists,<br />

Because it would be in the insurance company's<br />

interest to have the aggressor's reparations<br />

installments as large as possible, it<br />

would have him confined to no greater degree<br />

than his own actions made necessary, since<br />

365


mar k e t p r inc i pie s tothe prob I ern 0 fag gres ­<br />

sion provides a built-in rehabilitiation system.<br />

This is in sharp contrast to governmentrun<br />

prisons, which are little more than<br />

"schools for crime," where young first<br />

offenders are caged with hardened criminals<br />

<strong>and</strong> there is no incentive or opportunity for<br />

rehabilitation.(91)<br />

S uchi s the a n archis t 's view 0 f the n p r i son s y s ­<br />

tern." Could it work? Jails are very expensive operations<br />

<strong>and</strong> the feasibility of such a system would depend<br />

largely on whether the earning power of criminals would<br />

be enough to (a) make reparations, (b) provide a profit<br />

for the penal agency <strong>and</strong> (c) leave enough left over to<br />

support the criminal <strong>and</strong>, perhaps, his or her spouse<br />

<strong>and</strong> children. In some cases the answer would no doubt<br />

be yes.(92) But since criminals are not generally<br />

known for their marketable skills, it is debatable<br />

whether profit-oriented prison companies could sustain<br />

themselves. But market arrangements are amazingly<br />

flexible. It could well be that insurance companies<br />

would either operate penal agencies themselves or provide<br />

some of the operating funds to particular penal<br />

agencies on a contractual basis. The interesting thing<br />

about this possibility is that it would probably not<br />

require higher insurance premiums. This is because the<br />

ability to confine dangerous or unreliable criminals<br />

would drastically reduce the default rate on restitut<br />

ion payments. Those insurance agencies that were not<br />

able to confine such criminals would no doubt find them<br />

evading payments by "skipping town." Since it would be<br />

forced to charge premiums high enough to cover the loss<br />

from its high default rate <strong>and</strong> the cost of reapprehendi<br />

n g thesecrim ina Is, itis qui t e pos siblethat prem i urn s<br />

charged by insurance companies operating prisons would<br />

be the same as, or even lower, than those that did not.<br />

It is a'lso conceivable that companies like Holiday Inn<br />

<strong>and</strong> Best Western might find it profitable to diversify<br />

into this area. Or, if prisons were in chronic financial<br />

difficulty it might be possible to distribute the<br />

"excess" in asymmetric cases among. these companies<br />

instead of awarding them to charities. No doubt other<br />

possibilities could be found.<br />

A stateless society, as its critics point out,<br />

would no doubt contain risks. But that is the nature<br />

of life. Anarchy is a method of social organization.<br />

It is not a utopia. Crime would not completely disappear.<br />

People would still be robbed <strong>and</strong> murdered. al-<br />

367


is rigorously limited to the individual<br />

criminals. We may judge for ourselves how<br />

many wars or conflicts in history have met<br />

this criterion.(93)<br />

While the "bow <strong>and</strong> arrow could be used for aggressive<br />

purposes. it could also be pinpointed to use only<br />

against aggressors," he continues. But "Nuclear<br />

weapons, even' conventional' aerial bombs, cannot be.<br />

These weapons are ipso facto engines of indiscrimininate<br />

mass destruction••• We must, therefore, conclude<br />

that the use of nuclear or similar weapons, or the<br />

threat thereof, is a sin <strong>and</strong> acrime against humanity<br />

for which there can be no justification."(94) Thus,<br />

contemporary states, with their panoply of modern<br />

weaponry, can "protect" their citizens only by exposing<br />

them to the perpetual risk of total annihilation.<br />

Also important for the anarchist is the fact that<br />

modern wars are (a) financed by taxes <strong>and</strong>/or inflation<br />

<strong>and</strong> (b) fought by conscripts. This means, that war can<br />

be waged only by governmental aggression against the<br />

states' own citizens. Hence, far from the state protecting<br />

its citizens it is actually the citizens who<br />

are both duped, by pleas to defend the "fatherl<strong>and</strong>"<br />

from the "foreign aggressors," <strong>and</strong> forced, by taxes <strong>and</strong><br />

conscription, into defending the state <strong>and</strong> its ruling<br />

group. "A <strong>State</strong> can only 'die' by defeat in war or by<br />

revolution. In war, therefore, the <strong>State</strong> frantically<br />

mobilizes the people to fight for it against another<br />

<strong>State</strong>, under the pretext that it is fighting for<br />

them."(95) In short, maintains the anarchist, the view<br />

that the state is necessary to protect its citizens is<br />

a myth.<br />

But how could such a society defend itself against<br />

foreign aggression? Anarchists believe that it is possible<br />

to defend the nonstate in the same way that they<br />

see 0 the r pro b 1 ems be i ng h<strong>and</strong>Ied: the rna r ke t • Jar ret<br />

Wollstein argues that private defense companies could<br />

raise capital by selling "defense bonds" <strong>and</strong> repaying<br />

the p r inc i pIe <strong>and</strong> i n t eres t from reven ue 0 b t a i ned by the<br />

sale of either products or rights to inventions resulting<br />

from technological spin-offs.(96) Even granting<br />

that private companies would operate more efficiently<br />

than governmentally operated defenses, it is doubtful<br />

that the number of technological spin-offs would be<br />

enough to cover the costs, must less to leave enough<br />

left over for profit. The same problem would apply to<br />

Da v i d F r i e dman's s u g g est ion t hat a I lor pa r t 0 f the<br />

369


cos t s of na tiona I defense would be funded by such devices<br />

as tipping <strong>and</strong> charitable contr"ibutions.(97)<br />

Another proposal is that "because of the close natural<br />

connection between insurance companies <strong>and</strong> defense<br />

agenci es, it would probably be most feasible to sell<br />

defense against foreign aggression in the form of insur<br />

a nee pol i c i e s • " ( 9 8 ) The ins uran c e company 0 r companies<br />

would then provide for defense out of the proceeds<br />

from the sale of their policies. But the problem<br />

wit h t his is, as Da v i d F r i e dma n po i n t sout, 0 the r i nd i ­<br />

viduals in the same geographical area would be protected<br />

even though they were not insured, or were insured<br />

by a compet ing company which would not have to pay the<br />

expense of actually providing defense services <strong>and</strong><br />

could therefore offer lower rates. Hence, the national<br />

defense insurance company would lose its customers <strong>and</strong><br />

go bankrupt. (99) The same problem exists in the proposal<br />

that national defense could be provided by the<br />

agreement of local 'police companies to pool part .of<br />

their resources to finance the development of national<br />

or at least regional defense equipment, for any agency<br />

concerning itself solely with local police protection<br />

could avoid the additional costs <strong>and</strong> force the other<br />

agencies out of business by charging lower rates. The<br />

fatal flaw in these proposals is that national defense<br />

isac0 lIe c t i vego 0 d • I teannot bed i v idedin t 0 rna r ­<br />

gin a I unit san d t his, i n t urn, rna k esit d iff i cui t t 0<br />

see how i t c 0 u I d b e sup p 1 i e d b Y any 0 f the rna r ke t ­<br />

oriented alternatives.(lOO><br />

Moreover, the very concept of "national defense<br />

agencies" is difficult to reconcile with natural<br />

rights. Natural rights anarchists argue, of course,<br />

that these defense companies could never be used<br />

aggressively since "No army could grow beyond what the<br />

market would support, <strong>and</strong> the market would never support<br />

an army larger than was actually necessry for<br />

defense, because force is a non-productive expenditure<br />

of energy."(lOl) Yet, as Rothbard has pointed out,<br />

"the old cliche no longer holds that it is not the arms<br />

but the will to use them that is significant in judging<br />

matters of war <strong>and</strong> peace. For it is precisely the<br />

characteristic of modern weapons that they cannot be<br />

used selectively; cannot be used in a libertarian<br />

manner." (102) Since the destruction wrought by modern<br />

weapons is so devastating that it could not be restricted<br />

to the aggressors, a national defense company<br />

would inevitably murder innocent individuals if it<br />

utilized such weaponry. But it would probably be unable<br />

to defend its clientele if it did not. Thus,<br />

370


national defense agencies strike me as being not only<br />

imp r act i c a I but from the na t ur a I righ t s po i n t 0 f view<br />

jus t a s i mm 0 r a 1 a s the s tat e • W0 u I d therebe any me a n s<br />

to defend the nonstate if the concept of national<br />

defense companies were ab<strong>and</strong>oned?<br />

Two mea n s by wh i c h de fenseaga instinvas ion migh t<br />

be effected are nonviolent civilian defense <strong>and</strong> guerrilla<br />

warfare. Nonviolent civilian, or nonmilitary,<br />

d e fen s e i s d e fin e d a s a s t rat e g y wh i c h "a i ms t 0 de f eat<br />

mi 1 itary aggression by using resistance by the civilian<br />

popUlation as a whole to make it impossible for the<br />

enemy to establish <strong>and</strong> maintain political control over<br />

the country."(103) As such it does not depend upon the<br />

defense of physical terrain from enemy occupation but<br />

on passive resistance to enemy rule by the civilian<br />

populatione It is based on the belief that all governmental<br />

power must ultimately come from the consent of<br />

the governed, that "so long as the citizens remain firm<br />

<strong>and</strong> refuse to cooperate <strong>and</strong> obey, the real power lies<br />

with them."(104) Nonviolent defense is actually an<br />

integral part of the anarchist tradition going back at<br />

least to Etienne de La Boetie in the sixteenth century<br />

<strong>and</strong> including anarchists as disparate as William<br />

Godwin, Leo Tolstoy <strong>and</strong> Benjamin Tucker.(lOS) But how<br />

would such defense proceed?<br />

Gene Sharp points out that an invasion is not an<br />

end in itself but a means to a higher end. This end<br />

must be one of two goals: (a) to eliminate the fear of<br />

invasion by striking first, or (b) to occupy the<br />

invaded territory for economic or political purposes.<br />

Since it would be impossible to use the civilian<br />

d e fen s e for a g g res s i v e pur p 0 s e s, i t wo u I d not 0 n I y<br />

dis pel the bel i e f by an 0 therna t ion t hat a coun try employing<br />

a civilian defense could constitute a threat,<br />

but it would also eliminate the possibility of a<br />

nat ion, desiring to wage an aggressive war against such<br />

a country, using the time-honored excuse of defending<br />

itself from an imminent attact by striking first. Conseq<br />

u e n t I y, any nat ion i n vadin g a coun try em p loy i n g a<br />

civilian defense would br<strong>and</strong> itself as the clear<br />

a g g res s 0 r for bot hitsown cit i zens<strong>and</strong> a I I the W0 rId<br />

to see.<br />

While a civilian defense would have no means to<br />

stop an invasion from taking place, it is designed to<br />

prevent the invader from obtaining the objetive(s) for<br />

which the invasion was made. This would be done by the<br />

refusal to cooperate with the invader <strong>and</strong>/or by the use<br />

371


of obstructionist tactics such as mass strikes in occupations<br />

like communications <strong>and</strong> transportation, the<br />

blocking of highways <strong>and</strong> airports with thous<strong>and</strong>s of<br />

ab<strong>and</strong>oned automobiles, the refusal of police to make<br />

political arrests, etc.(106)<br />

This would have a number of ramifications. First,<br />

it would force the invader either to ab<strong>and</strong>on the invasion<br />

or to crack-down on the resistance. If he chose<br />

the latter he would lose even more support in the world<br />

community. More importantly, the increasing use of<br />

repression <strong>and</strong> violence against individuals who were<br />

clearly innocent <strong>and</strong> nonviolent could provoke a moral<br />

<strong>and</strong> p s c Yhoi 0 g i cal dis 0 r i entat ion am 0 ng the i n vad e r ' s<br />

soldiers charged with carrying out the repressions<br />

against the civilian population. This might not only<br />

cause the soldiers to question the justice of their<br />

c a use <strong>and</strong>, u I timate I y, tor e f use toea r r you t the i r<br />

orders, it might also prompt others, perceiving the<br />

clear immorality of the invasion, to join the resistance.<br />

Second, the cost of the massive numbers of<br />

soldiers required to contain <strong>and</strong> crush the resistance<br />

could well outweigh the economic or political benefits<br />

of the invasion, particularly if the population refused<br />

to work for the invader. In such a case, the invader<br />

co u I d be fa c e d wit h no a I t ern a t i ve but go i ng home.<br />

Th i sis not to suggest that nonviolent defense is easy.<br />

On the contrary, death tolls could be considerable, although<br />

no doubt well below those wrought by a conventiona<br />

I mil it ary defense. And the fact that all of the<br />

casualities would be suffered by the civilian populat<br />

ion would no doubt take a heavy psychological toll on<br />

the members of the civilian defense. This is a problem<br />

unique to nonviolent defense <strong>and</strong> one that must be taken<br />

into account by any proponent of such measures. But,<br />

as Gene Sharp has noted:<br />

There" are many instances of effective<br />

non-violent action, including: the early<br />

res i s tan c e b y Ame rica ncoIon i s t s, 17 63- 177 5 ;<br />

Hungarian passive resistance vs. Austrian<br />

rule, especially 1850-1867; Finl<strong>and</strong>'s disobedience<br />

<strong>and</strong> political noncooperation against<br />

Russia, 1898-1905; the Russian 1905 Revolut<br />

ion, <strong>and</strong> t hat 0 f Feb r ua r y 1917 (be for e the<br />

October Bolshevik coup); the Korean nonviolent<br />

protest against Japanese rule, 1919-1922<br />

(which failed); the Indian 1930-1931 independence<br />

campa i gn; German government-sponsored<br />

res 1 s tan c e tot h e F ran co- Bel g i urn 0 c cupa t ion<br />

372


of the Ruhr in 1923.<br />

Later examples include: resistance In<br />

several NaZI-occupied countries, especially<br />

Norway, the Netherl<strong>and</strong>s, <strong>and</strong> Denmark; governmen<br />

1 a I <strong>and</strong> popu I a r me as ures 10 null i f Y an t i ­<br />

JeWIsh measures in several Nazi-allied <strong>and</strong><br />

Nazi-occupied countries, such as Belgium,<br />

I ta I y, France, <strong>and</strong> Denmark; the toppl ing by<br />

popular noncooperation <strong>and</strong> defiance of the<br />

die tat 0 r s 0 f E 1 Sal va d 0 ran d G ua t ema I a in<br />

1944; the 1963 <strong>and</strong> 1966 campaigns of the<br />

Buddhists against the Saigon regimes in South<br />

Vietnam.(107)<br />

Whi Ie civi I ian defense has no guarantee of<br />

success, it should not be cavalierly dismissed. It<br />

has, unfortunately, been given scant attention by the<br />

anarchists although it could prove one possible means<br />

of defending the nonstate, as well as the method most<br />

in accord with their moral principles.<br />

A sec 0 n d p 0 s sib iii t y, g u err i I I a wa r far e, s h 0 u I d<br />

also be considered. Guerrilla forces seldom win military<br />

battles. But they are capable of winning wars <strong>and</strong><br />

ous t ing invaders, provided they are able to retain the<br />

support of the community. Guerrilla wars are not won<br />

militarily but, as Andrew Mack has observed, by means<br />

of the progressive attrition of their opponents' political<br />

capacity to carryon the war.(I08) This is<br />

a C com p lis h e d by mea n s 0 f apr 0 t r act e d wa r, i n wh i c h<br />

the insurgents' goal is to provoke the invader into<br />

escalating his military commitment. As the war drags<br />

on<strong>and</strong>in ere a s esin cos t, b 0 1h h uma n<strong>and</strong> rna 1e ria I, the<br />

fact that the war would probably force cutbacks in the<br />

production of consumer goods a1 home, together with the<br />

fact that it was being fought against a country that<br />

p 0 sed not hrea1, co u I d res u I tin the ernerge nee 0 f pol i ­<br />

tical 'divisions in the invader's horne country. These<br />

divisions could hamper the war effort <strong>and</strong>, in time, sap<br />

the i n va de r 's wi I Ito prosecute the wa r to a suec e s s f u I<br />

conclusion. The guerrilla has a fairly good chance of<br />

WIn n i n g pro v ided he i s a blet 0 fig htaprot rae ted wa r •<br />

As Henry Kissinger has aptly put it, "the guerrilla<br />

WIns if he does not lose; the conventional army loses<br />

if it doesn't win.TI(I09)<br />

Th is too might prove to be a method for defense of<br />

the nonstate. In contrast to civilian defense guerril­<br />

I a war far e w0 u I d ern ploy v i 0 len ce, but 1he fa c t t hat i t<br />

373


w0 u I d ' be 11m i ted <strong>and</strong> co u I d be d i r ec ted a ga ins t the<br />

actual invaders would mean that, it could be justified<br />

as self-defense <strong>and</strong> thus reconciled with the libertarian<br />

anarchists' moral code.<br />

Could either of these two actually provide a<br />

viable defense for an anarchist community? Neither, of<br />

course, can guarantee success. But the same is true of<br />

conventional military defense. And against conventional<br />

forces nonviolent defense has had'both successes <strong>and</strong><br />

defeats; the same is true of guerrilla warfare.<br />

The ado p t ion 0 f e i the r de fen s e wo u I d, howe ve r ,<br />

pose special problems for an anarchy. In"particular<br />

would be the problem of organization <strong>and</strong> training. Adv<br />

0 cat e s 0 f non v i 0 len t de fen seemphas i z e the grea t degree<br />

of discipline <strong>and</strong> sacrifice that must be endured<br />

by nonviolent "soldiers" for it to have any chance of<br />

s u C c e SSe ( 11 0 ) Wh e t her ind i v i d ualsin a soc i e t y wh i c h<br />

emphasized, not sacrifice, but individual gratification,<br />

<strong>and</strong> which was not able to utilize the statist<br />

device of conscription, could be induced to endure the<br />

sacrifices, discipline <strong>and</strong> training required for the<br />

s u c c e s s f u Idevel 0 pme n t 0 f sueh t act i csis dub i 0 us, a I ­<br />

though G<strong>and</strong>hi, it should be noted, did utilize nonviolence<br />

in both South Africa <strong>and</strong> India without the aid of<br />

conscription. A similar problem exists for guerrilla<br />

warfare. While it does not require the large-scale<br />

coordination that nonviolent defense does, it does<br />

dem<strong>and</strong> a great deal of endurance <strong>and</strong> sacrifice on the<br />

part of individual guerrillas.<br />

There is a second, related difficulty. National<br />

defense is, by its nature, a collective effort. What<br />

incentive would an individual have to participate in<br />

e i the r t y p e 0 f defen s e ? On e 's own con t ributi 0 n tothe<br />

overall effort would be minimal. The rational course<br />

for each individual to pursue would therefore be to<br />

avoid the risks <strong>and</strong> seer ifices by not participating.<br />

In brief, given the discipline <strong>and</strong> self-sacrifice entai<br />

led in any defense effort, it is dubious whether any<br />

society based on the principle of individual satisfaction<br />

could present a viable defense.<br />

Thesea r ewe i g h t Y con sid era t ion s w h i c h co u I d ,<br />

conceivably, render such strategies unfeasible in an<br />

anarchy, especially one in which the principle of individual<br />

satisfaction was so basic. But man is far<br />

from unidimensional, <strong>and</strong> I am constantly amazed at the<br />

wi II ingness, even desire, of individuals to participate<br />

374


in, even sacr i f i ce themselves for, a cause or an abstract<br />

concept like "justice," "freedom," or "democracy."<br />

As many have noted, causes such as "defense<br />

against foreign aggressors," can <strong>and</strong> often do produce a<br />

feeling of exhilaration <strong>and</strong> a spiritual uplift in<br />

people. It frees people from the monotony of their<br />

daily routine, <strong>and</strong> the plea for a "total effort"<br />

infuses even those in the lowliest of jobs with a sense<br />

of great importance.{lll) The American home front duri<br />

n g W0 rId War I lis a c I ass i c i I Ius t rat ion • Ma r t ha<br />

Byrd has recently observed that everyone wanted to "do<br />

something, anything, to help." And "the government<br />

responded to the ci t i zens' need for involvement" by<br />

encouraging various kinds of sacrifices: the buying of<br />

war bonds, the growing of vegetable gardens, the collect<br />

ion of scrap metals, the use of car pools, longer<br />

working hours, reduced travel, fewer vacations <strong>and</strong> the<br />

I ike • The res u 1 t ? " M0 r a I e wa s h i g h ." "A fee ling 0 f<br />

being needed," she says, "contributed to a gratifying<br />

sen s e 0 f wo r t han d par tic i pa t ion ina common endea vor<br />

gave intense satisfaction to many."(112)<br />

Th is is no t to say that there would be a footrace<br />

to the sacrificial altar. Certainly many would not<br />

participate <strong>and</strong> some would even become quislings. But<br />

i tis 1 ike 1 y t hat rna ny wo u 1d pa r tic i pat e • Wh e the r i t<br />

would be enough to constitute a successful defense is<br />

impossible to say. Since the success of non-violent<br />

defense hinges on mass participation, even a moderate<br />

number of abstentions would jeopardize the tactic. But<br />

sin c e g uerr ill a war far e doe s not d e pendon rna s s i ve<br />

citizen participation its viability would not, ipso<br />

faeto, be undermined by the presence of a moderate<br />

number of non-participants.<br />

The problems of national defense presents a most<br />

difficult problem for the individualist anarchist. The<br />

bel ief in some sort of national defense company is not<br />

only difficult to reconcile with the libertarian moral<br />

code but is also based on the misperception that<br />

national defense can, like any other good, be divided<br />

.into marginal units. Hope does seem to lie in reliance<br />

on ei ther non-violent civilian defense <strong>and</strong>/or guerrilla<br />

war fa r e • 0 f the two, the I a t t e r s t r ike s me as ha v i ng<br />

the greater probability of success. That an anarchist<br />

society could successfully defend itself from a determined,<br />

ruthless foreign aggressor cannot be guaranteed.<br />

But, of course, the same holds true for the statist<br />

society.<br />

375


Such are the individualist anarchist responses to<br />

the major issue area. In contrast to traditional anarchi<br />

s t the 0 r y, wh i chi s some times based on the rat her<br />

na i ve bel ief that the abol it ion of the state would also<br />

mar k the dis a ppearanceof rna ny 0 f the un s a v 0 r y aspe c t s<br />

of human nature, free market anarchism is premised on<br />

the much less dem<strong>and</strong>ing proposition that while some may<br />

be wi II i ng to cheat, no one wishes to be cheated. Not<br />

only does this constitute a significant departure from<br />

traditional anarchist thought, but it is a far more<br />

credible basis' for social organization. It represents<br />

a new <strong>and</strong> challenging chapter in the history of<br />

anarchism.<br />

376


(38)Hayek, p. 35.<br />

(39)See Robert Nozick, Anarehy. <strong>State</strong> <strong>and</strong> Utopia<br />

( New Y0 r k: Bas i c Bo 0 ks, 19 7 4), for a c r i t i que 0 fana r ­<br />

chism from the "underdetermined areas" perspective.<br />

For a go 0 d rep I y to th is po i n t of view see Er i c Mack,<br />

"Nozick's Anarchism," Anarchism, eds.: J. Rol<strong>and</strong><br />

Pennock <strong>and</strong> John Chapman (New York: New York University<br />

Press, 1978), pp. 55-58. Also see John Sneed, "Order<br />

Wit h 0 u t Law: Wher e Wi I I the Ana r chi s t s Ke e p the Ma dmen?",<br />

Journal of Libertarian Studies (Spring 1977),<br />

p. 122: "The rules of evidence would tend to st<strong>and</strong>ardize<br />

quickly in minute detail, although the admissibilit<br />

y <strong>and</strong> wei g h t g i ve n totape r ecordin gs, hea r say, po I ygraph<br />

••• <strong>and</strong> other questions of this magnitude would<br />

probably not be resolved to all companies' satisfaction.<br />

In the absence of agreement between the companies<br />

as to the rules of evidence or procedure, the arbitrator<br />

would generally settle that dispute also, <strong>and</strong> in<br />

effect set his own rules."<br />

(40)Sneed, p. 121. Also see Friedman, pp. 155-64.<br />

(41 )Jerome Tucci lie, Radical Libertarianism (New<br />

York: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1971), p. 66.<br />

(42 )Kar 1 Hess, The Death of Politics (New York:<br />

Laissez-Faire Books, n.d.), p. 17. Also see the<br />

excellent elaboration of these possibilities by the<br />

minarchist, Robert Nozick, pp. 297-374; <strong>and</strong> Spencer<br />

Mac Ca I I um, The Art 0 f Communit y ( Men loPark, Ca 1 • :<br />

<strong>Institute</strong> for Humane Studies, 1970).<br />

( 4 3 ) S eea b 0 v e , Chapter I I I , Section 4 • Also see<br />

Robe r t Nisbet, The Quest for Communi ty (London:<br />

Oxford, 1953), <strong>and</strong> his The Sociological Tradition<br />

(New York: Basic Books, 1966), especially pp. 47-220.<br />

(44)Jeffrey Paul, "Anarchism <strong>and</strong> Natural Rights"<br />

( Pap e r pre sen ted a t the Ame rica n Ass 0 cia t ion for the<br />

Philosophic StUdy of <strong>Society</strong>, October 6,1977), pp.<br />

2-3. This issue is also raised in John Hosper's<br />

art i c 1 e " Will Rot h bard's Fr e e Ma r ke t Jus tice Suf fiee ?<br />

No," Reason (May 1973), p. 18.<br />

( 45 ) This, I t h ink, is wha t Ro t hba r d mean t by his<br />

statement that "1 see no reason whatever why anyone<br />

should worry about the consent of criminals to their<br />

jus t pun ishmen t • " In"Will Rot h bar d's F r e e Ma r ke t<br />

Justice Suffice? Yes," p. 25.<br />

(46)Murray Rothbard, "<strong>Society</strong> Without a <strong>State</strong>"<br />

(Paper delivered before the American <strong>Society</strong> for Polit<br />

i ca I <strong>and</strong> Legal Phi losophy, \\ashington, D.C., December<br />

28, 1 9 7 4 ); rep r i n ted inAn 8 r chi s m, e d s .: J. Ro I <strong>and</strong><br />

Pennock <strong>and</strong> John Chapman (New York: New York University<br />

Press, 1978), pp. 191-207.<br />

(47)William Wooldridge, Uncle Sam the Monopoly<br />

379


Man (New Rochelle: Arlington House, 1970), p. 101.<br />

(48)This, for example, is the charge made by<br />

Winston Bush. See his "Individual Welfare in Anarchy,"<br />

Explorations in the Theory of Anarchy (Blacksburg,<br />

Va.: Center for the Study of Public Choice, 1972), pp.<br />

5-18. Bush posits two "models of individual behavior":<br />

The Hobbes ian <strong>and</strong> the Proudhonian. In the Hobbesian<br />

model, of course, man is egotistical <strong>and</strong>, in the absence<br />

of government, life is "nasty br-utish <strong>and</strong> short."<br />

In contrast, he says, "the Proudhonian conception is<br />

based on the fai th that, once freed from the constraints<br />

of social rules, individuals will develop<br />

their mutual talents <strong>and</strong> live in harmony one with another."<br />

Since Bush insists on imputing this straw-man<br />

model to anarchists, it is not really surprising that<br />

h e fin d sanarchis m unsat i s fa c tor y • Few, i fan y a na r ­<br />

chists--including Proudhon--actually take this position.<br />

See, for example, the comment by the Tannehills,<br />

p. 73: "a man who refused to pay his debts is a poor<br />

bus i nessri s k, <strong>and</strong> insurance companies would undoubtedly<br />

cooperate in keeping central files listing poor<br />

risks, just as credit associations do today. If his<br />

default were serious enough, no one would want to do<br />

business with him ••• In a free society, men would soon<br />

dis co v e r t hat h 0 n esty withothersis a s elf ish, mo r a I<br />

necessity!"<br />

(49)Tannehill <strong>and</strong> Tannehill.<br />

(SO)Murray Rothbard, For a New Liberty (New<br />

York: Macmillan, 1973), pp. 245-46.<br />

(51)This is found in nearly all individualist<br />

anarchist literature. But especially see Sneed, pp.<br />

117-24.<br />

(52)Tannehill <strong>and</strong> Tannehill, p. 75.<br />

(53)Rothbard, "<strong>Society</strong> without a <strong>State</strong>."<br />

(54)Tannehill <strong>and</strong> Tannehill, p. 66.<br />

(55)Wooldridge, pp. 100-01.<br />

(56)Rothbard, "<strong>Society</strong> without a <strong>State</strong>."<br />

(57)Tannehill <strong>and</strong> Tannehill, p. 66.<br />

(58)Rothbard, Power <strong>and</strong> Market, p. 4.<br />

(59)Wheeler, p. 403.<br />

(60)Tannehill <strong>and</strong> Tannehill, p. 78.<br />

( 6 1 ) Jar ret W0 I 1ste in, " Soc i e t y wit h0 ut Co e r c ion, "<br />

Soc i e t y Wit h 0 u t Go v ernmen t ( New Yo r k: Ar n 0 Press<strong>and</strong><br />

the New York Times, 1972), p. 2.<br />

(62)Louis Rollins, "Symposium: Is Government<br />

Necessary? IV. Reply to C. J. Wheeler," The<br />

Personalist (Spring 1971), p. 403.<br />

(63)Friedman, pp. 155-78. Also see Nozick, pp.<br />

29 7 - 37 4, for the 0 utI i n e 0 f a s imil a r f r amewo r k for<br />

autonomous communities. Despite the similarities,<br />

380


Nozick is a natural rights advocate.<br />

(64)See Nozick.<br />

( 6 5 ) H0 s per s, "W i I I Ro t hbard's F r e e Ma r k e t Jus tice<br />

Suffice? No," p. 21.<br />

(66)Lawrence Moss, "Optimal Jurisdictions <strong>and</strong> the<br />

Economic Theory of the <strong>State</strong>: Or, Anarchy <strong>and</strong> One-World<br />

Go v ernmen tareon 1yeo r n e r Sol uti 0 n s ," Pub1 i c Ch 0 i ce<br />


(84)Ibid., pp. 155-56.<br />

(85) Ibid., pp. 157-58.<br />

(86)The paradigms are discussed in Gordon Tullock,<br />

"Does Punishment Deter Crime?", The Public Interest<br />

(Summer 1974), pp. 103-11; Marc Plattner, "The Rehabilitation<br />

of Punishment," The Public Interest (Summer<br />

1976), pp. 104-14; John Hospers, "Some Problems about<br />

Punishment <strong>and</strong> the Retal iatory Use of Force, Parts I<br />

<strong>and</strong> I I ," Reason (November 1972 <strong>and</strong> January 1973), pp.<br />

1 4 - 2 0 8 n d 1 9 - 2 6, res p e c t i vel y; A I a n Bent<strong>and</strong> Ra I ph<br />

R 0 s sum, Pol ice. Crim ina 1 Jus tiee 8 n d the Comm un i t Y<br />

(New York: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1976), pp. 143-88. Restit<br />

uti 0 n isspee i f i cally dis c ussedin Ra f fa e 1e Ga r 0 fa 10 ,<br />

"Enforced Reparation as a Substitute for Imprisonment,"<br />

Considering the V·ietim, eds.: Joe Hudson <strong>and</strong> Burt<br />

Galloway (Springfield, Ill.: Charles C. Thomas, 1975),<br />

pp. 43-56.<br />

(87)R<strong>and</strong>y Barnett, "Restitution: A New Paradigm of<br />

Criminal Justice," Ethics (July 1977), p. 292.<br />

(88)Ibid., ppe 296-98.<br />

( 8 9 ) T his i s dis c u sse d by Ch a r I e sKi n g, "A<br />

Rationale for Punishment," The Journal of Libertarian<br />

Studies (Spring 1980), p. 159.<br />

(90)Tannehill <strong>and</strong> Tannehill, pp. 126-27.<br />

(91)Ibid .. Also see Sneed's excellent outline,<br />

pp. 122-23.<br />

( 9 2 ) See, for exampIe, Ro u I Tun ley, "Ma king P r i son s<br />

Pay," Reader's Digest (June 1979), pp. 49-56; also<br />

see "P r 0 f i 1 e Swe den," i n Co r r e ct ions Magaz i ne (June<br />

1977), pp. 11-37, <strong>and</strong> especially pp. 22-25: "Inmates<br />

.Work for Free Market Wages at Tillberga Prison." Also<br />

See Kat hIe n e J. 8m i t h, "A euref0 r Cr i me ," Conside r inIt<br />

the Vietim, eds.: Joe Hudson <strong>and</strong> Burt Galloway<br />

(Springfield, Ill.: Charles C. Thomas, 1975), pp.<br />

340-50; <strong>and</strong> Gilbert Cantor, "An End to Crime <strong>and</strong><br />

Punishment," The Shingle (May 1976), pp. 99-114.<br />

(93)Murray Rothbard, "War, Peace <strong>and</strong> the <strong>State</strong>,"<br />

Ega 1 i tar ian ism As a Revol t Against Nature, <strong>and</strong> Other<br />

E s say s ( Was h i n g ton, D. C.: Lib e r tar ian Review Pre s s ,<br />

1974), pp. 71-72.<br />

(94)Ibid., p. 75; <strong>and</strong> Tannehill <strong>and</strong> Tannehill,<br />

pp. 126-27.<br />

(95)Rothbard, "War, Peace <strong>and</strong> the <strong>State</strong>," p. 79;<br />

<strong>and</strong> Tannehill <strong>and</strong> Tannehill, p. 127.<br />

(96)Wollstein, pp. 24-27.<br />

( 97 ) See F r i e dma n, p. 192.<br />

(98)Tannehill <strong>and</strong> Tannehill, p. 128.<br />

( 99 ) F r i e dma n, p • 128.<br />

(100)in ibid., pp. 191-92.<br />

(lOl)Tannehill <strong>and</strong> Tannehill, p. 132-133.<br />

382


(102)Rothbard, "War, Peace <strong>and</strong> the <strong>State</strong>." p. 73.<br />

(103)Gene Sharp, "National Defense without<br />

Armaments." Peace <strong>and</strong> War, eds.: Charles Beitz <strong>and</strong><br />

Theodore Herman (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman <strong>and</strong> Co.,<br />

1973), p. 352.<br />

(104)Gene Sharp, quoted in American Friends<br />

Service Committee, In Place of War (New York:<br />

Gr 0 s srna n, 19 67 ), P • 44.<br />

(105)Etienne de La Boetie, The Polities of Obedience<br />

(New York: Free Life Editions, 1975); William<br />

Godwin, An Enquiry Concerning Political Justice<br />

(Middlesex, Engl<strong>and</strong>: Penguin Books, 1976), especially<br />

pp. 255-66; Benjamin Tucker, Individual Liberty<br />

( Mil 1wood, NY: K r a us Re p r i nt, 19 7 3 ), pp. 7 6 - 81; <strong>and</strong> Leo<br />

T 0 1 s toy, 0 n C i viI Dis 0 bed i enc e <strong>and</strong> Non- Vi olenee ( New<br />

York: Signet, 1968).<br />

(106)Sharp, p. 352; also see Gene Sharp, Exploring<br />

Nonviolent Alternatives (Boston: Porter-Sargent,<br />

1971), p. 64. The literature on nonviolent tactics is<br />

quite extensive. In addition to those works already<br />

cited see Mulford Sibley, ed., The Quiet Battle<br />

( B 0 s ton: Be a con Pre s s, 19 6 3 ); Ma han d as Ga n d hi,<br />

Nonviolent Resistance (New York: Schock en Books,<br />

1974); <strong>and</strong> Wi 11 iam Mi IIer, Nonviolence (New York:<br />

Schocken Books, 1966).<br />

(107) Sharp, "National Defense Without Armaments,"<br />

pp. 354-55.<br />

( 108 ) See the ex celIe n tar tic I e by And r ew Ma c k ,<br />

"How Big Nations Lose Small Wars: The Politics of Asymmetric<br />

Conflict," World Politics (January 1975), pp.<br />

175-200.<br />

( 1 0 9 ) I nib i d ., p , 18 5 , On guerr ill a t act i cssee<br />

especially Mao Tse-tung, Basic Tactics (New York:<br />

Frederick Praeger, 1967), Ernesto Guevara, Che Guevara<br />

on Guerilla Warfare (New York, 1961); <strong>and</strong> Charles<br />

Thayer, Guerilla (New York: Harper <strong>and</strong> Row, 1963).<br />

(110)G<strong>and</strong>hi; <strong>and</strong> Sharp, Nonviolent Alternatives,<br />

p p. 5 7 - 6 1. A 1 s 0 see J e s s i e Wa 1 1ace Hug a n<strong>and</strong> Ce c i 1<br />

Hirshaw, "Toward a Non-Violent National Defense," The<br />

Quiet Battle, ed. Mulford Sibley (Boston: Beacon<br />

Press, 1963), pp. 316-56.<br />

(111 )See Nisbet, Twilight of Authority (New<br />

Yo r k: Ox for d, 1975), pp. 155- 56 •<br />

(112)Martha Byrd, "The Home Front -- World War<br />

lIt" American History Illustrated (July 1979)t pp.<br />

11-14.<br />

383


384


desirable. Order is a necessary element in any social<br />

system; it is not the only element.<br />

b. The "common good" <strong>and</strong> "modern utilitarian"<br />

arguments.<br />

Not jus tan at t rae t i ve soc i e t y but soc i e t y itself<br />

is probably impossible in the absence of the provision<br />

of such goods <strong>and</strong> services as pollut'ion control, road<br />

construction <strong>and</strong> maintenance, garbage collection,<br />

education, national defense <strong>and</strong> the like. Both the<br />

"common good" <strong>and</strong> "utilitarian" arguments boil down to<br />

the proposition that government is essential for the<br />

(effective) provision of these goods <strong>and</strong> services. The<br />

"common good" proponent justifies government action in<br />

these areas in terms of morality, argues that citizens<br />

have an obligation to follow these state policies, <strong>and</strong><br />

sees the provision of these goods <strong>and</strong> services as<br />

e i the r all 0 r par t 0 f the "comm 0 n good • " The" uti I i ­<br />

tar ian" on the other h<strong>and</strong> justifies such state action<br />

in terms of its necessity or practicality, argues that<br />

the restrictions on individual behavior are to the long<br />

run benefit of all citizens, <strong>and</strong> that it is therefore<br />

rat ional for the state to provide these services, which<br />

he terms "collective goods."<br />

There are, as we noted in Chapter VII, two methods<br />

to coordinate actions <strong>and</strong> policies in society: conscious<br />

coordination, which usually entails the state,<br />

<strong>and</strong> spontaneous coordination, which generally implies<br />

the market. The "common good" advocate tends either to<br />

be ignorant of, or to discount, the function of the<br />

market as a coordinating agent <strong>and</strong> therefore sees no<br />

alternative to the state. While relying heavily on the<br />

mar k e t for m0 s t t h i ngs, the " mo dern uti 1itarian" does<br />

not believe that it can function effectively in the<br />

area of "collective goods" <strong>and</strong> "externalitites" <strong>and</strong><br />

concludes that the state is necessary to supply these<br />

types of goods <strong>and</strong> to coordinate pol icy in this area.<br />

The anarchist has argued that there are no -- or few -goo<br />

d s t hat are i n her e n t lye 0 lIe c t i v e. Ra ther, the<br />

existence of collective goods today is a consequence of<br />

the failure, or even refusal, of the legal system to<br />

permit the extension of property rights into these<br />

areas. Given the proper (common law) legal system,<br />

such goods as air space <strong>and</strong> water could be broken down<br />

i n toma r gin a I unit s, the reby permit ting the rna r ke t to<br />

operate effectively in this realm as well. If correct,<br />

the market could be the functional equivalent of the<br />

state. This would mean that the state would not,<br />

386


1 e • S i mil a r I y, far from elimi na ting the pos sibiii t Y<br />

of an abuse of force, a monop.oly, which by definition<br />

is without external checks, is far more likely to engage<br />

in those very abuses feared by Locke than would a<br />

police or court agency. It is only the latter who face<br />

the ever-present possibility of dissatisfied customers<br />

taking their business elsewhere.<br />

While t he a n archis t pa r ad i gmappear s to be f eas i ­<br />

ble, its desirability is difficult to assess. Much<br />

depends on such things as one's personal values, one's<br />

view of human nature, <strong>and</strong> the like. For example, if<br />

one has a n 0 p tim i s tic view 0 f huma n na t ure<strong>and</strong>is not<br />

impressed by the Actonian aphorism that "power tends to<br />

corrupt," he will not fear concentrations of power.<br />

Rather, he would tend to look at the good things that<br />

ostensibly can be done with it, such as eliminating or<br />

red u c i n gpo v e r t y, red u c i ng rae i a I tens ions, etc. On<br />

the 0 the r han d, i f 0 net a k esape s s i mi s tic view 0 f<br />

man's nature he will focus on the evil that can be inflicted<br />

with such power. Consequently, the former<br />

would be prone to see anarchism as undesirable, even if<br />

feasible; the latter would be likely to react more<br />

favorably to the anarchist position: government is the<br />

principal threat <strong>and</strong> ought to be kept as small as possible.<br />

However, whether he would travel the entire<br />

route to anarchism is difficult to say. This would<br />

d e pendon 0 n e 's an swe r s to rna ny 0 the r que s t ions: does<br />

government have an inherent propensity to exp<strong>and</strong>?; can'<br />

internal checks be effective in keeping government accountable?;<br />

would the benefits of legislated law, e.g.,<br />

rapid change, outweigh its problems, e.g., legal uncertainty?<br />

Not only the answers one would give to these<br />

<strong>and</strong> other questions but the weights one would assign to<br />

the questions themselves would be relevant in determining<br />

how he viewed the desirability of anarchism.<br />

d. The "liberation" argument.<br />

Related to the "convenience" argument is the<br />

"liberation" argument of T. H. Green <strong>and</strong> the proponents<br />

ofthem 0 d ern wei farestate • Gr e e n rna i n t a i ned t hat a<br />

vigorous state can actually exp<strong>and</strong> individual freedom<br />

by eliminating certain obstacles to it which inhere in<br />

any laissez {aire society, anarchist or minarchist. If<br />

property rights <strong>and</strong> the market were SUbjected to vari<br />

0 us lim ita t ion s by the s tat e s uc h pe r enn i a I rna I ad i e s<br />

asp 0 v e r t y, dis e a s e, <strong>and</strong> i gnor an c e cou 1d be 0 vereom e .<br />

The "cycle of poverty" could be broken if the state<br />

could use some of its tax money to provide universal<br />

388


"free" education for children; much disease could be<br />

eliminated if the state would do such things as res<br />

t ric t the "fr e e d om 0 f con t raet" i nor de r t 0 1 imit the<br />

n umbe r 0 f h 0 u r s per wee k 1a bo r e r s cou I d wo r k, 0 res ­<br />

tab lis h s a f e t y <strong>and</strong> h e a 1 t h s t<strong>and</strong>ar dsin the wo r ks hop.<br />

Since the power of the state can be used for such noble<br />

ends, Green <strong>and</strong>h i s philosophical successors believe<br />

that the state ought to so act. There are two crucial<br />

assumptions in this position: [1] that in the absence<br />

of state act ion such problems as poverty <strong>and</strong> disease<br />

could not be ameliorated or eliminated, <strong>and</strong> [2] that<br />

the.y can be successfully dealt with through state<br />

action.<br />

The i n d i v i d ua 1 i s tanarc his t, a s we have seen,<br />

denies both assumptions. Not only does he believe that<br />

such problems can be solved in a laissez faire society,<br />

he also maintains that state action is likely to compound<br />

<strong>and</strong> perpetuate them.<br />

Briefly, the anarchist maintains that government<br />

economic intervention not only usually occurs for the<br />

benefIt of the "vested interests" but that.even when<br />

des i g ned t 0 h e 1 p the p 0 0 r itis s elf - d e f eat i ng . Re ­<br />

gar die s s 0 fin ten t ions, sueh programs as min i mum wa ge s<br />

eliminate jobs for the very group, viz., the poor, they<br />

we red e s i g ned t 0 h e 1 p, wh i leo the r programs suehas<br />

tariffs, subsidies, <strong>and</strong> the like, tend to protect the<br />

positions of the wealthy <strong>and</strong> politically powerful at<br />

the expense of the poor. Further, a laissez faire society,<br />

relieved of the debilitating effects of government<br />

regUlations, would be extremely productive. This,<br />

argues the anarchist, would have two significant consequences:<br />

[1] it would reduce involuntary poverty to<br />

those incapable of working, <strong>and</strong> [2] since, regardless<br />

of the economic system, such people can be cared for<br />

only with surplus production, the great productivity of<br />

a I a iss e z f aire s y stem wo u I d ge neratern0 rethan s uf f i ­<br />

cient means to provide for these 'people.<br />

It must be pointed out, however, that in the absence<br />

of government intervention there is no guarantee<br />

that any of this surplUS will be channeled into the<br />

care of the poor. But then it should also be pointed<br />

out that charitites currently collect billions of<br />

dollars each year, <strong>and</strong> there is no reason to believe<br />

that this figure would be lower in a taxless society.<br />

In fact, laissez fairists usually argue that with the<br />

cogni t ion that the h<strong>and</strong>icapped would receive no aid<br />

from the state, coupled with the increasing st<strong>and</strong>ard of<br />

389


living, doh'ations to charities, churches, etc., would<br />

actually increase. Whether this would be the case, <strong>and</strong><br />

whether it would be enough to afford adequate care for<br />

all of the disabled <strong>and</strong> h<strong>and</strong>icapped, are serious questions<br />

but ones that cannot be answered with a great<br />

degree of certainty.<br />

Whether one finds the "laissez faire" or the<br />

"liberation" argument the more convincing depends on<br />

one's answers to the previous two questions. This<br />

creates four possiblities:<br />

1. the market can't solve such problems but<br />

the state can;<br />

2. the market can so I ve such problems but<br />

the state can't;<br />

3. neither the market nor the state can<br />

solve such problems; <strong>and</strong><br />

4. both the rna r ket <strong>and</strong> the state can solve<br />

such problems.<br />

Clearly, if one subscribes to possibility [1] he<br />

will be likely, to find the "liberation" or "welfare"<br />

argument convincing. Just as clearly, one adhering to<br />

possibility [2] will be likely to find the "laissez<br />

faire" argument convincing. The two interesting possibilities<br />

are [3] <strong>and</strong> [4]. If neither or both the<br />

mar keta n d the s tat e can solvethe s e prob I em s thenone<br />

w0 u 1d h a vet 0 rna ke his dec i s ion 0 not her g r 0 un d s • For<br />

example, if one believes that greed ought not to be<br />

'encouraged <strong>and</strong> that this is what the market does, then<br />

he might still advocate state regulation of market<br />

activities. But'if one fears the concentration of<br />

political power then he would be likely to endorse tl1e<br />

laissez faire position.<br />

e. The "equality· argument.<br />

One final argument regarding the desirability of<br />

g 0 v ernmentis the " e can om i c justice " posit ion 0 f J 0 hn<br />

Rawls. Subscribing to a "patterned" theory of justice,<br />

Rawls argues that the social distribution of wealth is<br />

just only when the range of inequalities is held within<br />

strict limits. Since economic freedom would permit individuals<br />

to rise above <strong>and</strong> fall below the permissible<br />

I imi ts, the pattern of economic distribution would be<br />

immediately <strong>and</strong> continuously upset without intervention<br />

by the state.<br />

Moreover, if justice dem<strong>and</strong>s economic equality,<br />

390


G i v e n 0 u r b r i e f 0 v e r vie W 0 f s even pO pu I a r a r gumen<br />

t s for government <strong>and</strong> the anarchist repl ies, we are<br />

left with the following conclusions: [1] individualist<br />

anarch i sm is a feasible method of social organization<br />

<strong>and</strong> therefore ;government is not indispensible; [2] depending<br />

on one's personal values, individualist anarchism<br />

mayor may not bea desirable method of social<br />

organization; <strong>and</strong> [3] given the radical natural-rights<br />

position of most individualist anarchists, government<br />

can never be a morally justifiable institution.<br />

History shows that freedom is a fragile <strong>and</strong> fleeting<br />

possession. It also shows that governments exp<strong>and</strong>.<br />

It is not likely that the two are unrelated.'<br />

It was only in the twentieth century that the<br />

state emerged fully supreme, possessing the complete<br />

panoply of modern technology <strong>and</strong> unfettered by economic,<br />

religious or social restrictions. The results are<br />

c 1ear for all t 0 see: two w0 rid wa r s<strong>and</strong> t hat m0 r a I<br />

monstros i ty, the total i tarian state. But the United<br />

<strong>State</strong>s suffered neither the awesome destruction of<br />

world war nor the spiritual destitution of totalitarianism.<br />

The United <strong>State</strong>s, Americans were fond of<br />

tel lin g thems e 1 ves, wa sun i que • This wa s the "1 <strong>and</strong> 0 f<br />

the free," <strong>and</strong> government was "of, by <strong>and</strong> for the<br />

people," There was no need to worry.<br />

Yet, by any index -- taxes, expenditures, the size<br />

of the bureaucracy, the scope of activities, the number<br />

of departments -- government in the United <strong>State</strong>s has<br />

also exp<strong>and</strong>ed, <strong>and</strong> that expansion has been dramatic <strong>and</strong><br />

has ga i ned momentum wi th the passage of time. Perhaps<br />

what ween joyed wa s not a dis pensat ion but a me res t a y<br />

of execut ion. People are beginning to feel the pinch.<br />

Wherever one goes today people speak of bloated governmen<br />

t • Therearet 0 0 man y t a xes, too rna ny laws, too<br />

much regulat ion, too much waste, <strong>and</strong> just plain too<br />

much government. Not only does government restrict<br />

individual liberty but, with inflation, recession,<br />

gover nmen t cor r upt i on <strong>and</strong> the ever-present threat of<br />

nuclear annihilation, we are beginning to realize that<br />

neither can it provide security <strong>and</strong> prosperity. Along<br />

with this realization comes a search for alternatives.<br />

The individual anarchist has advanced a number of<br />

radical <strong>and</strong> quite exciting proposals which, he<br />

bel i eve s, w0 u I d po i n t the wa y to a f r e e <strong>and</strong> pr 0 s per 0 us<br />

society. It is an alternative that deserves serious<br />

consideration.<br />

392


A<br />

Adier. Max. 2<br />

Allende. Salvadore. 135<br />

Anderson. Benjamin, 118<br />

Andrews, Stephen Pearl,<br />

181, 182, 184, 188.<br />

194, 195,208<br />

Appleton, Henry. 207<br />

Aquinas, St. Thomas, 156<br />

Aristotle, 78, 80, 155,<br />

170<br />

Augustine. St •• 170<br />

Austin. John. 336<br />

B<br />

Babcock. John. 15<br />

Bakunin. Michael, 2, 4.<br />

6, 8, 37, 177<br />

Ballou. Adin. 179. 180<br />

Banfield, Edward. 242<br />

Baran, Paul. 117<br />

Barclay, Robert, 179<br />

Barnett, R<strong>and</strong>y. 359, 362.<br />

363<br />

Bastiat, Frederic, 24-26,<br />

36. 202<br />

Baumol, William, 294<br />

Beaird, Paul, 27-29<br />

Beard, Charles, 118<br />

Bechtler, Christopher, 299<br />

Bell.my, Edward, 37<br />

Bentham, Jeremy, 160-162,<br />

165, 166<br />

Berkley, George, 353<br />

Berkman, Alex<strong>and</strong>er, 51,<br />

52,210.222<br />

Bixler, Scott, 285<br />

Block, Walter, 249, 277,<br />

280, 281, 283<br />

Bodin, Jean, 88. 336<br />

Bourne. R<strong>and</strong>olph, 82, 83,<br />

86, 87<br />

Brailsford, H.N., 12<br />

Brecht, Arnold, 62<br />

Bresler, Robert, 129, 130<br />

INDEX<br />

393<br />

Buchanan, James, 262<br />

Buckley, William F., 32,<br />

34, 36<br />

Bukharin, N., 117<br />

Burke, Edmund, 32, 34,<br />

36, 170<br />

Burnham, James, 32, 33,<br />

36<br />

Burt, William, 304-306<br />

Byrd, Martha, 375<br />

C<br />

Calhoun, John, 88<br />

Cantor, Norman, 326<br />

Carneiro, Robert, 76, 77<br />

Carter. Owendolen, 327<br />

Cervero, Robert, 279<br />

Childs, Roy, 24<br />

Clark. J .M •• 253<br />

Collins, R<strong>and</strong>all, 79<br />

Commons. John R., 240<br />

Coquelin, Charles, 202<br />

Crosby, Peter, 324<br />

Cuzan, Alfred, 53<br />

D<br />

Dahl, Robert, 232, 233,<br />

235<br />

DeJouvenel, Bertr<strong>and</strong>.<br />

83-85, 87. 325<br />

DeMa i s t r e. J 0 s e ph. 34. 36<br />

Dewey, John, 240<br />

Dionysius, 80<br />

Dodd, Malurice, 117<br />

Downs, Anthony. 101-105<br />

Dunoyer, Charles, 202<br />

Durkheim, Emile, 341<br />

Dye, Thomas, 100<br />

E<br />

Edwards, James Rolph, 299<br />

Ellul, Jacques, 90<br />

Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 179


F<br />

Fisher, J. Greevz, 194<br />

Flynn, John, 120, 121,<br />

123, 124, 128<br />

Fox, Douglas, 353<br />

Frech, H.E., 235<br />

Fried, Morton, 78, 79<br />

Friedman, David, 36, 56,<br />

57, 62, 92, 275, 336,<br />

349, 350, 354, 369,<br />

370<br />

Friedman, Milton, 165,<br />

238, 246, 290, 293<br />

FUller, Lon, 336<br />

G<br />

Garrison, William Lloyd,<br />

179<br />

Gellhorn, Walter, 290<br />

Gentile, Giovanni, 37<br />

George, Henry, 184<br />

Godw in, Wi II i am, 2, 4, 12,<br />

13, 35, 36, 371<br />

Goldin, Kenneth, 310, 311<br />

Goldman, Emma, 36, 211<br />

Green, Thomas Hill, 166-<br />

168, 171, 240, 388, 389<br />

Greene, William, 189, 190,<br />

192-195, 208<br />

Grinder, Walter, 93, 125<br />

'Guerin, Daniel, 2<br />

Guillaume, James, 7<br />

Gumplowicz, <strong>Ludwig</strong>, 73<br />

H<br />

Hagel, John, 125-127<br />

Hallowell, John, 161<br />

Harrod, Roy F., 253<br />

Hayek, Friedrich, 31, 36,<br />

53, 225, 228, 240, 256,<br />

325,326,328-330,333,<br />

336<br />

Hegel, Ge 0 r ge, 166, 170<br />

Herbert, Auberon, 203, 258<br />

Herz, John, 327<br />

Hess ,Kar 1, 340<br />

Heywood, Ezra, 189, 190,<br />

192, 194<br />

394<br />

Hilferding, R., 117<br />

Hitler, Adolf, 121, 139,<br />

141<br />

Hobbes, Thomas, 14, 88,<br />

89, 157-160, 170, 336,<br />

380, 385<br />

Hobson, J .A., 118<br />

Hoover, Herbert, 257<br />

Hospers» John, 19-22, 36,<br />

258, 259, 273, 287,<br />

293, 311, 323, 351,<br />

353<br />

Humboldt, Wilhelm <strong>von</strong>,<br />

29, 36<br />

Hurne, David, 79<br />

Hutchinson, Anne, 179<br />

I<br />

Ingalls, Joshua, 195-197<br />

J<br />

Jacker, Corinne, 179<br />

Jenks, Edward, 327<br />

Johnson, Lyndon, 130<br />

J 0 I ow i c z, H. F., 327<br />

K<br />

Kaplan, Morton, 232, 235<br />

Kauder, Emil, 177<br />

Kelly, John, 207<br />

Kennedy, John F., 129<br />

Kerensky, Alex<strong>and</strong>er, 53<br />

Keynes, John M., 253<br />

Kimmel, Admiral Husb<strong>and</strong>,<br />

129, 139<br />

Kirk, Russell, 32, 34, 36<br />

Kirzner, Israel, 224<br />

Kissinger, Henry, 373<br />

Krader,Lawrence, 77<br />

Kropotkin, Peter, 2, 4-6,<br />

8, 37, 51, 54, 177,<br />

222, 227, 228<br />

L<br />

La Boetie, Etienne de,<br />

371


Laski, Harold, 240<br />

Lasswell, Harold, 2!2, 235<br />

Lazarus, M.E., 207<br />

Lenin, Vladimir, 117<br />

Leoni, Bruno, 237, 325-327<br />

Locke, John, 55, 56, 62,<br />

151,152,159,160,<br />

165, 166, 168, 170,<br />

190, 196, 203, 304,<br />

387, 388<br />

Low i e JR. H0, 78<br />

Lundberg, George, 130<br />

Luxemburg, Rosa, 117<br />

M<br />

Ma c ca 11, Will i am, 180<br />

MacCallum, Spencer Heath,<br />

312<br />

Machan, Tibor, 287<br />

MacIver, R. M., 78<br />

Mack, Andrew, 370<br />

Mackay, John Henry, 15,<br />

132, 133, 177<br />

Maddox, Robert, 132, 133<br />

Madison, Charles, 15, 211<br />

Madison, James, 83<br />

Magdoff, Harry, 117<br />

Maine, Sir Henry, 330<br />

Malatesta, Errico, 2<br />

Ma r ita in, J a cq ue s, 155­<br />

157, 170<br />

Martin, James, 14, 189,<br />

194-196<br />

Ma r x, Ka r 1, 3, 15, 35, 37,<br />

95, 96, 117<br />

McCloskey, J.J., 31<br />

Mi II, John Stuar t, 30-32,<br />

36, 166<br />

Miller, Martin, 5<br />

<strong>Mises</strong>. <strong>Ludwig</strong> <strong>von</strong>, 3. 29,<br />

30, 32, 36, 79, 83,<br />

117, 118, 120, 248, 296<br />

Mishan, E.J., 308<br />

Molinari, Gustave de, 177,<br />

201-203<br />

Montesquieu, Baron De, 85<br />

Moon, Parker T., 118<br />

Moore, Thomas Gale, 292<br />

Morris, William, 2<br />

Mosca, Gaetano, 98<br />

395<br />

Moss, Lawrence, 352<br />

Mossedegh, 134<br />

Most, Johann, 210<br />

Murray, Charles, 243, 246<br />

N<br />

Nisbet, Robert " 80, 89-92<br />

Nixon, Richard, 135<br />

Nock, Albert Jay, 83, 94<br />

Noyes, John Humphrey, 179<br />

Nozick, Robert, 20,<br />

22-24,<br />

36, 169, 258, 273,<br />

351, 353, 357, 358,<br />

391<br />

o Olson, Mancur, 252, 360<br />

Oppenheimer, Franz,<br />

73-79, 82, 83, 88,<br />

177<br />

Ostrom, Vincent, 352<br />

Owen, Robert, 180, 198<br />

p<br />

Parker, S.E., 177<br />

Paul, Jeffrey, 342<br />

Perkins, Ernestine <strong>and</strong><br />

Richard, 64, 306, 307<br />

Philip of Macedon, 80<br />

Plato, 13, 151-158, 170<br />

Plucknett, Theodore, 327,<br />

330, 331<br />

Prewitt, Kenneth, 99,<br />

100, 107<br />

Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph,<br />

2-4, 8, 10-13, 16, 36,<br />

177. 193. 313. 341<br />

R<br />

R<strong>and</strong>, Ayn, 26-29, 55,<br />

258, 260, 273<br />

Ratzenhofer, Gustav, 73<br />

RawIs, J ahn, 37, 168 ,<br />

169, 171, 390, 39 1<br />

Reichert, William 0., xi<br />

Reid, Margaret, 244


Renshaw, Edward, 295<br />

Ricardo, David, 195<br />

Robbins, Lionel, 162<br />

Robinson, J.B., 207<br />

Rocker, Rudolph, 8, 36<br />

Rockwell, George, 37<br />

Rollins, Louis, 349<br />

Roosevelt, Franklin D.,<br />

123, 127-129, 139, 140,<br />

257<br />

Rothbard, Murray, 17, 19,<br />

21, 27, 36, 54-64, 79,<br />

81, 84, 88, 107, 228,<br />

230-238, 240, 259, 275,<br />

281, 283, 291, 298,<br />

308, 312, 333, 335,<br />

336, 341, 343, 344,<br />

347, 353, 364, 368, 370<br />

Rousseau, Jean Jacques,<br />

89, 90, 151, 153-157,<br />

170<br />

S<br />

Sabine, George, 30, 166<br />

Saint-Simon, Henry, 37<br />

Samuels, Warren J., 230-<br />

232, 235<br />

Samuelson, Paul, 309<br />

S<strong>and</strong>ers, John, 360, 361<br />

Sargent, L.T., 34<br />

Say, J.B., 118,119, 201<br />

Schumpeter, Joseph, 117,<br />

121, 253<br />

Schuster, Eunice, 178,<br />

180, 211<br />

Scott, James B., 330<br />

Shallou, Jeremiah, 357<br />

Sharp, Gene, 371, 372<br />

Short, General Walter,<br />

129, 139<br />

Sibley, Mulford, 162<br />

Slater, Jerome, 132, 134<br />

Smith, Adam, 4,36,121,<br />

122, 177, 201<br />

Smith, Robert, 123, 127<br />

Sneed, John, 338<br />

Sorel, Georges, 8, 36<br />

Sowell, Thomas, 243<br />

Spencer, Herbert, 24-26,<br />

36.• 159, 160, 166,<br />

396<br />

170, 203, 205, 210,<br />

258, 391<br />

Spooner, Lys<strong>and</strong>er, 36,<br />

189-194, 196-198,<br />

203-207<br />

Spragens, Thomas, 59<br />

Stal in, Joseph, 133<br />

Stanwood, Edward, 194<br />

Stimson, -Frederic, 129<br />

Stimson, Henry, 326<br />

Stinchcombe, Arthur, 285<br />

Stirner, Max, 2, 14-16,<br />

36, 177, 207<br />

Stone, Alan, 99, 100, 107<br />

Stromberg, Joseph,<br />

121-123<br />

Sweezy, Paul, 117<br />

T<br />

Tannehill, Morris <strong>and</strong><br />

Linda, 64, 65, 324,<br />

344, 346, 355, 358,<br />

365<br />

Taylor, Richard, 323<br />

Thoreau, Henry David, 179<br />

Tol<strong>and</strong>, John, 139<br />

Tolstoy, Leo, 371<br />

Tuccille, Jerome, 340,<br />

341<br />

Tucker, Benjamin, 3, 4,<br />

15-17, 36, 56, 192,<br />

194, 197-203, 206-211,<br />

224, 275, 371<br />

Tullock, Gordon, 163,<br />

164, 170<br />

W<br />

Walker, J.L., 207<br />

Warren, Josiah, 3, 4,36,<br />

180-189, 192-198, 208<br />

Watner, Carl, 202<br />

Wheeler, Richard, 324,<br />

348, 349<br />

Wild, John, 58<br />

Wilkie, Wendel, 104<br />

Williams. William A.,<br />

132-134<br />

Wittman, Donald, 102-105<br />

Wolin, Sheldon, 152, 154<br />

Wollstein. Jarret, 274-


276, 279, 286, 369<br />

Wooldridge, William, 343,<br />

347, 357<br />

Wormser, Rene, 328-331<br />

Wright, Henry, 179<br />

y<br />

Yarros, Victor, 4, 15,<br />

199, 211<br />

Z<br />

Zeigler, Harmon, 100<br />

397

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!